Cardinality and ordinal numbers

Similar documents
ADVANCED CALCULUS - MTH433 LECTURE 4 - FINITE AND INFINITE SETS

MATH 3300 Test 1. Name: Student Id:

Notes on ordinals and cardinals

MATH 220 (all sections) Homework #12 not to be turned in posted Friday, November 24, 2017

S15 MA 274: Exam 3 Study Questions

Discussion Summary 10/16/2018

Let us first solve the midterm problem 4 before we bring up the related issues.

MATH 102 INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICAL ANALYSIS. 1. Some Fundamentals

20 Ordinals. Definition A set α is an ordinal iff: (i) α is transitive; and. (ii) α is linearly ordered by. Example 20.2.


Lecture Notes 1 Basic Concepts of Mathematics MATH 352

5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting

Math 455 Some notes on Cardinality and Transfinite Induction

1.4 Cardinality. Tom Lewis. Fall Term Tom Lewis () 1.4 Cardinality Fall Term / 9

Exercises for Unit VI (Infinite constructions in set theory)

SETS AND FUNCTIONS JOSHUA BALLEW

Chapter 1. Sets and Mappings

Chapter 1 : The language of mathematics.

Math 4603: Advanced Calculus I, Summer 2016 University of Minnesota Notes on Cardinality of Sets

Functions. Definition 1 Let A and B be sets. A relation between A and B is any subset of A B.

Economics 204 Summer/Fall 2011 Lecture 2 Tuesday July 26, 2011 N Now, on the main diagonal, change all the 0s to 1s and vice versa:

A Logician s Toolbox

Notes for Math 290 using Introduction to Mathematical Proofs by Charles E. Roberts, Jr.

Mathematics 220 Workshop Cardinality. Some harder problems on cardinality.

Initial Ordinals. Proposition 57 For every ordinal α there is an initial ordinal κ such that κ α and α κ.

Functions and cardinality (solutions) sections A and F TA: Clive Newstead 6 th May 2014

ABOUT THE CLASS AND NOTES ON SET THEORY

Econ Lecture 2. Outline

Infinite constructions in set theory

3 FUNCTIONS. 3.1 Definition and Basic Properties. c Dr Oksana Shatalov, Spring

Finite and Infinite Sets

3 FUNCTIONS. 3.1 Definition and Basic Properties. c Dr Oksana Shatalov, Fall

Cartesian Products and Relations

Axioms of separation

A Short Review of Cardinality

Discrete Mathematics 2007: Lecture 5 Infinite sets

6 CARDINALITY OF SETS

Some Basic Notations Of Set Theory

RED. Name: Math 290 Fall 2016 Sample Exam 3

Well Ordered Sets (continued)

RED. Name: Instructor: Pace Nielsen Math 290 Section 1: Winter 2014 Final Exam

Section 7.5: Cardinality

Diskrete Mathematik Solution 6

Axioms for Set Theory

Outside ZF - Set Cardinality, the Axiom of Choice, and the Continuum Hypothesis

Great Theoretical Ideas in Computer Science. Lecture 5: Cantor s Legacy

Mathematics Course 111: Algebra I Part I: Algebraic Structures, Sets and Permutations

INVERSE LIMITS AND PROFINITE GROUPS

Final Exam Review. 2. Let A = {, { }}. What is the cardinality of A? Is

Set theory. Math 304 Spring 2007

Introduction to Proofs in Analysis. updated December 5, By Edoh Y. Amiran Following the outline of notes by Donald Chalice INTRODUCTION

Short notes on Axioms of set theory, Well orderings and Ordinal Numbers

Selected problems from past exams

Basics of Model Theory

NOTES ON WELL ORDERING AND ORDINAL NUMBERS. 1. Logic and Notation Any formula in Mathematics can be stated using the symbols

DO FIVE OUT OF SIX ON EACH SET PROBLEM SET

Topics in Logic, Set Theory and Computability

Economics 204 Summer/Fall 2017 Lecture 1 Monday July 17, 2017

Introduction to Topology

Principles of Real Analysis I Fall I. The Real Number System

Course 212: Academic Year Section 1: Metric Spaces

SOME TRANSFINITE INDUCTION DEDUCTIONS

2. Prime and Maximal Ideals

Topology. Xiaolong Han. Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA address:

RED. Fall 2016 Student Submitted Sample Questions

Lecture Notes on Discrete Mathematics. October 15, 2018 DRAFT

Sets, Models and Proofs. I. Moerdijk and J. van Oosten Department of Mathematics Utrecht University

Introduction to Proofs

Section 4.4 Functions. CS 130 Discrete Structures

MODEL ANSWERS TO THE SEVENTH HOMEWORK. (b) We proved in homework six, question 2 (c) that. But we also proved homework six, question 2 (a) that

INTRODUCTION TO CARDINAL NUMBERS

Sets and Functions. (As we will see, in describing a set the order in which elements are listed is irrelevant).

Prof. Ila Varma HW 8 Solutions MATH 109. A B, h(i) := g(i n) if i > n. h : Z + f((i + 1)/2) if i is odd, g(i/2) if i is even.

SOLUTIONS TO EXERCISES FOR. MATHEMATICS 205A Part 1. I. Foundational material

1.2 Functions What is a Function? 1.2. FUNCTIONS 11

CHAPTER 8: EXPLORING R

2.1 Sets. Definition 1 A set is an unordered collection of objects. Important sets: N, Z, Z +, Q, R.

The cardinal comparison of sets

Countability. 1 Motivation. 2 Counting

Sets, Structures, Numbers

Relations, Functions, and Sequences

(a) We need to prove that is reflexive, symmetric and transitive. 2b + a = 3a + 3b (2a + b) = 3a + 3b 3k = 3(a + b k)

Week Some Warm-up Questions

REVIEW FOR THIRD 3200 MIDTERM

POL502: Foundations. Kosuke Imai Department of Politics, Princeton University. October 10, 2005

CSE 20 DISCRETE MATH. Fall

Chapter 1. Sets and Numbers

Definition: Let S and T be sets. A binary relation on SxT is any subset of SxT. A binary relation on S is any subset of SxS.

Set theory. Peter J. Kahn

1. Decide for each of the following expressions: Is it a function? If so, f is a function. (i) Domain: R. Codomain: R. Range: R. (iii) Yes surjective.

Economics 204 Fall 2011 Problem Set 1 Suggested Solutions

VI I : The Axiom of Choice and related properties

Well-Ordered Sets, Ordinals and Cardinals Ali Nesin 1 July 2001

Homework 1 (revised) Solutions

Sets and Functions. MATH 464/506, Real Analysis. J. Robert Buchanan. Summer Department of Mathematics. J. Robert Buchanan Sets and Functions

MTH Abstract Algebra I and Number Theory S17. Homework 6/Solutions

Universal Totally Ordered Sets

MATH 13 SAMPLE FINAL EXAM SOLUTIONS

Section 0.7. The Axiom of Choice, Order, and Zorn s Lemma

Thus, X is connected by Problem 4. Case 3: X = (a, b]. This case is analogous to Case 2. Case 4: X = (a, b). Choose ε < b a

Transcription:

Cardinality and ordinal numbers The cardinality A of a finite set A is simply the number of elements in it. When it comes to infinite sets, we no longer can speak of the number of elements in such a set. We can, however, try to match up the elements of two infinite sets A and B one by one. If this is possible, i.e. if there is a bijective function h : A B, we say that A and B are of the same cardinality and denote this fact by A = B. If two (finite or infinite) sets A and B are not of the same cardinality, we can try to compare which one of the two sets has at least as many elements as the other. There are basically two ways of doing that: if we can pair up every element a of the set A with one and only one element b of the set B so that no two elements of B are paired with the same element of A (i.e. if there is an injective function f : A B), then B must have at least as many elements as A. Alternatively, one could detect this by exhibiting a surjective function g : B A, because that would mean that there are enough elements in B to cover all elements in A. It is a consequence of the following two theorems that these two notions of has at least as many elements as agree. Theorem. For a function f : A B, the following four statements are equivalent: (a) f : A B is injective. (b) f(s T ) = f(s) f(t ) for all S, T A. (c) f 1 (f(s)) = S for all S A. (d) There is a function g : B A such that g f = id A. Remark. Recall that the identity function id A is defined by id A (a) = a for all a A. PROOF. (a) (b) Exercise. (b) (c) Suppose f(s T ) = f(s) f(t ) for all S, T A. Let S A. We wish to sow that f 1 (f(s)) = S. First we show that S f 1 (f(s)): let s S, then f(s) f(s). So, by definition of preimage, s f 1 (f(s)). Conversely, let a f 1 (f(s)). This means that f(a) f(s). Hence, f(a) f(s) f({a}) = f(s {a}), where we use T = {a}. In particular, S {a}. Consequently, a S. (c) (d) Suppose f 1 (f(s)) = S for all S A. Assuming, as we may, that A is not empty, fix any a 0 A. We now define a function g : B A as a subset of B A as follows g = {(b, a) B A (b f(a) a = a 0 ) (b f(a) f(a) = b)}. Let us verify that g is indeed a function, i.e., that it passes the vertical line test:

Suppose (b, a 1 ), (b, a 2 ) g. If b f(a), then a 1 = a 2 = a 0 and all is well. If b f(a), then f(a 1 ) = f(a 2 ) = b, so that a 1 f 1 (f({a 2 })) = {a 2 }, where we use our assumption with S = {a 2 }. So, again, a 1 = a 2. Therefore, g is a function. Finally, in order to check if g f = id A, we let a A and put b = f(a). Then (g f)(a) = g(f(a)) = g(b) = a by definition of g. (d) (a) Exercise. Theorem. For a function g : B A, the following three statements are equivalent: (a) g : B A is surjective. (b) g(g 1 (S)) = S for all S A. (c) There is a function f : A B such that g f = id A. Remark. If you expected a forth statement here, recall that g(s T ) = g(s) g(t ) is always true for all S, T B, whether g is surjective or not. PROOF. (a) (b) Suppose that g : B A is surjective. Let S A be any subset. We wish to show that g(g 1 (S)) = S. We start with proving that g(g 1 (S)) S: let a g(g 1 (S)), then a = g(b) for some b g 1 (S). So, a = g(b) S. (Notice that this is always true.) Conversely, let s S. Since g : B A is surjective and s A, then s = g(b) for some b B. Hence, b g 1 (S), and consequently s = g(b) g(g 1 (S)). This proves that S g(g 1 (S)). (b) (c) Let us now assume that statement (b) holds. We construct the desired function f as follows: for every a A we can form the set G a = {(a, b) A B a = g(b)} of all pairs whose second coordinate b maps to its first coordinate a under g. Since, by assumption, g(g 1 ({a})) = {a} for all a A, the set g 1 ({a}) is not empty, guaranteeing the existence of at least one element b B with g(b) = a. Consequently, none of the sets G a is empty. Moreover, if a 1 a 2 then G a1 G a2 =, as can be seen by looking at the first coordinates. We are now in a position to apply the axiom of choice: let f be a set which contains exactly one element from each of the sets G a with a A. Then f A B. In fact, since by the very choice of f no two elements of f have the same first coordinate, f : A B is a function. Also, g(f(a)) = a for all a A by definition of the sets G a. (c) (a) Suppose there is a function f : A B such that g f = id A. This allows us to show that g : B A is surjective. For if a A, we can define b = f(a) B. Then g(b) = g(f(a)) = a, proving that g is surjective.

