Week 2. This week, we covered operations on sets and cardinality.

Similar documents
APPENDIX A Some Linear Algebra

Lectures - Week 4 Matrix norms, Conditioning, Vector Spaces, Linear Independence, Spanning sets and Basis, Null space and Range of a Matrix

Introductory Cardinality Theory Alan Kaylor Cline

12 MATH 101A: ALGEBRA I, PART C: MULTILINEAR ALGEBRA. 4. Tensor product

The Order Relation and Trace Inequalities for. Hermitian Operators

Linear, affine, and convex sets and hulls In the sequel, unless otherwise specified, X will denote a real vector space.

On the set of natural numbers

20. Mon, Oct. 13 What we have done so far corresponds roughly to Chapters 2 & 3 of Lee. Now we turn to Chapter 4. The first idea is connectedness.

2 More examples with details

= z 20 z n. (k 20) + 4 z k = 4

An Introduction to Morita Theory

A CLASS OF RECURSIVE SETS. Florentin Smarandache University of New Mexico 200 College Road Gallup, NM 87301, USA

a b a In case b 0, a being divisible by b is the same as to say that

REAL ANALYSIS I HOMEWORK 1

LECTURE V. 1. More on the Chinese Remainder Theorem We begin by recalling this theorem, proven in the preceeding lecture.

FACTORIZATION IN KRULL MONOIDS WITH INFINITE CLASS GROUP

THE CHINESE REMAINDER THEOREM. We should thank the Chinese for their wonderful remainder theorem. Glenn Stevens

MATH 241B FUNCTIONAL ANALYSIS - NOTES EXAMPLES OF C ALGEBRAS

Graph Reconstruction by Permutations

where a is any ideal of R. Lemma 5.4. Let R be a ring. Then X = Spec R is a topological space Moreover the open sets

Problem Set 9 Solutions

Anti-van der Waerden numbers of 3-term arithmetic progressions.

find (x): given element x, return the canonical element of the set containing x;

Subset Topological Spaces and Kakutani s Theorem

Complete subgraphs in multipartite graphs

On the Operation A in Analysis Situs. by Kazimierz Kuratowski

ALGEBRA SCHEMES AND THEIR REPRESENTATIONS

ALGEBRA HW 7 CLAY SHONKWILER

Affine transformations and convexity

For now, let us focus on a specific model of neurons. These are simplified from reality but can achieve remarkable results.

Inner Product. Euclidean Space. Orthonormal Basis. Orthogonal

8.4 COMPLEX VECTOR SPACES AND INNER PRODUCTS

Games of Threats. Elon Kohlberg Abraham Neyman. Working Paper

ALGEBRA SCHEMES AND THEIR REPRESENTATIONS

2.3 Nilpotent endomorphisms

Fixed point. The function q revisited. Function q. graph F factorial graph factorial. factorial is a fixed point of F, since

Spectral Graph Theory and its Applications September 16, Lecture 5

MARTIN S AXIOM AND SEPARATED MAD FAMILIES

First day August 1, Problems and Solutions

Math 594. Solutions 1

On the smoothness and the totally strong properties for nearness frames

= s j Ui U j. i, j, then s F(U) with s Ui F(U) G(U) F(V ) G(V )

arxiv: v1 [math.co] 1 Mar 2014

Lecture 7: Gluing prevarieties; products

FINITELY-GENERATED MODULES OVER A PRINCIPAL IDEAL DOMAIN

Exercise Solutions to Real Analysis

DIFFERENTIAL FORMS BRIAN OSSERMAN

( 1) i [ d i ]. The claim is that this defines a chain complex. The signs have been inserted into the definition to make this work out.

Canonical transformations

SUPER PRINCIPAL FIBER BUNDLE WITH SUPER ACTION

Bernoulli Numbers and Polynomials

Lecture 3. Ax x i a i. i i

THE SUMMATION NOTATION Ʃ

Lecture 3: Probability Distributions

k(k 1)(k 2)(p 2) 6(p d.

the ordinal-least-upper-bound of any set of cardinals is a cardinal; for any set I, and cardinals λ is a cardinal.

