Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved.

Similar documents
2 RENATA GRUNBERG A. PRADO AND FRANKLIN D. TALL 1 We thank the referee for a number of useful comments. We need the following result: Theorem 0.1. [2]

A NEW LINDELOF SPACE WITH POINTS G δ

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved.

MORE ABOUT SPACES WITH A SMALL DIAGONAL

DENSELY k-separable COMPACTA ARE DENSELY SEPARABLE

A NOTE ON THE EIGHTFOLD WAY

The Arkhangel skiĭ Tall problem under Martin s Axiom

Tallness and Level by Level Equivalence and Inequivalence

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved.

Successive cardinals with the tree property

Lindelöf spaces which are Menger, Hurewicz, Alster, productive, or D

The Ultrapower Axiom implies GCH above a supercompact cardinal

A CHARACTERIZATION OF POWER HOMOGENEITY G. J. RIDDERBOS

Productively Lindelöf spaces may all be D

arxiv:math/ v1 [math.gn] 28 Mar 2007

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved.

PFA(S)[S] and the Arhangel skiĭ-tall Problem

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved.

K. Kunen and F. D. Tall: joint papers

MONOTONICALLY COMPACT AND MONOTONICALLY

FORCING AXIOMS AND THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS, PART II: TRANSCENDING ω 1 -SEQUENCES OF REAL NUMBERS

CARDINAL RESTRICTIONS ON SOME HOMOGENEOUS COMPACTA. István Juhász*, Peter Nyikos**, and Zoltán Szentmiklóssy*

EXTERNAL AUTOMORPHISMS OF ULTRAPRODUCTS OF FINITE MODELS


FORCING WITH SEQUENCES OF MODELS OF TWO TYPES

FINITE BOREL MEASURES ON SPACES OF CARDINALITY LESS THAN c

GO-SPACES AND NOETHERIAN SPECTRA

Singular Failures of GCH and Level by Level Equivalence

SOME REMARKS ON NON-SPECIAL COHERENT ARONSZAJN TREES

arxiv: v1 [math.gn] 2 Jul 2016

that is used in this paper follows [E]. We also use the powerful method of elementary submodels which is well-presented in [JuW] chapter Topolo

THE STRONG TREE PROPERTY AND THE FAILURE OF SCH

LOCALLY COMPACT PERFECTLY NORMAL SPACES MAY ALL BE PARACOMPACT. Paul Larson and Franklin D. Tall 1

COMPLETE NORMALITY AND COUNTABLE COMPACTNESS

Ultrafilters with property (s)

GREGORY TREES, THE CONTINUUM, AND MARTIN S AXIOM

On Σ-Ponomarev-systems

COLLAPSING FUNCTIONS

The ideal of Sierpiński-Zygmund sets on the plane

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved.

ITERATIONS WITH MIXED SUPPORT

Aronszajn Compacta. July 1, 2008

SET MAPPING REFLECTION

SINGULAR COFINALITY CONJECTURE AND A QUESTION OF GORELIC. 1. introduction

Independence of Boolean algebras and forcing

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved.

CH AND THE MOORE-MROWKA PROBLEM

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved.

Jónsson Properties for Non-Ordinal Sets Under the Axiom of Determinacy

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved.

Generalizing Gödel s Constructible Universe:

Extremely large cardinals in the absence of Choice

NON-EXISTENCE OF UNIVERSAL SPACES FOR SOME STRATIFIABLE SPACES

with the topology generated by all boxes that are determined by countably many coordinates. Then G is a topological group,

Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras

Forcing notions in inner models

APPLICATIONS OF ANOTHER CHARACTERIZATION OF βn \ N

Large Cardinals and Higher Degree Theory

Covering a bounded set of functions by an increasing chain of slaloms

Locally Connected HS/HL Compacta

COUNTABLE COMPACTNESS, HEREDITARY π CHARACTER, AND THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS

A variant of Namba Forcing

Scales, topological reflections, and large cardinal issues by Peter Nyikos

SOME CALKIN ALGEBRAS HAVE OUTER AUTOMORPHISMS

CERTAIN WEAKLY GENERATED NONCOMPACT, PSEUDO-COMPACT TOPOLOGIES ON TYCHONOFF CUBES. Leonard R. Rubin University of Oklahoma, USA

UNIVERSALLY BAIRE SETS AND GENERIC ABSOLUTENESS TREVOR M. WILSON

ON ALMOST COUNTABLY COMPACT SPACES. Yankui Song and Hongying Zhao. 1. Introduction

The Proper Forcing Axiom: a tutorial

REALCOMPACTNESS IN MAXIMAL AND SUBMAXIMAL SPACES.

