Exponentiable functors between quantaloid-enriched categories

Similar documents
CATEGORICAL STRUCTURES ENRICHED IN A QUANTALOID: TENSORED AND COTENSORED CATEGORIES

Exponentiation in V-categories

FROM LAX MONAD EXTENSIONS TO TOPOLOGICAL THEORIES

Span, Cospan, and Other Double Categories

arxiv:math/ v1 [math.ct] 16 Nov 2004

ON EXTENSIONS OF LAX MONADS

SYMMETRY AND CAUCHY COMPLETION OF QUANTALOID-ENRICHED CATEGORIES

LAX DISTRIBUTIVE LAWS FOR TOPOLOGY, II

Categories and Modules

Topological Groupoids and Exponentiability

An algebraic description of regular epimorphisms in topology

ON SOME SPECIAL CLASSES OF CONTINUOUS MAPS

FROM LAX MONAD EXTENSIONS TO TOPOLOGICAL THEORIES MARIA MANUEL CLEMENTINO AND WALTER THOLEN. To Manuela, teacher and friend

State Transitions as Morphisms for Complete Lattices

ON EXTENSIONS OF LAX MONADS Dedicated to Aurelio Carboni on the occasion of his sixtieth birthday

A NOTE ON ENRICHED CATEGORIES

CATEGORIES ENRICHED OVER A QUANTALOID: ISBELL ADJUNCTIONS AND KAN ADJUNCTIONS

Cellularity, composition, and morphisms of algebraic weak factorization systems

CATEGORIES ENRICHED OVER A QUANTALOID: ISBELL ADJUNCTIONS AND KAN ADJUNCTIONS

Ordered Topological Structures

EXTENSIONS IN THE THEORY OF LAX ALGEBRAS Dedicated to Walter Tholen on the occasion of his 60th birthday

1. Introduction and preliminaries

Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic

CAHIERS DE TOPOLOGIE ET Vol. LI-2 (2010) GEOMETRIE DIFFERENTIELLE CATEGORIQUES ON ON REGULAR AND HOMOLOGICAL CLOSURE OPERATORS by Maria Manuel CLEMENT

Extensions in the theory of lax algebras

Category Theory. Travis Dirle. December 12, 2017

Lecture 9: Sheaves. February 11, 2018

PART II.1. IND-COHERENT SHEAVES ON SCHEMES

PART I. Abstract algebraic categories

Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic

ON SOME BASIC CONSTRUCTIONS IN CATEGORIES OF QUANTALE-VALUED SUP-LATTICES. 1. Introduction

ON THE HOMOTOPY THEORY OF ENRICHED CATEGORIES

Topological K-theory, Lecture 3

Some glances at topos theory. Francis Borceux

ON THE CATEGORICAL MEANING OF HAUSDORFF AND GROMOV DISTANCES, I

Journal of Pure and Applied Algebra

Notes about Filters. Samuel Mimram. December 6, 2012

UNIVERSAL DERIVED EQUIVALENCES OF POSETS

An introduction to quantaloid-enriched categories

Elements of Category Theory

Analysis and Enriched Category Theory

Topos Theory. Lectures 21 and 22: Classifying toposes. Olivia Caramello. Topos Theory. Olivia Caramello. The notion of classifying topos

University of Oxford, Michaelis November 16, Categorical Semantics and Topos Theory Homotopy type theor

On quantaloid-enriched categories in general, and sheaves on a quantaloid in particular

Coreflections in Algebraic Quantum Logic

CONTINUITY. 1. Continuity 1.1. Preserving limits and colimits. Suppose that F : J C and R: C D are functors. Consider the limit diagrams.

