Simultaneous Choice Models: The Sandwich Approach to Nonparametric Analysis

Similar documents
The Identi cation Power of Equilibrium in Games: The. Supermodular Case

Supermodular Games. Ichiro Obara. February 6, 2012 UCLA. Obara (UCLA) Supermodular Games February 6, / 21

Nonlinear Programming (NLP)

Volume 30, Issue 3. Monotone comparative statics with separable objective functions. Christian Ewerhart University of Zurich

Extensive Form Games with Perfect Information

Endogenous timing in a mixed duopoly

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 7: Supermodular Games

Mathematical Economics - PhD in Economics

Lecture Notes on Game Theory

1 Lattices and Tarski s Theorem

UNIVERSITY OF NOTTINGHAM. Discussion Papers in Economics WEAK LINKS, GOOD SHOTS AND OTHER PUBLIC GOOD GAMES: BUILDING ON BBV

Solving Extensive Form Games

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 8: Supermodular and Potential Games

Lecture 8: Basic convex analysis

The Kuhn-Tucker Problem

Robust Mechanism Design and Robust Implementation

Lecture Notes on Bargaining

Advanced Microeconomics Fall Lecture Note 1 Choice-Based Approach: Price e ects, Wealth e ects and the WARP

Microeconomics, Block I Part 2

UNIVERSITY OF NOTTINGHAM. Discussion Papers in Economics CONSISTENT FIRM CHOICE AND THE THEORY OF SUPPLY

On strategic complementarity conditions in Bertrand oligopoly

Lecture Notes on Game Theory

Some Notes on Costless Signaling Games

Unique Nash Implementation for a Class of Bargaining Solutions

Implicit Function Theorem: One Equation

EconS Advanced Microeconomics II Handout on Subgame Perfect Equilibrium (SPNE)

Puri cation 1. Stephen Morris Princeton University. July Economics.

Intro to Economic analysis

Economics Bulletin, 2012, Vol. 32 No. 1 pp Introduction. 2. The preliminaries

Alvaro Rodrigues-Neto Research School of Economics, Australian National University. ANU Working Papers in Economics and Econometrics # 587

Non-parametric Identi cation and Testable Implications of the Roy Model

Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics

Labor Economics, Lecture 11: Partial Equilibrium Sequential Search

Multimarket Oligopolies with Restricted Market Access

Limit pricing models and PBE 1

1 Games in Normal Form (Strategic Form)

Chapter 2. GMM: Estimating Rational Expectations Models

Treatment response with social interactions: Partial identification via monotone comparative statics

Identification of Discrete Choice Models for Bundles and Binary Games

Chapter 1. GMM: Basic Concepts

Game Theory. Bargaining Theory. ordi Massó. International Doctorate in Economic Analysis (IDEA) Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona (UAB)

DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES

ECON2285: Mathematical Economics

Internet Appendix for The Labor Market for Directors and Externalities in Corporate Governance

Applied cooperative game theory:

On the microeconomic foundations of linear demand for di erentiated products

Advanced Microeconomics

Banks, depositors and liquidity shocks: long term vs short term interest rates in a model of adverse selection

OPTIMISM AND PESSIMISM IN GAMES

The Intuitive and Divinity Criterion:

Tijmen Daniëls Universiteit van Amsterdam. Abstract

Topics in Mathematical Economics. Atsushi Kajii Kyoto University

Microeconomics, Block I Part 1

Exclusive contracts and market dominance

Final Exam (Solution) Economics 501b Microeconomic Theory

Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics

Cowles Foundation for Research in Economics at Yale University

Carrot and stick games

Moral Hazard: Hidden Action

A Characterization of Strategic Complementarities

NBER WORKING PAPER SERIES IDENTIFICATION OF POTENTIAL GAMES AND DEMAND MODELS FOR BUNDLES. Jeremy T. Fox Natalia Lazzati

A Folk Theorem For Stochastic Games With Finite Horizon

Bayesian Persuasion Online Appendix

Northwestern University

Positive Models of Private Provision of Public Goods: A Static Model. (Bergstrom, Blume and Varian 1986)

Iterative Weak Dominance and Interval-Dominance Supermodular Games

9 A Class of Dynamic Games of Incomplete Information:

The Geometry of Aggregative Games

1 Uncertainty and Insurance

Cowles Foundation for Research in Economics at Yale University

Some Notes on Adverse Selection

COMPARISON OF INFORMATION STRUCTURES IN ZERO-SUM GAMES. 1. Introduction

EconS Microeconomic Theory II Homework #9 - Answer key

An E cient Auction. (First version: October 1998) April 2001

Implementation with Interdependent Valuations Preliminary and Incomplete

Learning and Risk Aversion

Nonparametric Welfare Analysis for Discrete Choice

A Necessary and Sufficient Condition for a Unique Maximum with an Application to Potential Games

Iterative Weak Dominance and Interval-Dominance Supermodular Games

Desire-as-belief revisited

On the Existence of a Bayesian Nash Equilibrium in Tullock Contests with Incomplete Information y

Choosing the Two Finalists

Lecture 3 - Axioms of Consumer Preference and the Theory of Choice

Comparative Statics and Heterogeneity

Identi cation of Positive Treatment E ects in. Randomized Experiments with Non-Compliance

ECON0702: Mathematical Methods in Economics

Discussion Paper #1541

Not Only What But also When A Theory of Dynamic Voluntary Disclosure

Gi en Demand for Several Goods

Lecture 7: General Equilibrium - Existence, Uniqueness, Stability

Robust Predictions in Games with Incomplete Information

RSMG Working Paper Series. TITLE: The value of information and the value of awareness. Author: John Quiggin. Working Paper: R13_2

Economics 201B Economic Theory (Spring 2017) Bargaining. Topics: the axiomatic approach (OR 15) and the strategic approach (OR 7).

Existence of Equilibrium in Tullock Contests with Incomplete Information

A Solution to the Problem of Externalities When Agents Are Well-Informed

Advanced Economic Growth: Lecture 21: Stochastic Dynamic Programming and Applications

Lecture 7. Simple Dynamic Games

AGM-consistency and perfect Bayesian equilibrium. Part II: from PBE to sequential equilibrium.