Corollary. For any two sets A and B, the following two statements are equivalent: (i) There is an injective function f : A B. (ii) There is a surjective function g : B A. PROOF. The above theorems imply that being injective is equivalent with having a left inverse and being surjective is equivalent with having a right inverse. To prove the corollary one only has to observe that a function with a right inverse is the left inverse of that function and vice versa. This, finally, allows us to make the following Definition. Let A and B be two sets. If there is an injective function f : A B, or, equivalently, if there is a surjective function g : B A, then we write A B. We will use the notation A < B to mean ( A B A B ). If A < N, then we call A finite. If A N, then we call A countable. A set, which is not countable is called uncountable. Example. A < P(A) for every set A. PROOF. Since f : A P(A) given by f(a) = {a} is clearly an injective function, we have A P(A). So, we only have to show that A = P(A). We do this by way of contradiction. Suppose that there is a surjective function g : A P(A). Then g(a) is a subset of A for every a A. Consider the set B = {a A a g(a)}. Since B A, i.e. B P(A), and g is surjective, we have B = g(b) for some b A. Now, either b B or b B. We will show that neither is possible, thus establishing the desired contradiction. If b B, then (by the very definition of the set B) b g(b) = B; but this is impossible! On the other hand, if b B, then (again by the definition of B) b g(b) = B; another impossibility. Remark (Continuum hypothesis). The following statement is known as the continuum hypothesis: there is a set B such that N < B < R. Recall that R = P(N). Accordingly, there is a generalized continuum hypothesis: given an infinite set A, there is a set B such that A < B < P(A). It has been shown that neither of these statements can be proved or disproved using the standard axioms of set theory! Theorem (Schröder-Bernstein). If A B and B A, then A = B. PROOF. Suppose there are two injective functions f : A B and g : B A. Then their composition h : A A given by h = g f is also injective. (Verify that!) Consider the set C = A \ g(b). We claim that none of the sets h(c), h(h(c)), h(h(h(c))), (which are all subsets of A) shares any elements with the set C. To see this, notice that each one of the sets h(c), h(h(c)), h(h(h(c))), is a subset of h(a) = g(f(a)) which, in turn, is a subset of g(b) = A \ C.

Put D = C h(c) h(h(c)). Then h(d) = h(c) h(h(c)) h(h(h(c))). Therefore, due to the above claim, h(d) = D \ C. Since h is injective, the function k : D h(d) defined by k(x) = h(x) is bijective. Hence, defining k(x) = x for x A\D, extends k to a bijective function k : A A\C. (Recall that C D A.) Consequently, A = A\C. We also have B = A\C, because g : B g(b) = A\C is a bijection. Thus, A = B. Definition. A relation on a set A is called a partial order if for all a, b, c A the following are true (i) a a (Reflexivity); (ii) (a b b c) a c (Transitivity); (iii) (a b b a) a = b (Antisymmetry). We will often write a x instead of (a x a x). Definition. A partial order on A is called a linear order if for every two elements a, b A either a b or b a (Comparability). Definition. Two linearly ordered sets A and B, with order relations A and B, respectively, are said to have the same order type, if there is a bijective function h : A B such that x A y if and only if h(x) B h(y). (Note that this is equivalent to requiring that h : A B be surjective and that h(x) B h(y) whenever x A y.) Remark. Different linear orders on the same set may result in different order types! Definition. A linearly ordered set A is called well-ordered if every nonempty subset S of A has a smallest element s 0, that is, if there is an s 0 S such that s 0 s for all s S. The order type of a well-ordered set is called its ordinal number. One advantage of having a well-order on a set is that it allows us to perform an induction: Theorem (Transfinite induction). Let A be a well-ordered set and let P (x) be some predicate. Suppose that P (a) is true whenever P (x) is true for all x a. Then P (a) is true for all a A. PROOF. Exercise! Definition. For an element x of a well-ordered set A we define the set S x (A) by and call it the section of A by x. S x (A) = {a A a x and a x}

We state the following theorem without proof. Theorem (Trichotomy of ordinal numbers). Suppose A and B are two well-ordered sets. Then exactly one of the following three statements is true: (i) A and B have the same order type; or (ii) A has the order type of a section of B; or (iii) B has the order type of a section of A. Remark. It is customary to denote the statements of the above theorem as (i) A = B ; (ii) A < B ; (iii) B < A. Caution: it is possible to have A < B while A = B. Can you think of an example? Corollary (Comparibility of cardinalilties). For any two sets A and B either A B or B A. PROOF. By the well-ordering theorem, there are linear orders A and B on A and B, respectively, which make A and B well-ordered. If A and B have the same order type, then there is an order preserving bijective function h : A B, so that A and B must have the same cardinality. If A has the order type of a section S b (B) of B, then there is an order preserving bijection f : A S b (B). Since this function f : A B is injective, we see that A B. The corollary now follows from the preceding theorem.