CONJUGACY IN THOMPSON S GROUP F. 1. Introduction

Homework Notes Week 7

Math 101 Fall 2013 Homework #7 Due Friday, November 15, 2013

8.6 The Complex Number System

NP-Completeness : Proofs

A Quantum Gauss-Bonnet Theorem

R n α. . The funny symbol indicates DISJOINT union. Define an equivalence relation on this disjoint union by declaring v α R n α, and v β R n β

42. Mon, Dec. 8 Last time, we were discussing CW complexes, and we considered two di erent CW structures on S n. We continue with more examples.

Expected Value and Variance

On wgrα-continuous Functions in Topological Spaces

Polynomials. 1 More properties of polynomials

Bayesian epistemology II: Arguments for Probabilism

Math 2534 Final Exam Review Answer Key 1. Know deþnitions for the various terms: a. Modus Ponens b. Modus Tollens c. divides d. rational e.

Problem Do any of the following determine homomorphisms from GL n (C) to GL n (C)?

FORCING COPIES OF ω 1 WITH PFA(S)

princeton univ. F 17 cos 521: Advanced Algorithm Design Lecture 7: LP Duality Lecturer: Matt Weinberg

Errors for Linear Systems

Google PageRank with Stochastic Matrix

COMPLEX NUMBERS AND QUADRATIC EQUATIONS

Errata to Invariant Theory with Applications January 28, 2017

REVERSE MATHEMATICS AND PROPERTIES OF FINITE CHARACTER

UNIQUE FACTORIZATION OF COMPOSITIVE HEREDITARY GRAPH PROPERTIES

where a is any ideal of R. Lemma Let R be a ring. Then X = Spec R is a topological space. Moreover the open sets

Self-complementing permutations of k-uniform hypergraphs

Homotopy Type Theory Lecture Notes

On intransitive graph-restrictive permutation groups

DIFFERENTIAL SCHEMES

Chapter Twelve. Integration. We now turn our attention to the idea of an integral in dimensions higher than one. Consider a real-valued function f : D

A Labelling of the Faces in the Shi Arrangement

9 Characteristic classes

Ali Omer Alattass Department of Mathematics, Faculty of Science, Hadramout University of science and Technology, P. O. Box 50663, Mukalla, Yemen

Introduction to Vapor/Liquid Equilibrium, part 2. Raoult s Law:

THE CLASS NUMBER THEOREM

BOUNDEDNESS OF THE RIESZ TRANSFORM WITH MATRIX A 2 WEIGHTS

THERE ARE NO POINTS OF ORDER 11 ON ELLIPTIC CURVES OVER Q.

SUCCESSIVE MINIMA AND LATTICE POINTS (AFTER HENK, GILLET AND SOULÉ) M(B) := # ( B Z N)

Math 261 Exercise sheet 2

Foundations of Arithmetic

Stanford University CS359G: Graph Partitioning and Expanders Handout 4 Luca Trevisan January 13, 2011

SL n (F ) Equals its Own Derived Group

Introduction to Algorithms

Descent is a technique which allows construction of a global object from local data.

MTH 819 Algebra I S13. Homework 1/ Solutions. 1 if p n b and p n+1 b 0 otherwise ) = 0 if p q or n m. W i = rw i

The Multiple Classical Linear Regression Model (CLRM): Specification and Assumptions. 1. Introduction

Transcription:

Week 2 Ths week, we covered operatons on sets and cardnalty. Defnton 0.1 (Correspondence). A correspondence between two sets A and B s a set S contaned n A B = {(a, b) a A, b B}. A correspondence from A to A s called a relaton. Defnton 0.2 (Equvalence Relaton). An equvalence relaton s a relaton R on A satsfyng the followng: Reflexvty For all a A, (a, a) R Symmetry If (a, b) R then (b, a) R. Transtvty If (a, b) R and (b, c) R then (a, c) R. We often denote (a, b) R by arb. Defnton 0.3 (Functon). A functon f : A B s a correspondence from A to B such that for each a A, there exsts a unque b B such that (a, b) f. We denote (a, b) f by f(a) = b. Defnton 0.4 (Injectve, Surjectve, Bjectve). A functon s sad to be njectve f f(a) = f(a ) mples that a = a. A functon s sad to be surjectve f for all b B, there exsts a A such that f(a) = b. A functon s sad to be bjectve f t s njectve and surjectve. Defnton 0.5 (Equvalence). We say that two sets A and B are equvalent, wrtten A B f and only f there exsts a functon f : A B whch s a bjecton. Now, on fnte sets, ths amounts to them havng the same sze (see frst homework) Defnton 0.6 (Composton of functons). If f : A B and g : B C are functons, we defne g f by g f(a) = g(f(a)). Lemma 0.1. Let f : A B be a bjecton. Then there exsts a functon g : B A such that g f(a) = a and f g(b) = b for all a A and b B. We call g the nverse of f and denote t by f 1. 1