A brief Introduction to Category Theory

Embedding locales and formal topologies into positive topologies

TWO-SIDED DISCRETE FIBRATIONS IN 2-CATEGORIES AND BICATEGORIES

Enriched Categories. Stephen Fitz

arxiv: v2 [math.ct] 5 May 2009

Review of category theory

1 The Hyland-Schalke functor G Rel. 2 Weakenings

Cartesian Closed Topological Categories and Tensor Products

Quantale-valued Topological Spaces via Closure and Convergence

Semantics for algebraic operations

ON THE COFIBRANT GENERATION OF MODEL CATEGORIES arxiv: v1 [math.at] 16 Jul 2009

Applications of 2-categorical algebra to the theory of operads. Mark Weber

Locally cartesian closed categories

What s category theory, anyway? Dedicated to the memory of Dietmar Schumacher ( )

Category Theory. Categories. Definition.

Adjunctions! Everywhere!

CLOSURE, INTERIOR AND NEIGHBOURHOOD IN A CATEGORY

Enriched and internal categories: an extensive relationship

via Topos Theory Olivia Caramello University of Cambridge The unification of Mathematics via Topos Theory Olivia Caramello

Topos Theory. Lectures 17-20: The interpretation of logic in categories. Olivia Caramello. Topos Theory. Olivia Caramello.

Injective objects and lax idempotent monads

A representation theorem for quantale valued sup-algebras

MORITA EQUIVALENCE OF MANY-SORTED ALGEBRAIC THEORIES

Derived Algebraic Geometry I: Stable -Categories

SPAN, COSPAN, AND OTHER DOUBLE CATEGORIES

ON THE HOMOTOPY THEORY OF ENRICHED CATEGORIES

ON THE UNIFORMIZATION OF L-VALUED FRAMES

CATEGORY THEORY. Cats have been around for 70 years. Eilenberg + Mac Lane =. Cats are about building bridges between different parts of maths.

ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY COURSE NOTES, LECTURE 9: SCHEMES AND THEIR MODULES.

A Grothendieck site is a small category C equipped with a Grothendieck topology T. A Grothendieck topology T consists of a collection of subfunctors

A NEW SET THEORY FOR ANALYSIS

A Fibrational View of Geometric Morphisms

Derived Algebraic Geometry IX: Closed Immersions

SJÄLVSTÄNDIGA ARBETEN I MATEMATIK

Categorical models of homotopy type theory

Exponentiability in categories of lax algebras

Assume the left square is a pushout. Then the right square is a pushout if and only if the big rectangle is.

arxiv: v2 [math.ct] 27 Dec 2014

INTRODUCTION TO PART V: CATEGORIES OF CORRESPONDENCES

Localizations as idempotent approximations to completions

Limit Preservation from Naturality

What are Iteration Theories?

Model Structures on the Category of Small Double Categories

The tensor product of commutative monoids

On some properties of T 0 ordered reflection

Maps and Monads for Modal Frames

2. ETALE GROUPOIDS MARK V. LAWSON

arxiv: v1 [math.ct] 28 Dec 2018

Boolean Algebras, Boolean Rings and Stone s Representation Theorem

arxiv: v1 [math.ct] 10 Jul 2016

PART III.3. IND-COHERENT SHEAVES ON IND-INF-SCHEMES

On injective constructions of S-semigroups. Jan Paseka Masaryk University

Higher Order Containers

CHANGE OF BASE, CAUCHY COMPLETENESS AND REVERSIBILITY

Transcription:

Exponentiable functors between quantaloid-enriched categories Maria Manuel Clementino, Dirk Hofmann and Isar Stubbe July 3, 2007 Abstract. Exponentiable functors between quantaloid-enriched categories are characterized in elementary terms. The proof goes as follows: the elementary conditions on a given functor translate into existence statements for certain adjoints that obey some lax commutativity; this, in turn, is precisely what is needed to prove the existence of partial products with that functor; so that the functor s exponentiability follows from the works of Niefield [1982] and Dyckhoff and Tholen [1987]. Keywords: quantaloid, enriched category, exponentiability, partial product. MSC 2000 Classification: 06F07, 18A22, 18D05, 18D20 1. Introduction The study of exponentiable morphisms in a category C, in particular of exponentiable functors between (small) categories (i.e. Conduché fibrations), has a long history; see [Niefield, 2001] for a short account. Recently M. M. Clementino and D. Hofmann [2006] found simple necessary-and-sufficient conditions for the exponentiability of a functor between V-enriched categories, where V is a symmetric quantale which has its top element as unit for its multiplication and whose underlying sup-lattice is a locale. Our aim here is to prove the following characterization of the exponentiable functors between Q-enriched categories, where now Q is any (small) quantaloid, thus considerably generalizing the aforementioned result of [Clementino and Hofmann, 2006]. Centro de Matemática, Universidade de Coimbra, Portugal. Email: mmc@mat.uc.pt Departamento de Matemática, Universidade de Aveiro, Portugal. Email: dirk@mat.ua.pt Postdoctoral Fellow of the Research Foundation Flanders (FWO), Department of Mathematics and Computer Science, University of Antwerp, Belgium. Email: isar.stubbe@ua.ac.be First complete version written on August 17, 2006; submitted to Applied Categorical Structures on October 27, 2006; accepted for publication on March 30, 2007; revised on July 3, 2007. 1

Theorem 1.1 A functor F : A i.e. the functor product with F B between Q-enriched categories is exponentiable, F : Cat(Q)/B Cat(Q)/B admits a right adjoint, if and only if the following two conditions hold: 1. for every a, a A and i f i B(F a, F a), ( ) f i A(a, a) = ( ) f i A(a, a), i i 2. for every a, a A, b B, f B(b, F a) and g B(F a, b ), (g f) A(a, a) = ( ) (g A(a, a )) (f A(a, a)). a F 1 b These conditions are elementary in the sense that they are simply equalities (of infima, suprema and compositions) of morphisms in the base quantaloid Q. The second condition is precisely what [Clementino and Hofmann, 2006] had too, albeit in their more restrictive setting; but they did not discover the first condition an sich: because it is obviously always true if the base category is a locale. The proof of our theorem goes as follows. In section 3 we first translate conditions 1.1 1 and 1.1 2 into existence statements for certain adjoints obeying some lax commutativity. Next, in section 4, we show that these latter adjoints are precisely what is needed to prove the existence of partial products in Cat(Q) over F : A B. The result then follows from R. Dyckhoff and W. Tholen s [1987] observation, complementary to S. Niefield s [1982] work, that a morphism f: A B in a category C with finite limits is exponentiable if and only if C admits partial products over f. Acknowledgement. This work was done when Isar Stubbe was a post-doctoral researcher at the Centre for Mathematics of the University of Coimbra. 2. Preliminaries For the basics on Q-enriched categories we refer to [Stubbe, 2005]; all our notations are as in that paper. Here we shall just observe that Cat(Q) has pullbacks and a terminal object and therefore all finite limits [Borceux, 1994, Proposition 2.8.2] and fix some notations. The terminal object in Cat(Q), write it as T, has: - objects: T 0 = Q 0, with types tx = X, - hom-arrows: T(Y, X) = X,Y = the top element of Q(X, Y ). For two functors F : A C and G: B C with common codomain, their pullback A C B has: 2

- objects: (A C B) 0 = {(a, b) A 0 B 0 ) F a = Gb} with t(a, b) = ta = tb, - hom-arrows: (A C B)((a, b ), (a, b)) = A(a, a) B(b, b), and comes with the obvious projections. All verifications are entirely straightforward. For an X Q, the one-object Q-category with hom-arrow 1 X is written as X. There is an obvious bijection between the objects of type X in some Q-category B and the functors from X to B. Thus, let [b]: tb B stand for the functor pointing at b B. Given a functor F : A B and an object b B in its codomain, we shall write A b for the pullback A b A That is to say, A b has tb [b] B F - objects: (A b ) 0 = F 1 b = {a A b = F a}, all of type tb, - hom-arrows: A b (a, a) = 1 tb A(a, a). Note that A b = if and only if b F (A). 3. Adjoints obeying a lax commutativity In this section we shall translate the elementary conditions in 1.1 into existence statements of certain adjoints obeying some lax commutative diagrams. B between Q-categories, the following are equiv- Lemma 3.1 For a functor F : A alent conditions: 1. condition 1.1 1 holds, 2. for every a, a A, the order-preserving map B(F a, F a) Q(ta, ta ): f f A(a, a) (1) has a right adjoint, 3. for every b, b F (A), the order-preserving map ( ) B(b, b) Matr(Q)(A b, A b ): f f A(a, a) (a,a ) A b A b (2) has a right adjoint. 3