Groups with Intersecting Interests

ONLINE APPENDICES FOR INCENTIVES IN EXPERIMENTS: A THEORETICAL INVESTIGATION BY AZRIELI, CHAMBERS & HEALY

Transcription:

Simultaneous Choice Models: The Sandwich Approach to Nonparametric Analysis Natalia Lazzati y November 09, 2013 Abstract We study collective choice models from a revealed preference approach given limited data. By limited data we mean that we observe a single equilibrium from the equilibrium set of a nite collection of related models. The objective of our analysis is twofold: We rst use the data to provide out-of-sample predictions of equilibrium points via a novel use of the monotone comparative statics method. We then propose conditions on the data so that the empirical evidence can be rationalized as the Nash equilibria of a supermodular game. Our approach is nonparametric and does not rely on any equilibrium selection mechanism. It only depends on monotone and exclusion restrictions. JEL codes: C31, D01 Keywords: Simultaneous choice models, supermodular games, partial identi cation, out-of-sample predictions, monotone comparative statics. Natalia Lazzati, Department of Economics, University of Michigan, Ann Arbor (e-mail: nlazzati@umich.edu). y I thank Dan Ackerberg, Amilcar Menichini, and John Quah for very useful comments. participants at the economics seminars of Cornell U, U of Pittsburgh and CMU, and Binghamton U. I also thank 1

1 Introduction Much of the empirical content of economics lies in the comparative statics predictions it generates [Kreps (2013)]. The celebrated monotone comparative statics (MCS) for games is a powerful yet simple method to contrast equilibrium points for an indexed family of models as we vary the parameter of interest. 1 From a theoretical perspective, MCS has proved very useful. There are at least two plausible explanations for its success. First, it works under conditions that are often easy to justify on economic grounds. Second, it allows us to compare equilibrium points in games with multiple solutions. From an empirical perspective, on the other hand, it has not received much attention. One of the reasons is that, with partial observability of equilibrium points, the standard predictions of MCS are neither testable nor useful for counterfactual analysis unless we impose speci c equilibrium selection rules on the data-generating process. One may conclude too readily that, in contrast to our initial statement, MCS is of little use in the empirical analysis of games. We give a new look at the importance of MCS for counterfactual predictions in the context of simultaneous choice models. The idea is simple: There is a set of agents that receive treatments and make interdependent decisions. We think of a treatment in a very general way. For instance, if individual behavior derives from an underlying game, then the treatment may a ect the payo function of the player and/or the collection of feasible strategies. Observable choices are assumed to be consistent with equilibrium behavior. We have limited data on past choices for various realized treatments. The data is limited in that, for each realized treatment, we observe only one equilibrium from the equilibrium set. The objective of our analysis is twofold: We rst want to predict the actions that could be taken by the group members if they were to receive a treatment that di ers from the ones we observe in the data. We refer to this set of choices as either the counterfactual or the out-of-sample predictions. Our second objective is to address whether our limited data can be rationalized as the Nash equilibria of an underlying supermodular game among the agents. The approach we propose to achieve our goals is nonparametric and does not impose any equilibrium selection mechanism on the data-generating process. It alternatively relies on 1 See, e.g., Milgrom and Roberts (1990), Milgrom and Shannon (1994), and Vives (1990). 2

exclusion restrictions at the individual level and monotone shape conditions on the primitives of the model (i.e., the choice functions). An advantage of our assumptions is that they are indeed testable. That is, they can be proved false given the data. By exclusion restrictions we mean that individual treatments may a ect the choice of one agent without having a direct impact on the choice functions of the other agents in the group. For instance, in a model of demand with network e ects, income levels are natural candidates for the exclusion restrictions. The reason is that the income level of a given person only conditions the budget set of that particular individual. In the same model, prices may or may not play the role of exclusion restriction depending on whether we allow for price discrimination. This restriction allows us to track the choice function of each agent for any action pro le of the others. We elaborate next on the monotone assumptions we sustain. The primitives of our model are a system of interdependent choice functions that relate the choice of each individual in a group to the treatment and the decisions of the other group members. The two monotone conditions we impose are as follows: the choice function of each individual increases with the action pro le of the others; and it varies monotonically with the treatment to be received by the agent. These conditions imply clear restrictions on the equilibrium set: The system of structural equations leads to an increasing function that maps feasible choices into itself, so that the set of solutions of the model coincides with the set of xed points of this arti cial function. By Tarski s xed point theorem, the rst condition guarantees the system has a minimal and a maximal solution, i.e., the model is coherent. The second restriction shifts the function up or down, inducing the extremal solutions to vary monotonically with the treatments. This is the celebrated MCS of equilibrium points for games. Since this comparative statics result only refers to the extremal equilibria, its implications regarding equilibrium behavior are neither testable nor useful for making counterfactual predictions unless we impose speci c equilibrium selection rules on the data-generating process, e.g., coordination on extremal equilibria. As we described above, we develop this model with two objectives in mind. We rst show that while the standard implications of the MCS method are uninformative regarding counterfactual predictions, the two monotone conditions that are behind this result are yet extremely powerful. Speci cally, when combined with the exclusion restrictions we mentioned above, they allow us to construct sharp bounds for individual choice functions given the empirical evidence. By sharp we mean 3

that the true set of choice functions must lie between the bounds we propose, and that we cannot reject the hypothesis that the true set actually coincides with one or the other. We then use these extremal choice functions to bound equilibrium behavior by an approach that relies on a novel use of the MCS method. This result addresses our initial objective of analysis, namely, deriving out-of-sample predictions of equilibrium points. We refer to the latter as the sandwich approach to the out-of-sample predictions. The second objective of our analysis is to show that, if the data satis es certain monotone conditions, then the empirical evidence can always be rationalized as the Nash equilibria of a supermodular game. (Thus, the monotone restrictions we derive capture all the empirical content of the supermodular games.) To achieve our goal we show that any set of monotone choice functions can be rationalized as a set of best-reply functions of a supermodular game among the agents. The proof follows by construction. That is, we construct a set of payo functions, one for each agent, that have the choice functions as the corresponding maximizers. Because the consistent set of choice functions is multivalued and has extremal elements, we construct extremal supermodular games that are consistent with the data. These games di er regarding the strength of the interaction e ects: The lowest set of consistent choice functions is associated with the supermodular game with the weakest interaction e ects. The opposite is true regarding the highest set. We refer to this result as the sandwich approach to the supermodular rationalization. We nally extend the idea to allow for multivalued choice functions (or choice correspondences) and discuss some other relevant features of our model. Literature Review This study is intimately related to the theoretical literature of supermodular games [see, e.g., Milgrom and Roberts (1990), Milgrom and Shannon (1994), Vives (1990), and Topkis (1979)]. We contribute to this work by elaborating on the empirical content of monotone comparative statics for equilibrium points [see also Aradillas-López (2011), De Paula (2009), Jia (2008), and Molinari and Rosen (2008)]. Our work also relates to some recent studies on the testable implications of collective choice models [see, e.g., Browning and Chiappori (1998), Cherchye et al. (2013), Carbajal et al. (2013-a), Chambers et al. (2010), Deb et al. (2012), and 4