Proof. Defne a correspondence g from B to A by (a, b) f f and only f (b, a) g. We wll show that g s a functon. As f s surjectve, for every b B, there exsts a A wth f(a) = b. Thus, for any b B, there exsts some a A wth (b, a) g. To see that t s unque, we note that f s njectve, and so we have f(a) = f(a ) mples a = a. Specfcally, that means that f (b, a) g and (b, a ) g then a = a. Thus, for any b B, there exsts a unque a A such that (b, a) g. So g s a functon. To see that the compostons work out, fx a A. then g(f(a)) = a because (a, f(a)) f and (f(a), a) g. The same argument works for the other composton. Proposton 0.2. s an equvalence relaton. Proof. For any set A, we have 1 A : A A the functon whch has 1 A (a) = a for all a A. Ths s a bjecton A A, and so s reflexve. If f : A B s a bjecton, then f 1 : B A s also a bjecton, and so s symmetrc. If f : A B and g : B C are bjectons, then g f : A C s a bjecton, and so s transtve. So now we have an equvalence relaton on sets. Gven a set A, we ll call A the collecton of all sets equvalent to A. We call A the cardnal number of A. For fnte sets, we use numbers. So {a, b} = 2. Ths s justfed by the fact that the arthmetc we wll descrbe shortly s exactly the usual arthmetc for natural numbers when restrcted to fnte sets, as you are to prove n your homework. Now for a couple of examples Example 0.1. We wll show that N Z. Any functon f : N A for any set A can be thought of as a sequence, or a lstng. So, to descrbe f, we must merely lst the elements of A. For A = Z, we can take f to be the lst 0, 1, 1, 2, 2, 3, 3,..., n, n,.... Ths functon s surjectve and njectve, and so s a bjecton, and demonstrates that N Z. Example 0.2. We wll also show that N R. We ll actually do t by showng that N [0, 1] R. Every element of [0, 1] can be wrtten as a =1 10. Now, assume, for contradcton, that there s a bjecton N [0, 1]. Then the number j s sent to x j = a j =1 10. We now construct a number x [0, 1] not on the lst. Let x = a +1 =1 10 wth the conventon that 9 + 1 = 0 rather than 10. Now, x can t be on the lst, because t dffers wth every element of the lst n some poston. Thus, we ddn t have a bjecton n the frst place, and N R. As a conventon, we say that f there s an njecton f : A B that A B. If there s an njecton but no bjecton, then we say A < B. So the above example n fact says that N < [0, 1] R, and so N < R. Defnton 0.7 (Power Set). Gven a set A, defne P(A) to be the set of all subsets of A. Call ths the power set of A. 2

Theorem 0.3. For any set A, A < P(A). Proof. That A P(A) follows from the exstence of the njecton A P(A) gven by a A maps to {a} A. To see that there s no bjecton, we assume one exsts for contradcton. Let f : A P(A) be a bjecton. Then, n partcular, t s surjectve. So any subset of A that we can descrbe s n the mage. Look at B = {a A a / f(a)} A. Now, there must be an element of A sent to B, and we ll denote t by a 0. Here s where we encounter the problem: can a 0 be n B? If a 0 B, then a 0 f(a 0 ) and so a 0 / B, whch s a contradcton. Smlarly, f a 0 / B, then a 0 / f(a 0 ), and so by the defnton of B, we have a 0 B, whch s also a contradcton. So, f we assume that there s a bjecton, there s a contradcton, so such a functon cannot exst, and A P(A). Though we won t be usng t later, we state the followng theorem wthout proof because t s mportant to know n general: Theorem 0.4 (Cantor-Schroeder-Bernsten). Let A and B be sets. If A B and B A then A = B. All ths says s that nstead of lookng for bjectons, we can just look for njectons both ways. The proof actually uses them to construct a bjecton, but we won t go nto detal there, because t s rather complcated and not relevant at the moment. Defnton 0.8 (Operatons on Sets and Cardnal Numbers). Gven two sets A, B, we defne the followng: A B = {(a, b) a A, b B} the Cartesan product, A B = (A {0}) (B {1}) and B A =the set of all functons f : A B. We defne A B = A B, A + B = A B and B A = B A. Note that the power set of A can be dentfed wth {0, 1} A, and has cardnalty 2 A. Defnton 0.9 (Partal Orderng). A partal order on a set A s a relaton on A that s reflexve, transtve and antsymmetrc (e, f a b and b a then a = b). We call a set wth a partal orderng a poset. (Partall Ordered SET) Defnton 0.10 (Total Order). A partal orderng s a total orderng f for any a, b A we have a b or b a. A subset of a poset f called a chan f the orderng restrcts to a total order on t. Example 0.3. The usual order on the natural numbers s a lnear orderng. However, the poset of subsets of a gven set ordered by ncluson s not, as for {1, 2, 3}, nether {1, 2} or {2, 3} contans the other. 3