4. for every b, b F (A), the order-preserving map ( ) B(b, b) Dist(Q)(A b, A b ): f f A(a, a) (a,a ) A b A b (3) has a right adjoint. 5. for every b, b B, the order-preserving map in (3) has a right adjoint. Proof : The equivalence of the first two statements is trivial: an order-preserving map between complete lattices has a right adjoint if and only if it preserves arbitrary suprema. Next, if we use g g F as generic notation for the right adjoints to the maps in (2), then M M F := {M(a, a) F (a, a ) A b A b } is the right adjoint to the map in (3). Conversely, if M M F is the right adjoint to the map in (3), then for any a, a A g g F := ( ) F T (a,a ) (g) is the right adjoint to the map in (2), with T (a,a ) (g) standing for the Q-matrix from A F a to A F a all of whose elements are set to the top element in Q(ta, ta ) except for the element indexed by (a, a ) which is set to g. The equivalence of 3 and 4 follows straightforwardly from two facts: First, the matrix ( ) f := f A(a, a) a A b,a A b is always a distributor from A b to A b : because for any a, a 1 A b and a, a 1 A b it is automatic that ( ) ( ) f(a, a 1 ) A b (a 1, a) = f A(a, a 1 ) 1 ta A(a 1, a) ) ( ) (f 1 ta A(a, a 1 ) A(a 1, a) f A(a, a) = f(a, a) and similarly A b (a 1, a ) f(a, a) f(a, a). And second, the inclusion Dist(Q)(A b, A b ) Matr(Q)(A b, A b ): Φ Φ has both a left and a right adjoint; namely, its left adjoint is M A b M A b and its right adjoint is M [A b, {A b, M}]. (In both expressions, A b and A b are viewed as monads in the quantaloid Matr(Q), and we compute composition, resp. 4

lifting and extension, of matrices.) Hence both triangles in B(b, b) f f f f Φ Φ Matr(Q)(A b, A b ) Dist(Q)(A b, A b ) M A b M A b commute and both solid arrows are left adjoints, so it follows that one dashed arrow is a left adjoint if and only if the other one is. Finally, the only difference between the fourth and the fifth statement is that in the latter it may be that A b or A b is empty; but then Dist(Q)(A b, A b ) is a singleton (containing the empty distributor) in which case the right adjoint to (3) always exists. In the statement of the next lemma we shall write B(b, b) f f Dist(Q)(A b, A b ) (4) Φ F Φ for the adjunctions (one for each pair (b, b ) of objects of B) that 3.1 5 alludes to. Lemma 3.2 For a functor F : A B between Q-categories for which the equivalent conditions in 3.1 hold, the following are equivalent conditions: 1. condition 1.1 2 holds, 2. for every a, a A and b B, the diagram Dist(Q)( ta, A b ) Dist(Q)(A b, ta ) Dist(Q)( ta, ta ) Q(ta, ta ) (5) B(b, F a) B(F a, b ) B(F a, F a) in which the horizontal arrows are given by composition (in Dist(Q), resp. Q), the left vertical arrow is ( (f (f, g) A(a, a) ) a, ( g A(a, a ) ) ) (6) Ab a Ab and the right vertical arrow is as in (1), is lax commutative as indicated, 5