M ath. Res. Lett. 15 (2008), no. 00, NN c International Press 2008 A UNIVERSAL ARONSZAJN LINE. Justin Tatch Moore. 1.

THE LENGTH OF THE FULL HIERARCHY OF NORMS

ITERATING ALONG A PRIKRY SEQUENCE

How does universality of coproducts depend on the cardinality?

Löwenheim-Skolem Theorems, Countable Approximations, and L ω. David W. Kueker (Lecture Notes, Fall 2007)

Katětov and Katětov-Blass orders on F σ -ideals

Topological Problems for Set Theorists, II

Topological Games and Covering Dimension

The Vaught Conjecture Do uncountable models count?

SMALL SUBSETS OF THE REALS AND TREE FORCING NOTIONS

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved.

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved.

Chain Conditions of Horn and Tarski

SELF-DUAL UNIFORM MATROIDS ON INFINITE SETS

Topological homogeneity and infinite powers

The topology of ultrafilters as subspaces of 2 ω

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved.

HEREDITARILY NORMAL MANIFOLDS OF DIMENSION > 1 MAY ALL BE METRIZABLE

COUNTABLY S-CLOSED SPACES

BOUNDING THE CONSISTENCY STRENGTH OF A FIVE ELEMENT LINEAR BASIS

TRANSFERING SATURATION, THE FINITE COVER PROPERTY, AND STABILITY

j-3 Consistency Results in Topology, II: Forcing and Large Cardinals

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved.

FAR POINTS AND DISCRETELY GENERATED SPACES

A DIRECT PROOF OF THE FIVE ELEMENT BASIS THEOREM

AMS regional meeting Bloomington, IN April 1, 2017

NAMBA FORCING, WEAK APPROXIMATION, AND GUESSING

Slow P -point Ultrafilters

arxiv: v1 [math.gn] 9 Jul 2017

Diagonalize This. Iian Smythe. Department of Mathematics Cornell University. Olivetti Club November 26, 2013

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved.

Transcription:

Topology Proceedings Web: http://topology.auburn.edu/tp/ Mail: Topology Proceedings Department of Mathematics & Statistics Auburn University, Alabama 36849, USA E-mail: topolog@auburn.edu ISSN: 0146-4124 COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved.

TOPOLOGY PROCEEDINGS Volume 25, Summer 2000 Pages 345 350 REFLECTING ON COMPACT SPACES Franklin D. Tall Abstract We consider whether, if a topological space reflects via an elementary submodel to a generalized Cantor discontinuum it must in fact equal its reflection. The answers involve large cardinals. Given an elementary submodel M of some H(θ) (see [JW, Chapter 24] for a careful elucidation of the implications of this) and a topological space X, T M, we define X M to be X M with topology generated by T M = {U M : U T M}. In [JT 1 ] we developed this notion; in [T 1 ] I proved that if X M is homeomorphic to the Cantor set, then X = X M. I. Juhász (personal communication) asked whether this generalized to arbitrary cardinals, i.e. if X M is homeomorphic to a generalized Cantor discontinuum D λ, where D is the 2-point discrete space, then does X = X M? We shall show that the answer is yes for small λ, but not necessarily for very huge ones. The following technical result is the key observation for our work on Juhász problem. It and Corollary 2 are due independently to Lucia Junqueira, conversations with whom have been very helpful. Note that when we write X M, we are implicitly assuming that X M. Also note that D λ M implies λ M. Research supported by NSERC Grant A-7354. Mathematics Subject Classification: Primary: 54D30; Secondary: 03E35, 03E55, 54B10. Key words: Elementary submodel, reflection, compact, generalized Cantor discontinuum, huge cardinals.