Sprumont (2000)]. We emphasize on the advantages of both exclusion and monotone shape restrictions to recover the objects of interest. Varian (1982) and De Clippel and Rozen (2013) provide a nonparametric analysis of individualistic models of rational behavior and bounded rationality, respectively. We extend their results to models of interdependent decisions. As we mentioned above, we construct a family of supermodular games that rationalize the set of choice functions that are consistent with both our assumptions and the data. The family we construct is bounded from below and above by two games that di er regarding the strength of the interaction e ects. This result relates to the approach proposed by Amir (2008) to obtain comparative statics analysis of equilibrium points in games that may not be supermodular. Echenique and Komunjer (2009) provide a test for MCS. They show that, under a general stochastic equilibrium selection rule that places positive probability on the extremal equilibria, MCS has observable implications on the extremal quantiles of the distribution of equilibrium points. Their result applies to models of individual behavior with multiple maximizers and certain games with multiple equilibria. Along the study, we show that, while the implications of MCS in terms of equilibrium behavior for games are non-testable unless we impose some structure on the equilibrium selection rule, its underlying assumptions can be proved false given the data without such a restriction. This result opens new avenues for testing complementarities under Nash-behavior or for testing Nash-behavior in games of strategic complements (see also Carbajal et al. (2013-b)). The econometric literature has recently emphasized on the relevance of monotone restrictions to provide identi cation results. In this line of research, Kline and Tamer (2012), Lazzati (2013), and Manski (1997, 2011) take advantage of monotone conditions to obtain non-parametric partial identi cation results of di erent counterfactuals. Our closest precedent is Lazzati (2013), who studies identi cation in a model of treatment response with social interactions. A key di erence between the present study and the former is that, in order to bound equilibrium behavior, we rst recover individual choice functions. This intermediate step allows us to dispense with any assumption about equilibrium selection but it requires exclusion restrictions at the level of each agent. Thus, the two studies complement each other. Uetake and Watanabe (2013) also exploit MCS to provide estimation results for supermodular games. Their approach is parametric and the bounds they obtain are (generally) not sharp. The rest of the paper is organized as follows. Section 2 presents the model and the 5

objective of our analysis. Section 3 shows why the standard implications of the MCS method are not useful for counterfactual predictions and proposes an alternative approach to tackle this di culty. Section 4 uses the previous results to achieve our twofold objective, namely, outof-sample prediction of equilibrium points and rationalization of the data by a supermodular game. Section 5 includes some extensions and remarks, and Section 6 concludes. All proofs are collected in Section 7. 2 The Model This section presents the model and elaborates on the objective of our analysis. We consider a nite set of agents N = f1; 2; :::; ng that make interdependent decisions. Agent i 2 N selects an element a i from her set of available options A i ( i ) A i : We describe her behavior by the choice function C i ( i ; a i ) : T i A i! A i with C i ( i ; a i ) 2 A i ( i ) where a i = (a j : j 2 N; j 6= i) is the vector of other agents choices and A i = j2n;j6=i A j. We refer to i 2 T i as the treatment received by the agent. Thus, the choice function of agent i indicates the action that she selects for each possible treatment and pro le of actions of the other agents in N. This last e ect is the source of interdependence in our model. If the choice functions derive from an underlying game, then C i ( i ; a i ) = arg max ai fu i (a i ; a i ; i ) : a i 2 A i ( i )g (1) where U i is the payo function of agent i and C i can be interpreted as her best-reply function. In (1), the treatment a ects the choice of the agent by modifying both her payo function and her set of available options. Let V = (C i : i 2 N). We refer to V as the microeconomic speci cation of the model. Thus, our model can be described by the tuple = (N; V; ) where = ( i : i 2 N) 2 T = i2n T i is a treatment vector. We next introduce our solution concept. De nition (Solution Concept): We say () = ( i () : i 2 N) is consistent with equilibrium behavior generated by if, for all i 2 N, i () = C i ( i ; a i ) with a i = j () : j 2 N; j 6= i : 6

We indicate by : T i2n A i, with i2n A i ( i ), the equilibrium correspondence: That is, we say () is consistent with equilibrium behavior if each agent selects an option according to both her choice function and the equilibrium behavior of the other agents. In the context of a game, our solution concept is a Nash equilibrium in pure strategies. We are now ready to describe the objective of our analysis. Objective of Analysis: We have limited data on realized choices for a set of treatments a m = (a m i : i 2 N) and m = ( m i : i 2 N) for m = 1; :::; M: We assume these observations are consistent with equilibrium behavior. Our data is limited because for each realized treatment we only observe one element of the equilibrium set, i.e., the equilibrium selected by the group. Our rst goal is to learn about the actions that could be taken by this set of agents if they were to receive a treatment. In other words, we observe an equilibrium outcome ( m ) 2 m for a set of realized treatments ( m : m M) and want to use this information to learn about the equilibrium set for an alternative. Our second goal is to provide conditions on the data so that the empirical evidence can be rationalized as the Nash equilibria of an underlying game. This is the same as to ask whether we can nd a set of payo functions P = (U i : i 2 N), with each U i given as in (1), that can generate the data as the Nash equilibria of the induced game. The approach we propose to achieve our goals relies on monotone conditions on the microeconomic speci cation of our model (V) and exclusion restrictions at the individual level. The next example illustrates the concepts and ideas that we just described and motivates our main assumptions. Example 1: Let us consider a demand model with network e ects. The choice function of each agent indicates the amount of the network good, X, that the person acquires. The treatment is the price the individual has to pay per unit of the good and her income level. Thus, i = p; m i and A i ( i ) = [0; m i =p] : (We write p instead of p to ful ll our monotone restrictions.) We have that C i (p; m i ; x i ) : R ++ R + R n 1 +! R + with C i (p; m i ; x i ) 2 [0; m i =p] 7