3. for every b, b F (A) and b B, the diagram Dist(Q)(A b, A b ) Dist(Q)(A b, A b ) Dist(Q)(A b, A b ) ( ) ( ) ( ) (7) B(b, b) B(b, b ) is lax commutative as indicated, B(b, b) 4. for every b, b, b B, the diagram in (7) is lax commutative as indicated, 5. for every b, b, b B, the diagram Dist(Q)(A b, A b ) Dist(Q)(A b, A b ) Dist(Q)(A b, A b ) ( ) F ( ) F B(b, b) B(b, b ) ( ) F (8) B(b, b) is lax commutative as indicated. Proof : First it is easily verified, in an analogous manner as in the previous proof, that the map in (6) is well-defined, i.e. that we indeed defined distributors ( f A(a, a) ) a A b, resp. ( g A(a, a ) ) a A b from ta to A b, resp. from A b to ta. Now the equivalence of the first two statements is immediate; the oplax commutativity of the diagram in (5) is always true, thus explaining why in 1.1 2 there is an equality instead of an inequality. That the second and the third statement are equivalent, is because all order-theoretic operations on a distributor are done elementwise ; and the third and fourth are equivalent because in case A b or A b is empty, Dist(Q)(A b, A b ) is a singleton, hence all is trivial. Finally, the equivalence of the two last statements follows from the respective vertical arrows being adjoint. 4. Partial products In this section we link the conditions in 3.1 and 3.2 on a functor F : A B to the existence of so-called partial products in Cat(Q) with F : this completes the proof of 1.1. First recall R. Dyckhoff and W. Tholen s [1987] definition (which they gave for any morphism f: A B and any object C in any category C with finite limits, but 6

here it is for Q-categories): the partial product of a functor F : A B with a Q- category C is a Q-category P together with functors P : P B, E: P B A C such that, for any other Q-category P and functors P : P B, E : P B A C there exists a unique functor K: P P satisfying P K = P and E (K B 1 A ) = E. The following diagram illustrates this definition: E C P B A A K B 1 A E P B A F P P B K P P (9) This is really just the explicit description of the coreflection of C along the functor pullback with F B A: Cat(Q)/B Cat(Q). Hence Cat(Q) admits all partial products with F : A B if and only if this functor has a right adjoint. S. Niefield [1982] proved that this in turn is equivalent to the functor product with F F : Cat(Q)/B Cat(Q)/B having a right adjoint, i.e. to the exponentiability of F. Suppose now that F : A B and C are given, and that we want to construct their partial product (P, P, E). Putting P = X in the diagram in (9) and letting X range over all objects of Q, the universal property of the partial product dictates at once what the object-set P 0 and the object-maps P : P 0 C 0 and E: (P B A) 0 C 0 must be: - P 0 = {(b, H) b B and H: A b C is a functor}, with types t(b, H) = tb, - for (b, H) P 0, P (b, H) = b, - for ((b, H), a) (P B A) 0, E((b, H), a) = Ha. Thus we are left to find a Q-enrichment of the object-set P 0, making it a Q-category P and making P and E functors with the required universal property; the next lemma tells us how to do this. Lemma 4.1 If F : A B satisfies 3.1 5 and 3.2 5, then Cat(Q) admits partial products over F : A B. 7

Proof : Assuming 3.1 5 it makes sense to define P((b, H ), (b, H)) := C(H, H ) F Whereas the identity inequality = the outcome of applying the right adjoint to the map in (3) on the distributor C(H, H ): A b A b. 1 t(b,h) P((b, H), (b, H)) reduces to the fact that H: A b C is a functor, it is the assumed 3.2 5 together with the composition inequality in the Q-category C that assures the composition inequality: P((b, H ), (b, H )) P((b, H ), (b, H)) P((b, H ), (b, H)). This construction clearly makes P and E functorial. As for the universal property of (P, P, E), given a Q-category P and functors P : P B and E : P B A C, it is straightforward to verify that K: P P: x K(x) := is the required unique factorization. ( P x, E (x, ): A P x Finally we shall show that conditions 3.1 5 and 3.2 5 are not only sufficient but also necessary for Cat(Q) to admit partial products over F : A B. Thereto we shall use an auxiliary construction concerning distributors between Q-categories that we better recall beforehand: given a distributor Φ: X Y, we shall say that a co-span of functors like X S C T Y represents Φ when Φ = C(T, S ). Any Φ admits at least one such representing cospan: let C 0 = X 0 Y 0 and for all a, a X 0 and b, b Y 0 put C(a, a) = X(a, a), C(b, b) = Y(b, b), C(b, a) = Φ(b, a), C(a, b) = 0 tb,ta, so that the co-span of full embeddings X SX C S Y Y surely represents Φ. (This latter co-span is universal amongst all representing cospans for Φ; M. Grandis and R. Paré [1999] speak, in the context of double colimits in double categories, of the cotabulator (or gluing, or collage) of Φ. This is however not important for us here; on the contrary, further on it is crucial to consider nonuniversal representing co-spans.) Lemma 4.2 If Cat(Q) admits partial products over F : A B, then F : A B satisfies 3.1 5 and 3.2 5. ) C 8