Defnton 0.11 (Well Orderng). A total orderng on S s a well orderng f every subset of S has a least element. Theorem 0.5. The followng are equvalent: Axom of Choce Gven any collecton fo nonempty sets A b ndexed by b B, there exsts a functon f : B A b such that f(b) A b for all b B. Gven any collecton of nonempty sets, ther product s nonempty. Well-Orderng Prncple Gven a set S, there exsts a partal orderng on S whch s a well orderng. Zorn s Lemma Gven a poset S, f every chan has an upper bound (that s, an element x wth a x for all a n the chan) then there exsts a maxmal element of S. (We say a s maxmal f a x mples that a = x.) Most mathematcans just take the equvalent statements above to hold, though there s some dsagreement. For our purposes, we wll assume them. Theorem 0.6. If A, B are sets, A B, then A + B = B. Proof. It s smple to check that B A + B B + B, and so t s enough to check that B = B + B for nfnte sets. We wll proceed usng Zorn s Lemma to construct a bjecton between B and B B = B {0, 1}. Look at pars (X, f) wth X B and f : X {0, 1} X a bjecton. Frst, we must check that such thngs exst. Now, every nfnte set has a subset that s equvalent to N (Exercse), so we take C B to be such a subset. Then, as N {0, 1} s equvalent to N, (To see t, sent N {0} to the even natural numbers and N {1} to the odd natural numbers) we have C {0, 1} C a bjecton. So there exst pars lke ths. Now, we order them to get a poset as follows: (X, f) (Y, g) f and only f X Y and g X = f. That s, for all x X, g(x) = f(x). That ths s a partall orderng s left as an exercse. Now take any chan wth elements (X α, f α ). Then t has an upper bound gven by X = X α and f = f α. Here s one of the rare tmes we recall that a functon s a set. Now, f wll be a functon, because once an element of X s assgned a value, t must have the same value forever after. Now, Zorn s Lemma mples the exstence of (C, g), a maxmal element. Because g s a bjecton C {0, 1} C, we note that C = C + C. We wll now show that C = B. If B \ C s nfnte, then t would contan X B \ C equvalent to N. Then we can take h : X {0, 1} X a bjecton, and have X C wth f h a bjecton from (X C) {0, 1} X C. Ths, however, contradcts C beng maxmal, and so can t happen. Thus, B \ C s fnte. So then B = C (B \ C), and so B = C + B \ C = C + n for some fnte n. As an exercse, show that for any nfnte set, addng a fnte number doesn t change the cardnalty. Wth that, we are done, C + n = C = B, and C + C = C, so B + B = B and A + B = B. 4

Theorem 0.7. If A, B are sets, A, B nfnte and A B, then A B = B. Proof. Here B A B B B, so all we must show s that B B = B. We wll agan use Zorn s lemma. Look at pars (X, f) wth f : X X X a bjecton. We note that ths s nonempty, because there s a subset D B wth D N, and N N N gven by (m, n) 2 m (2n + 1) s a bjecton. Applyng Zorn s lemma n the same way as above gves a maxmal element (C, g) wth C C = C. Now, for contradcton, we suppose that B\C > C. Then there s a subset D B\C such that D C. Now, D C C C C D D C D D, and all of these sets are dsjont. Ths tells us that (C D) (C D) = C C + D D + C D + D C = C + C + D + D = C + D = C D, and so there s a bjecton (C D) (C D) (C D), whch contradcts the maxmalty of C. Thus, B \ C C, and so B = C + B \ C = C, by the prevous. 5