where x i = (x j : j 2 N; j 6= i) is the amount of the network good acquired by the others. In this application, C i represents the demand function of consumer i. An equilibrium (p; m), with m = (m i : i 2 N), is a vector in R n + that indicates the amount of the network good that has been acquired by each person in the economy. We have limited data on past consumption decisions for a set of di erent prices and income levels. We want to use the empirical evidence to predict market demand for a vector of prices and income levels that di er from the ones we observe in the data. The method we propose relies on monotone restrictions on V. When applied to this model, it requires the decision of each consumer to be increasing in the choices of the others and her income level, and decreasing with respect to the price of the good. Our approach also depends on exclusion restrictions. Since the income level of consumer i a ects her demand function without having a direct impact on the choices of the others, income levels are natural exclusion restrictions in this application. These exclusion restrictions allow us to track the demand function of each consumer as a function of the choices of other consumers in the economy. The method we propose allows for price discrimination. That is, we could let prices depend on the names of the agents by substituting p by p i : In this context, the counterfactual predictions we derive could be used to evaluate target marketing strategies that aim to identify the in uential consumers, that is, the set of consumers that have a large impact on the choices of other consumers in the economy (see, e.g., Candogan et al. (2012)). The next section introduces our required conditions and presents a few propositions that will allow us to make out-of-sample predictions. It also connects our assumptions with the so-called supermodular games. 3 Another Look at Monotone Comparative Statics Simultaneous choice models may have no equilibrium. Lack of equilibrium existence means that we cannot use our solution concept to predict consistent behavior. From an econometrics perspective this possibility introduces additional di culties into the analysis. For instance, data on past choices may not be informative about the beliefs of each agent with respect to the behavior of the others and it is therefore hard to recover their choice functions. To address this di culty, we rst impose simple conditions on V that guarantee the model has 8

at least one equilibrium. 2 We then provide comparative statics results and elaborate on our strategy for making out-of-sample predictions given the limited data. We nally connect all our assumptions with the class of supermodular games. With a slight abuse of notation, we use to compare elements of both the action and the treatment spaces. When applied to either R m or Z m, is simply the standard coordinatewise order on the reals. Along the analysis, T i is a partially ordered set. When applied to the treatments, the meaning of depends on the speci c application. Our rst condition imposes some structure on the choice sets. (A1) For all i 2 N, A i ( i ) and A i are non-empty compact intervals of either R m or Z m and a i ( i ) = inf (A i ( i )) and a i ( i ) = sup (A i ( i )) increase in i : The monotonicity of the extremal elements of the choice sets is a natural restriction given the nature of the approach we propose for the nonparametric analysis. In Example 1 A i ( i ) = [0; m i =p] is a non-empty compact interval in R and a i ( i ) = 0 and a i ( i ) = m i =p increase in i = p; m i : Thus, this model satis es A1. The next condition requires the choice function of each agent to be increasing in the action pro le of the other agents. (A2) For all i 2 N, C i ( i ; a i ) increases in a i : Under condition A2, our model displays positive interaction e ects. In Example 1, cellphones and software are goods for which researchers and practitioners often believe this restriction is naturally satis ed. The next result states that, if A1 and A2 hold, then the solution set is non-empty and has extremal elements for each treatment level. Proposition 1 Under A1 and A2, is a non-empty complete lattice. Thus, there exist extremal equilibria, and, such that any of satis es () () : 2 Chesher and Rosen (2012) provide identi cation results for models that have no solution for some covariate values. 9

We next provide a sketch of the proof for two agents. The proof of Proposition 1 relies on a mapping M : A 1 A 2! A 1 A 2, de ned as follows M (a 1 ; a 2 ) = (C 1 ( 1 ; a 2 ) ; C 2 ( 2 ; a 1 )) : (2) Function M maps pairs of actions into itself. Given our solution concept, any xed point of M corresponds to a pro le of actions consistent with equilibrium behavior generated by : Thus, the proof of Proposition 1 consists in showing that the set of xed points of M is a non-empty complete lattice. Under A2, the result follows by Tarski s xed point theorem. Though important, the existence result we just described does not impose enough structure on the model in order to make the empirical evidence informative. To do so, we need to connect the alternative models in such a way that we can use the equilibrium behavior revealed by the data for a set of treatments to learn about the equilibrium set corresponding to a di erent treatment level. We next add a second restriction on V that establishes this connection. (A3) For all i 2 N, C i ( i ; a i ) increases in i : When applied to Example 1, this condition requires the demand function of consumer i to be increasing in the income level and decreasing in the market price. Note that we can always reverse the order of some of the elements in the treatment to satisfy this condition. We just need to be consistent with A1. The next proposition states that, under (A1, A2, and A3), we can compare the extremal elements of the equilibrium sets for every pair of ordered treatment vectors. Proposition 2 (MCS) Under A1, A2, and A3, () and () increase in : Assumption A3 shifts map M up (in equation (2)), inducing an increase in the extremal solutions. Proposition 2 is the standard MCS result of equilibrium points. The next example serves various purposes: First, it helps us to illustrate our claim in the introduction. That is, we show that the MCS result, in and of itself, is not useful for counterfactual analysis with limited data. We then show that its underlying assumptions namely, A2 and A3 are nevertheless extremely powerful for deriving out-of-sample predictions. We nally use the example to highlight the role of the exclusion restrictions in our identi cation analysis. 10

Example 2: Let N = f1; 2g, T 1 = T 2 = f; g (with ), and A i = fa i ; a i g (with a i a i ) for i = 1; 2: The data we have and the problem we face are described by the next tables Data Out-of-Sample Prediction a 2 a 2 a 2 a 2 1 = ; 2 = a 1 a 1 1 = ; 2 = a 1 a 1 a 2 a 2 1 = ; 2 = a 1 a 1 1 = ; 2 = a 1 a 1 a 2 a 2 That is, we know the options selected by these two agents under three di erent treatments: The selected pro les are indicated by dots in the tables on the left. We also know that these data were generated by equilibrium behavior. Our goal is to describe all possible equilibrium pro les for the low treatment levels that are consistent with the empirical evidence and satisfy our initial assumptions. We will write X for consistent pro les, and reserve x for the inconsistent ones. It is readily veri ed that the MCS result, in and of itself, does not allow us to rule out any action pro le. That is, by only relying on this prediction, every single pair of choices is consistent with equilibrium behavior given the available data. Out-of-Sample Prediction with MCS a 2 a 2 1 = ; 2 = a 1 X X a 1 X X Nevertheless, if we know that A2 and A3 are satis ed, then we can make a unique prediction. The table below captures this observation. 11