346 Franklin D. Tall Theorem 1. Let λ be a set. (Most of the time, it will be a cardinal.) Suppose (D λ ) M is compact. Then (D λ ) M is homeomorphic to D λ M. Proof. Let h :(D λ ) M D λ M be defined by h(f) =f (λ M). Claim h is a homeomorphism. Since (D λ ) M is compact and also T 2 (since D λ is [JT 1 ]), it suffices to show h is continuous, one-one, and has dense image. Let [p] ={g D λ M : g dom(p) =p}, where p is a finite partial function from λ M into D. Then h 1 ([p]) = {f D λ M : f dom(p) =p}. But this is open in (D λ ) M. h is one-one, since if f 1 f 2 are in D λ M, f 1 (λ M) f 2 (λ M) by elementarity. Finally, given any non-empty basic open [p] ind λ M, since dom(p) M, p M, so the function f defined by i) f dom(p) =p, ii) f ( λ dom(p) ) =0, is in (D λ ) M, and h(f) [p]. Corollary 2. If λ M and (D λ ) M is compact, then (D λ ) M = D λ. Proof. In this case, h is the identity function. Corollary 3. Let µ be the least ordinal not included in M. Then if λ is a cardinal less than µ and (D λ ) M is compact, then D λ =(D λ ) M. The proof is immediate. Corollary 4. Let µ be the least ordinal not included in M. If X M is homeomorphic to D λ, λ < µ, and D λ M, then X = X M. Proof. By [J], since X M is compact, so is X and there is a continuous map from X onto X M. Relativizing, there is a continuous map from X M onto (D λ ) M. Hence (D λ ) M is compact,

REFLECTING ON COMPACT SPACES 347 so D λ and hence 2 λ M. Therefore λ + M. We now do some easy calculation of cardinal functions. See [H] for definitions and theorems. Using a straightforward argument done in detail in [T 1 ], we see that X has no right- or left-separated subspaces of size λ +, else X M would. But w(x M )=λ. Since X M and hence [T 1 ] X is T 3, it follows that X T 2 λ,sox T M, so X = X M. Theorem 5. The first cardinal λ if any such that (D λ ) M is compact for some M but D λ must be strongly inaccessible. Proof. The first cardinal if any for which (D λ ) M is compact but D λ cannot be 2 κ for some κ<λ, κ M. By elementarity, we can omit κ M. The point is that since D κ is a continuous image of D λ (D λ ) M compact implies (D κ ) M is compact implies D κ =(D κ ) M implies 2 κ M implies λ M implies (D λ ) M = D λ. The first such cardinal can also not be singular, since D λ M implies λ M implies cf(λ) M implies D cf(λ) M (since D λ M). Then, since λ is least and as before (D cf(λ) ) M is compact, (D cf(λ) ) M = D cf(λ). Therefore D cf(λ) and a fortiori cf(λ) M. But then there is a set S of cardinals cofinal in λ included in M. For each σ S, D σ M and (D σ ) M is compact, so D σ =(D σ ) M so D σ and hence σ M. But then λ M and so D λ =(D λ ) M, contradiction. Thus M thinks λ is strongly inaccessible, so it is. Corollary 6. Suppose X M is homeomorphic to D λ M and λ is less than the first strongly inaccessible cardinal. Then X = X M. Proof. As for Corollary 4 above. Thus if there are no strongly inaccessible cardinals, Juhasz problem is solved. A less draconian solution is given by the following two results. 0 # is a set of natural numbers, the existence of which has large cardinal strength. See [K]. V = L implies 0 # does not exist.