Proof : For b, b B and Φ: A b A b, choose a representing co-span S A b C T A b. Considering the partial product of F with C, say (P, P, E), it is a fact that the hom-arrow P((b, T ), (b, S)) is a Q-arrow smaller than B(b, b). We may thus define a map Dist(Q)(A b, A b ) B(b, b): Φ Φ F := P((b, T ), (b, S)). (10) Now let X = tb and Y = tb, and f: X a Q-category 1 P f like so: Y an arrow in Q; the latter determines - objects: (P f ) 0 = {X} {Y } with tx = X Q and ty = Y Q, - hom-arrows: P f (Y, X) = f, P f (X, X) = 1 X, P f (Y, Y ) = 1 Y and P f (X, Y ) = 0 Y,X. The inequality f B(b, b) holds if and only if P f : P f B: X b, Y b is a functor; and similarly the collection of inequalities f A(a, a) Φ(a, a) (one for each a A b, a A b ) is equivalent to E f : P f B A C: (X, a) a, (Y, a ) a being a functor. Using the universal property of the partial product (P, P, E) one easily checks that P f and E f determine and are determined by the single functor K: P f P: X (b, S), Y (b, T ), whose functoriality in turn is equivalent to the inequality f P((b, T ), (b, S)). This proves that the map in (10) is the right adjoint in (4). We end by showing that the map in (10) satisfies the lax commutativity of the diagram in (8); thereto it is important that in the map prescription, by uniqueness of adjoints, any chosen representing co-span for a given distributor will do. For b, b, b B, Φ: A b A b and Ψ: A b A b, consider the Q-category C like so: - objects: C 0 = (A b ) 0 (A b ) 0 (A b ) 0 with inherited types, - hom-arrows: for all a, a 1 A b, a, a 1 A b and a, a 1 A b, put C(a 1, a) = A b (a 1, a), C(a 1, a ) = A b (a 1, a ), C(a 1, a ) = A b (a 1, a ), C(a, a) = Φ(a, a), C(a, a ) = Ψ(a, a ) and C(a, a) = (Ψ Φ)(a, a), all other hom-arrows are zero. 1 This is actually an instance of the universal representing co-span, when viewing the Q-arrow f: X Y as a one-element distributor (f): X Y between one-object Q-categories. 9

The co-spans of full embeddings S A b C T A b, A b T C U S A b, A b U C A b represent respectively Φ, Ψ and Ψ Φ. Writing (P, P, E) for the partial product of F and C, the compostion-inequality P((b, U), (b, T )) P((b, T ), (b, S)) P((b, U), (b, S)) says precisely that Ψ F Φ F (Ψ Φ) F, as wanted. 5. Applications, examples A Q-category A is an exponentiable object of Cat(Q) precisely when the unique functor A T: a ta is an exponentible morphism of Cat(Q); 1.1 tells us that this is the case if and only if - for all a, a A, A(a, a) is exponentiable in Q(ta, ta ), - for all a, a A and f: ta Y, g: Y ta in Q, (g f) A(a, a) = { (g A(a, a )) (f A(a, a)) a A, ta = Y }. An interesting necessary condition for A s exponentiability can be obtained upon letting f = ta,y and g = Y,ta be the top elements of, respectively, Q(ta, Y ) and Q(Y, ta ): - for all a, a A and Y Q, ( Y,ta ta,y ) A(a, a) = { A(a, a ) A(a, a) a A, ta = Y }. (11) If the base quantaloid Q is such that (i) each hom-suplattice is a locale, and (ii) for any arrows A the interchange law (g f) (k h) = (g k) (f h) holds, then the necessary condition (11) for A s exponentiability is also sufficient. f h Example 5.1 In case of a one-object quantaloid Q satisfying conditions (i ii) above, every Q-enriched category is exponentiable, because (11) becomes A(a, a) = A(a, a ) A(a, a) a A 10 B g k C