Out-of-Sample Prediction with A2 and A3 a 2 a 2 1 = ; 2 = a 1 X x a 1 x x We now elaborate on how we found (; ) under A2 and A3. We know the data corresponds to equilibrium behavior. Thus, each data point allows us to recover an element of the choice functions, e.g., C 1 (; a 2 ) = a 1. Once we recover all these elements we can invoke A2 and A3 to infer the other ones. For instance, since C 1 (; a 2 ) = a 1, then, by A2, it must be that C 1 (; a 2 ) = a 1. Proceeding in this way, there is only one element for which we do not have any information, C 2 (; a 1 ) : For this element, all we can say is that C 2 (; a 1 ) 2 fa 2 ; a 2 g. Thus, we nd two sets of choice functions that are consistent with the data and satisfy A2 and A3, namely, U and W below. U = W = 0 @ B 1 ( 1 ; a 2 ) = a 1 1 ( 1 ; a 2 < ; a 2 ) + a 1 [1 1 ( 1 ; a 2 < ; a 2 )] B 2 ( 2 ; a 1 ) = a 2 1 ( 2 ; a 1 ; a 1 ) + a 2 [1 1 ( 2 ; a 1 ; a 1 )] 0 @ D 1 ( 1 ; a 2 ) = a 1 1 ( 1 ; a 2 < ; a 2 ) + a 1 [1 1 ( 1 ; a 2 < ; a 2 )] D 2 ( 2 ; a 1 ) = a 2 1 ( 2 ; a 1 ; a 1 ) + a 2 [1 1 ( 2 ; a 1 ; a 1 )] 1 A 1 A We nally compute all possible equilibria for U and W. These action pro les constitute our out-of-sample prediction. After doing so, we nd only one equilibrium, namely, (a 1 ; a 2 ). In summary, while the MCS result is neither testable nor informative for out-of-sample analysis, the opposite is true regarding assumptions A2 and A3. This is the leading force of our nonparametric analysis in the following section. In this example, by exclusion restrictions we mean that the treatment level can take on di erent values for the two individuals. This allowed us to track the choice function of each agent for a given treatment and alternative choices of the other one. While the method we propose for out-of-sample predictions can still be applied without these exclusion restrictions, if they do not hold, then our bounds for equilibrium behavior would almost always be just the trivial ones, i.e., the extremal elements of the set of available options. To illustrate this point, 12

note that, in absence of the exclusion restrictions, the available data and the corresponding predictions would be as follows. Data 1 = ; 2 = a 1 a 1 a 2 a 2 Out-of-Sample Prediction with A2 and A3 a 2 a 2 1 = ; 2 = a 1 X X a 1 X X Thus, even assuming that A2 and A3 hold, we cannot rule out any action pro le. Example 2 shows the power of (A1, A2, and A3) and the exclusion restrictions for making counterfactual predictions. The problem with the approach we just described is that it is non-tractable when we add more feasible options. Moreover, it does not work if the choice set of each agent is of in nite dimension, e.g., a compact interval on the real line as in Example 1. The key idea we want to convey is that, in our model, in order to provide sharp bounds for equilibrium points we only need to recover the extremal elements of the consistent set of choice functions, e.g., U and W above. We formalize this idea in the following section by invoking a theoretical result that we present next. We will refer to this result as the sandwich approach to the nonparametric analysis. Let B i and D i be two possible speci cations for the choice function of agent i. Our last proposition relies on the next condition. (A4) For all i 2 N, D i ( i ; a i ) C i ( i ; a i ) B i ( i ; a i ) for all i and a i. Let us indicate by U = (B i : i 2 N) and W = (D i : i 2 N) two microeconomic speci cations for the model. Let ; and ; be the extremal equilibria corresponding to U and W, respectively, when such equilibria exist. The next proposition states that if A1 holds and U, V, and W satisfy A2 and A4, then the extremal equilibria associated to U and W bound every element of the equilibrium set corresponding to V. Proposition 3 Assume A1 holds and U, V, and W satisfy A2 and A4. Then, for all 2 T, () () () and () () () : 13

From a theoretical perspective, Proposition 3 is just a variant of Proposition 2. 3 It says that if we nd two sets of monotone choice functions that sandwich the one we are interested in, then the extremal equilibria of these two sets of functions bound any equilibrium behavior that is consistent with the true one. We next o er a sketch of proof for the case of two agents. In addition to M, we de ne two other mappings L (a 1 ; a 2 ) = (B 1 ( 1 ; a 2 ) ; B 2 ( 2 ; a 1 )) and N (a 1 ; a 2 ) = (D 1 ( 1 ; a 2 ) ; D 2 ( 2 ; a 1 )). Under A4, we have that, for all (a 1 ; a 2 ) 2 A 1 A 2, N (a 1 ; a 2 ) M (a 1 ; a 2 ) L (a 1 ; a 2 ) : Functions L, M, and N map pairs of actions into themselves. Under A2, the three mappings are increasing. Thus, the three of them have extremal xed points and these extremal xed points respect the order of the mappings. The next section invokes this result to provide out-of-sample predictions for equilibrium points. To this end, we will show that, if the empirical evidence satis es certain monotone conditions, then we can always use the data to construct extremal sets of monotone choice functions such as U and W in Example 2. The result will then follow as a simple corollary of Proposition 3. We next connect our modeling restrictions with the theoretical literature on supermodular games. Supermodular Games with Monotone Best-Reply Functions: Let P = (U i : i 2 N) be the set of payo functions of all players in N. We assume that condition A1 holds. When the choice functions result from an underlying game, then C i ( i ; a i ) = arg max ai fu i (a i ; a i ; i ) : a i 2 A i ( i )g where U i is the payo function of agent i and C i is her best-reply function. If U i is strictly concave in a i (on all R m ); then C i ( i ; a i ) is indeed non-empty and single-valued. 4 3 Amir (2008) shows that a similar result can be obtained even if the intermediate mapping is not increasing. 4 If A i Z m ; then the standard de nition of strict concavity needs to be modi ed as follows. We say U i is strictly concave in a if there exists an extention of U i on the convex hull of A i that is strictly concave. 14