348 Franklin D. Tall Corollary 7. If 0 # does not exist and M λ and (D λ ) M is compact, then (D λ ) M = D λ. Proof. This follows immediately from Lemma 8. [KT] If 0 # does not exist and M λ, then M λ. Corollary 9. If 0 # does not exist and X M is homeomorphic to D λ M, then X = X M. Proof. M X M =2 λ,so2 λ M, so as in the proof of Corollary 4, X = X M. By going to very large cardinals, we can find a λ such that (D λ ) M is compact but not equal to D λ. Definition. A cardinal λ is η-extendible if there is a ζ and an elementary embedding j : V λ+η V ζ, with critical point λ. See [K] to find out about such cardinals and about 2-huge ones, which we shall shortly introduce. Here we shall only mention that η-extendible cardinals are weaker in consistency strength than supercompact cardinals. Observe that for η 1, D j(λ) j V λ+η = {j(s) :j(s) D j(λ) and S V λ+η } = {j(s) :S D λ } = j D λ. Now if we want D j(λ) j V λ+η, we need η 2, for then D λ V λ+η,soj(d λ )=D j(λ) j V λ+η. We would be done if our definition of X M used V θ instead of H(θ) since j V λ+η is an elementary submodel of V ζ. To get H(θ), we use the fact that for inaccessible θ, V θ = H(θ), and work with a larger cardinal. Definition. λ is 2-huge if there is an elementary embedding j : V N, an inner model, with critical point λ such that j(j(λ)) N N.

REFLECTING ON COMPACT SPACES 349 2-hugeness has considerably more consistency strength than supercompactness and assures us that j V j(λ) N, as is j D λ. j V j(λ) is an elementary submodel of V j(j(λ)) = H(j(j(λ))) (since j(j(λ)) is inaccessible by elementarity). As before, D j(λ) j V j(λ) and D j(λ) j V j(λ) = j D λ, which is compact T 2. (D j(λ) ) j Vj(λ) is also a T 2 (since D j(λ) is and T 2 goes down [JT 1 ]) topology on D j(λ) j V j(λ) that is weaker than the subspace topology and hence the two topologies are equal by compactness. Both j V j(λ) and V j(j(λ)) are in N; the proof that the former is an elementary submodel of the latter can be carried out in N. Thus, N thinks there is an elementary submodel M of H(j(j(λ))) such that (D j(λ) ) M is compact T 2 but D j(λ) (since j(λ) >λ). By elementarity, in V there is an elementary submodel M of H j(λ) such that (D λ ) M is compact T 2 but D λ. We have proved Theorem 8. If λ is 2-huge, then there is an elementary submodel M such that (D λ ) M is compact but D λ. There are several problems that remain: What is the consistency strength of the existence of a λ such that (D λ ) M is compact but D λ? Could such a λ be a successor cardinal? Must the first such λ be larger than merely strongly inaccessible? After this paper was completed, Lucia Junqueira [JT 2 ] proved that the condition that M λ can be removed from Corollary 7. It follows that the existence of a compact (D λ ) M D λ has consistency strength at least equal to the existence of 0 #. In [JT 2 ] we discuss in general when X M compact implies X M = X. In [T 2 ] we investigate the particular case of when X M is a dyadic compactum; the results obtained generalize those in this paper. Of course there are simple examples in ZFC of X s which are not equal to X M, even if the latter is compact. For example, let X be the one-point compactification of an uncountable discrete space and let M be countable.

350 Franklin D. Tall In [Ku], K. Kunen considerably sharpened the large cardinal bounds of Theorems 5 and 8. References [H] R. Hodel, Cardinal Functions I, 1-61, eds., K. Kunen and J.E. Vaughan, The Handbook of Set-theoretic Topology, North- Holland, Amsterdam, 1984. [J] L.R. Junqueira, Upwards preservation by elementary submodels, Top. Proc. 25, Spring 2000. [JT 1 ] L.R. Junqueira and F.D. Tall, The topology of elementary submodels, Top. Appl. 82 (1998), 239-266. [JT 2 ], More reflections on compactness, submitted. [JW] W. Just and M. Weese, Discovering modern set theory, II in Graduate Studies in Mathematics, American Mathematical Society 18 1997. [K] A. Kanamori, The Higher Infinite, Springer Verlag, Berlin 1994. [Ku] K. Kunen, Compact spaces, compact cardinals, and elementary submodels, preprint. [KT] K. Kunen and F.D. Tall, The real line in elementary submodels of set theory, J. Symbolic Logic 65 (2000), 683-691. [T 1 ] F.D. Tall, If it looks and smells like the reals,..., Fund. Math. 163 (2000), 1-11. [T 2 ] F.D. Tall, Reflections on dyadic compacta, Top. Appl., to appear. Department of Mathematics, University of Toronto, Toronto, Ontario M5S 3G3 CANADA E-mail address: tall@math.utoronto.ca