which is automatic. This is in particular true for the one-object suspension of a locale (and a fortiori for the one-object suspension of the two-element Boolean algebra, as is well-known: every ordered set is exponentiable). Example 5.2 So-called free quantaloids [Rosenthal, 1991] satisfy conditions (i ii) above: by definition, the free quantaloid PC on a (small) category C has the same objects as C, the hom-suplattice PC(X, Y ) is the powerset P(C(X, Y )), composition in PC is done elementwise and the identity on an object X is {1 X }. (This construction is free in that it provides a left adjoint to the forgetful functor from quantaloids to categories.) Categories enriched in a free quantaloid have been linked with automata theory and process semantics in [Betti, 1980] (but see [Rosenthal, 1995] for an overview of further developments). More precisely, let A be a PCenriched category; then the objects of A are the (typed) states of a automaton, and the arrows of C are its (typed) labels or processes. To have an f A(a, a) is then read as having a process f to produce a from a ; often this is denoted as f: a a. The exponentiability condition (11) for A can now be rephrased as: - for any states a and a and type Y C, if f: a a and f = h g with cod(g) = Y = dom(h) in C, then there is a state a of type Y together with p: a a, q: a a such that f = q p. In words, if f: a a factors in C over some object Y, then it factors in the automaton over some state of type Y (but it is not necessarily the same factorization). This statement is trivial when C is a one-object category (as already attested in 5.1), i.e. in the case of an untyped automaton; we do not know what rôle it has to play in typed automata theory or process semantics. For a detailed treatment of generalized metric spaces and non-expansive maps (categories and functors enriched over the quantale of positive real numbers) we refer to [Clementino and Hofmann, 2006]. This example is quite different from the ones given above: the quantale of positive real numbers does not satisfy the interchange law (even though its underlying suplattice is a locale). References [1] [Renato Betti, 1980] Automata and closed categories, Boll. Un. Mat. Ital. B Serie V 17, pp. 44 58. [2] [Francis Borceux, 1994] Handbook of Categorical Algebra I, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. [3] [Maria Manuel Clementino and Dirk Hofmann, 2006] Exponentiation in V- categories, Topology Appl. 153, pp. 3113 3128. 11

[4] [Roy Dyckhoff and Walter Tholen, 1987] Exponentiable morphisms, partial products and pullback complements, J. Pure Appl. Algebra 49, pp. 103 116. [5] [Marco Grandis and Robert Paré, 1999] Limits in double categories, Cahiers Topologie Géom. Différentielle Catég. 40, pp. 162 220. [6] [Susan Niefield, 1982] Cartesianness: topological spaces, uniform spaces and affine schemes, J. Pure Appl. Algebra 23, pp. 147 167. [7] [Susan Niefield, 2001] Exponentiable morphisms: posets, spaces, locales, and Grothendieck toposes, Theory Appl. Categories 8, pp. 16 32. [8] [Kimmo I. Rosenthal, 1991] Free quantaloids, J. Pure Appl. Algebra 72, pp. 67 82. [9] [Kimmo I. Rosenthal, 1995] Quantaloids, enriched categories and automata theory, Appl. Categ. Structures 3, pp. 279 301. [10] [Isar Stubbe, 2005] Categorical structures enriched in a quantaloid: categories, distributors, functors, Theory Appl. Categories 14, pp. 1 45 12