We say U i is supermodular in a i if, for all a i ; a 0 i 2 A i, U i a i ^ a 0 i; a i ; i + Ui a i _ a 0 i; a i ; i Ui (a i ; a i ; i ) + U i a 0 i; a i ; i : In addition, U i has increasing di erences in (a i ; a i ) if, for all a i a 0 i and a i a 0 i, U i (a i ; a i ; i ) U i a 0 i; a i ; i Ui a i ; a 0 i; i U i a 0 i; a 0 i; i : That is, if the extra payo of increasing own action increases with the choices of the others. When U i is supermodular in a i and has increasing di erences in (a i ; a i ), then C i ( i ; a i ) increases in a i and A2 holds. These two conditions are the distinctive feature of any supermodular game. We say U i has increasing di erences in (a; i ) if, for all a i a 0 i and i 0 i, U i (a i ; a i ; i ) U i a 0 i; a i ; i Ui a i ; a i ; 0 i U i a 0 i; a i ; 0 i : That is, if the extra payo of increasing own action increases with the treatment. If U i is supermodular in a i and has increasing di erences in (a i ; i ), then C i ( i ; a i ) increases in i and A3 holds. Thus, our initial assumptions are satis ed by certain types of supermodular games with single valued best-reply functions and our results can be thereby applied to them. We will show later that the reverse is also true. That is, if the available data satisfy certain monotone restrictions, then we can always construct a set of payo functions that rationalize the empirical evidence as the Nash equilibria of a supermodular game with the above properties. We will also show that our results apply to certain games with multi-valued best-replies. We next illustrate our last concepts by using an extension of Example 1. Example 3: Let X be the network good and let Y be a numerarie. Suppose that consumer i selects X and Y by solving the standard optimization problem max x;y Ui (x; y; x i ) : x; y 2 R 2 + and xp + y m i : Let U i be strictly concave and strictly increasing in y. It follows that C i ( i ; x i ) = arg max x fu i (x; m i xp; x i ) : x 2 [0; m i =p]g : 15

Thus, we can think of C i as the best-reply function of person i induced by a game among potential consumers. In this context, the equilibrium demand is just a Nash equilibrium. In this example, U i has increasing di erences in (x; x i ) if, for all x x 0 and x i x 0 i, U i (x; m i xp; x i ) U i x 0 ; m i xp; x i Ui x; m i xp; x 0 i When U i is continuously di erentiable, this condition holds if U i x 0 ; m i xp; x 0 i : MRS x;y = (@U i (x; y; x i ) =@x) = (@U i (x; y; x i ) =@y) increases in x i : That is, if the marginal rate of substitutions between the network good and the numerarie increases with the amount of the network good acquired by the other consumers. When this condition is satis ed, then A2 holds and the game among potential consumers is said to be supermodular. In addition, U i has increasing di erences in (x; m i ; p) if, for all x x 0 and m i ; p m 0 i ; p0, U i (x; m i xp; x i ) U i x 0 ; m i xp; x i Ui x; m 0 i xp 0 ; x i U i x 0 ; m 0 i xp 0 ; x i : When U i is continuously di erentiable, this condition holds if @U i (x; y; x i ) =@x increases in y: That is, if the marginal utility with respect to the network good increases with the numerarie. Finally, the constraint set is ascending in i = p; m i in the sense that the extremal elements of the interval [0; m i =p] increase in i = p; m i. Thus, A1 holds. It follows that A3 is also satis ed. The next section elaborates on the nonparametric analysis of our model: We rst use our previous results to provide out-of sample predictions of equilibrium points given the limited data. We then address rationalization of the data by a supermodular game. 4 The Sandwich Approach to Nonparametric Analysis 4.1 Out-of-Sample Predictions This section addresses our rst goal. That is, we provide out-of-sample predictions of equilibrium behavior for alternative treatments given our limited data. We do so without im- 16

posing functional form restrictions on the choice functions. Taking advantage of our previous results, we follow what we call the sandwich approach to nonparametric analysis. Kline and Tamer (2012), Lazzati (2013), and Manski (1997, 2011) exploit similar monotone conditions to obtain nonparametric partial identi cation results of counterfactuals in di erent models. In what follows, we maintain the next restriction. Identi cation Assumption (IA): (A1, A2, and A3) hold and A i ( i ) is known for all i 2 N. Recall that we have limited data on realized choices for a set of treatments a m = (a m i : i 2 N) and m = ( m i : i 2 N) for m = 1; :::; M: By Proposition 1, IA guarantees that, for each 2 T, there is at least one equilibrium. Since the empirical evidence is consistent with equilibrium behavior, the data identi es ( m ) = a m for all m M: Given our solution concept, for each i 2 N, C i m i ; a m i = a m i for all m M: Thus, C i ( i ; a i ) is identi ed by the data for all i ; a i 2 m i ; am i : m M. means that, if IA holds, then the data must satisfy the next monotone restriction. This also (M) For all i 2 N and m; t M, a m i a t i if m ; a m i t ; a t i and a m i = a t i if m ; a m i = t ; a t i: We next elaborate on the other direction. That is, we show that if the data satis es condition M, then we can always nd a set of monotone choice functions V = (C i : i 2 N) such that each C i extends [C i m i ; i am = a m i for all m M] to all other arguments. This is precisely what we did in Example 2 to provide bounds for equilibrium behavior. Functions B i and D i below constitute the smallest and the largest speci cations of C i that, being consistent with the data, satisfy conditions A2 and A3. In the following expressions, inf and sup are taken with respect to A i. B i ( i ; a i ) = inf a i : a i 2 A i ( i ) ; a i sup a m i D i ( i ; a i ) = sup a i : a i 2 A i ( i ) ; a i inf a m i : m i ; am i i; a i ; m M : m i ; am i i; a i ; m M The next proposition formalizes our claim. 17

Proposition 4 Given the data and IA, for all i 2 N, D i ( i ; a i ) C i ( i ; a i ) B i ( i ; a i ) for all i and a i : Moreover, the bounds are sharp. A key step in the proof of Proposition 4 consists of showing that B i and D i are indeed monotone. We now use the previous result to provide bounds for. Let us de ne U = (B i : i 2 N) and W = (D i : i 2 N) and let and indicate the smallest and the largest equilibrium corresponding to U and W, respectively. Given Proposition 4, the next result follows as a corollary of Proposition 3. Proposition 5 Given the data and IA; for all 2 T : () () for all 2 : Moreover, the bounds are sharp. We next summarize our main ndings. The Sandwich Approach to Out-of-Sample Predictions: If the empirical evidence satis es condition M, then, for any treatment, we can always construct two extremal sets of choice functions such that the true one must lie between them and can actually coincide with one or the other. The extremal equilibria of these two sets of functions bound any element of the equilibrium set corresponding to the treatment of interest. In the following section we show that if the data satis es condition M, then the empirical evidence can be always rationalized as the Nash equilibria of a supermodular game. 4.2 Rationalization by a Supermodular Game This section addresses our second goal. That is, we show that if the data satisfy condition M in the previous section, then we can always construct a supermodular game with monotone best-replies that rationalizes the empirical evidence as its Nash equilibria. 18

In the last section, we showed that if M holds, then we can always construct extremal sets of monotone choice functions U = (B i : i 2 N) and W = (D i : i 2 N) such that the true set of choice functions V = (C i : i 2 N) lies between them and can actually coincide with one or the other. To achieve our second goal we now show that for any given set of monotone choice functions V there always exists a set of payo functions, one for each agent, that has V as the set of maximizers. Moreover, by construction, these payo functions satisfy the conditions of the supermodular games with monotone best-reply functions that we discussed at the end of Section 3. Before presenting the main proposition, we de ne the concept of supermodular rationalization. De nition (Supermodular Rationalization): We say a set of payo functions P = (U i : i 2 N), with U i : A i A i T! A i, rationalize V if, for all i 2 N, C i ( i ; a i ) = arg max ai fu i (a i ; a i ; i ) : a i 2 A i (a i )g : If in addition, for all i 2 N, U i is supermodular in a i and has increasing di erences in both (a i ; a i ) and (a i ; i ), then we say P is a supermodular rationalization of V. The next theorem formalizes our previous claim. Proposition 6 If V satis es A2 and A3, then there exists a supermodular rationalization P of V. The proof of this proposition follows by construction. That is, we construct a set of payo functions P = (U i : i 2 N) that satisfy the properties of a supermodular game with monotone best-replies and rationalize V. We elaborate next on this idea. Let us de ne, for all i 2 N, U i (a i ; a i ; i ) = X m j=1 (1=2) (a ij) 2 + X m j=1 ij (a i ; i ) a ij (3) with ij : A i T! R and a ij 2 R for all j m (so that a i 2 R m ): We next show that if C i is monotone, then we can always nd a set of increasing functions i = ( ij : i n; j m) such that (3) rationalizes C i : (If C i : T i Z m(n 1)! Z m, then we rede ne C i as the smallest or the largest monotone extension of the initial choice function to all R m(n 1).) 19

The rst-order condition for an interior maximizer is @U i (a i ; a i ; i ) =@a ij = a ij + ij (a i ; i ) = 0 for all j m: Since U i is strictly concave, this condition is also su cient. If this agent were utilitymaximizer, then C ij (a i ; i ) + ij (a i ; i ) = 0 for all j m where C ij is the jth coordinate of C i : Thus, by letting i (a i ; i ) = C i (a i ; i ), we get that P = (U i : i 2 N) rationalizes V. It is readily veri ed that U i is supermodular in a i. Since C i is increasing, then i is an increasing function. Thus, U i has increasing di erences in both (a i ; a i ) and (a i ; i ). It follows that P = (U i : i 2 N) is a supermodular rationalization of V. The functions s in our construction capture the strength of the interaction e ects. Moreover, we have that @U i (a i ; a i ; i ) =@a ij = a ij + ij (a i ; i ) increases in ij for all j m: Thus, U i has increasing di erences in (a i ; i). It follows, by Topkis theorem, that the maximizer of U i increases in i: Therefore, in our construction, the game that rationalizes U = (B i : i 2 N) has lower interaction e ects than the one that rationalizes W = (D i : i 2 N) : This observation leads to our last statement. The Sandwich Approach to the Supermodular Rationalization: If the empirical evidence satis es condition M, then we can always construct two extremal supermodular games that rationalize the data and di er regarding the strength of the interaction e ects. For any other consistent set of choice functions, the corresponding supermodular game will be sandwiched by the last two games. 5 Extensions of the Model and Remarks 5.1 Choice Correspondences Along the study we described the behavior of each agent by a choice function. We next propose an alternative set of conditions to show that we can still make out-of-sample predictions if we substitute choice functions by choice correspondences. 20

Let us suppose the behavior of agent i is described by the choice correspondence C i ( i ; a i ) : T i A i A i with C i ( i ; a i ) A i ( i ) where a i = (a j : j 2 N; j 6= i) and A i = j2n;j6=i A j. In this context, we need to adapt our solution concept as follows. De nition (Solution Concept): We say () = ( i () : i 2 N) is consistent with equilibrium behavior generated by if, for all i 2 N, i () 2 C i ( i ; a i ) with a i = j () : j 2 N; j 6= i : The extra di culty we face when we allow for correspondences is that observed choices are not enough to describe C i even for those arguments that satisfy i ; a i = m i ; am i for some m M: We next show that, with additional restrictions, this di culty can be overcome. To compare correspondences we will use the set order S that we de ne next. Let A and B be two sets. We write A S B if a b for any a 2 A and b 2 B: That is, if each element in A is larger than every element in B: The next two restrictions are the analogue to conditions A2 and A3. (A2 0 ) For all i 2 N, C i ( i ; a i ) S C i i ; a 0 i for all a i > a 0 i : (A3 0 ) For all i 2 N, C i ( i ; a i ) S C i ( 0 i ; a i) for all i > 0 i : These two conditions guarantee that any selection from C i is increasing in both i and a i : When the choice correspondences derive from an underlying game, A2 0 holds if U i is supermodular in a i and satis es the next condition. For all a i > a 0 i and a i > a 0 i, U i (a i ; a i ; i ) U i a 0 i; a i ; i > Ui a i ; a 0 i; i U i a 0 i; a 0 i; i : That is, if it has strict increasing di erences in (a i ; a i ). In addition, A3 0 is satis ed if, for all a i > a 0 i and i > 0 i, U i (a i ; a i ; i ) U i a 0 i; a i ; i > Ui a i ; a i ; 0 i U i a 0 i; a i ; 0 i : and assumption A1 holds. 21

Given A1, A2 0 and A3 0, any a i 2 C i ( i ; a i ) satis es a t i a i a m i whenever t i; a t i > i ; a i > m i ; a m i for some m; t 2 M: That is, we can still use the data to bound the choice function. The di erence with respect to our previous analysis is that in order to provide bounds for the choice correspondence evaluated at i ; a i we need information regarding two data points associated with pairs of treatments and choices of other agents that are strictly smaller and strictly larger than the argument we are interested in. It can be easily shown that Propositions 4 and 5 remain valid if we slightly modify the sharp bounds for C i, B i, and D i, as we show next. B 0 i ( i; a i ) = inf a i : a i 2 A i ( i ) ; a i sup a m i D 0 i ( i; a i ) = sup a i : a i 2 A i ( i ) ; a i inf a m i : m i ; am i < i; a i ; m M : m i ; am i > i; a i ; m M That is, if we change two of the weak inequalities by strict ones. 5.2 Identi cation of Choice Functions vs Equilibrium Points Manski (2010) clearly explains that identi cation of the choice functions by shape restrictions is quite di erent from identi cation of the equilibrium points. By using examples of models where the solution set is a singleton, he shows that the assumptions we need to impose on the primitives of the models to identify one or the other object can be quite di erent. We next explain why the issue is more delicate when the solution set has multiple elements. Our approach to identify solution sets relies on previous identi cation of the choice functions. Thus, in terms of Manski s discussion, the question is whether we can provide bounds for by imposing monotone conditions on V without (partially) identifying rst V = fc i : i 2 Ng : The answer to this question would be positive if, for instance, we were able to provide conditions on V so that S 0 for all 0 where S is de ned as in the previous subsection. If we were able to do so, then, for any 2, 22

sup fa : a 2 A () ; a inf fa m : m ; m Mgg inf fa : a 2 A () ; a sup fa m : m ; m Mgg : The problem with this approach is that, so far, there is no xed point theorem that, allowing for multiple solutions, provides conditions on the primitives so that S 0. In view of the result we provided in the last subsection, this negative statement highlights a key di erence between the MCS method for maximizers as compared to xed points. 5.3 Equilibrium Selection and Out-of-Sample Predictions Along the study, we obtained out-of-sample predictions without assuming any equilibrium selection rule. It is nevertheless interesting to emphasize that the equilibrium selection rule in the data-generating process will a ect the informativeness of our predictions. We illustrate this idea via a simple example. Example 4: Let N = f1; 2g, T 1 = T 2 = f; g (with ), and A i = fa i ; a i g (with a i a i ) for i = 1; 2: The next table describes the equilibrium set for the high treatment Equilibrium Set a 2 a 2 1 = ; 2 = a 1 a 1 Let us suppose the data was generated by equilibrium behavior and A2 and A3 hold. Moreover, let us assume rst that these agents always coordinate in the largest equilibrium (though the researcher does not know it). The problem we face is captured by the next tables Data 1 = ; 2 = a 1 a 1 a 2 a 2 Out-of-Sample Predictions a 2 a 2 1 = ; 2 = a 1 X X a 1 X X 23

That is, A1 and A2 are not informative in this case. Let us next suppose that these agents always coordinate in the smallest equilibrium (though the researcher does not know it). Now the situation is Data a 2 a 2 1 = ; 2 = a 1 a 1 Out-of-Sample Predictions a 2 a 2 1 = ; 2 = a 1 X x a 1 x X Under this alternative equilibrium selection rule our prediction is more informative. We hypothesize that, with more data points, a stochastic equilibrium selection rule would lead, on average, to smaller bounds as compared to extremal selections. The reason is that a stochastic equilibrium selection rule would generate more variation in the selected action pro les and this would allow us to track individual choice functions more precisely. 6 Conclusion Monotone comparative statics (MCS) has proved extremely useful in economic theory due to the wide variety of models where this method allows us to compare equilibrium points. This paper shows that this method for comparative statics can be equally valuable for the nonparametric analysis of simultaneous choice models, e.g., supermodular games. The primitives of our model are a system of interdependent choice functions. When they arise from an underlying game, they constitute the best-reply functions of the various players. We show that, while the standard implications of the MCS method for games may be neither testable nor useful for counterfactual predictions with partial observability of equilibrium points, its underlying assumptions are yet quite informative. Speci cally, they allow us to partially identify the set of choice functions from observed behavior. We then propose an alternative use of the MCS method that translates the latter into bounds for counterfactual prediction of equilibrium behavior. We refer to this method as the sandwich approach to the out-of-sample predictions. We nally show that if the data satis es certain monotone restrictions, then the empirical evidence can be always rationalized as the Nash equilibria of 24

a supermodular game. We illustrate all our ideas with an IO model of demand with network e ects. 25

7 Proofs Proof of Proposition 1: Let us consider a mapping M : i2n A i! i2n A i, de ned as follows M (a 1 ; a 2 ; :::; a n ) = (C 1 ( 1 ; a 1 ) ; C 2 ( 2 ; a 2 ) ; :::; C n ( n ; a n )). Function M maps n-dimensional actions into itself. Given our solution concept, the set of xed point of M coincides with : Thus, the proof of Proposition 1 reduces to show that the set of xed points of M is a non-empty complete lattice. Any compact interval of R m or Z m is a complete lattice. It is well-known that if a product lattice is a product of all complete lattices, then it is itself complete. Thus, i2n A i is a complete lattice. Under A2, M is increasing. The result follows by Tarskis 0 xed point theorem (see Tarski (1955)). Proof of Proposition 2: Under A3, we have that, for all 0, M (a 1 ; a 2 ; :::; a n ) M 0 (a 1 ; a 2 ; :::; a n ) where M and M 0 are de ned as in the proof of Proposition 1. Under A1, they map complete lattices into themselves. Under A2, M and M 0 Topkis (1998, Corollary 2.5.2). are increasing. Thus, the result follows by Proof of Proposition 3: Let us consider two mapping L and N from i2n A i into itself, de ned as follows L (a 1 ; a 2 ; :::; a n ) = (B i ( i ; a i ) : i 2 N) and N (a 1 ; a 2 ; :::; a n ) = (D i ( i ; a i ) : i 2 N). Under A4, we have that N (a 1 ; a 2 ; :::; a n ) M (a 1 ; a 2 ; :::; a n ) L (a 1 ; a 2 ; :::; a n ) where M is de ned as in the proof of Proposition 1. By our argument in the proof of Proposition 2, they map complete lattices into themselves. Under A2, the three mappings are increasing. Thus, the result follows by Topkis (1998, Corollary 2.5.2). Proof of Proposition 4: Under IA, we get that: B i m i ; a m i = Di m i ; a m i = a m for all m M: 26