Definitions and Proofs

Similar documents
Graduate Microeconomics II Lecture 5: Cheap Talk. Patrick Legros

Mechanism Design: Basic Concepts

Costly Expertise. Dino Gerardi and Leeat Yariv yz. Current Version: December, 2007

Ex Post Cheap Talk : Value of Information and Value of Signals

Government 2005: Formal Political Theory I

Coordination and Cheap Talk in a Battle of the Sexes with Private Information

Deceptive Advertising with Rational Buyers

Some Notes on Costless Signaling Games

Bayes Correlated Equilibrium and Comparing Information Structures

joint with Jonathan Pogach (Penn) 2009 FESAMES at Tokyo Hong Kong University of Science and Technology Honesty vs. White Lies Kim & Pogach Overview

Supplementary appendix to the paper Hierarchical cheap talk Not for publication

When to Ask for an Update: Timing in Strategic Communication. National University of Singapore June 5, 2018

9 A Class of Dynamic Games of Incomplete Information:

An Example of Conflicts of Interest as Pandering Disincentives

ECO421: Communication

When to Ask for an Update: Timing in Strategic Communication

An Efficient Solution to the Informed Principal Problem

Communication with Self-Interested Experts Part II: Models of Cheap Talk

Informed Principal in Private-Value Environments

Correlated Equilibrium in Games with Incomplete Information

Robust Predictions in Games with Incomplete Information

Equilibrium Refinements

On the Unique D1 Equilibrium in the Stackelberg Model with Asymmetric Information Janssen, M.C.W.; Maasland, E.

Communication in Cournot Oligopoly

1 Web Appendix: Equilibrium outcome under collusion (multiple types-multiple contracts)

Cheap Talk with Two Senders and Complementary Information

Static Information Design

Reputation and Bounded Memory in Repeated Games with Incomplete Information

EconS Microeconomic Theory II Midterm Exam #2 - Answer Key

On the Informed Principal Model with Common Values

Honesty vs. White Lies

Bayesian Persuasion Online Appendix

Hierarchical cheap talk

Disclosure of Endogenous Information

Game Theory. Monika Köppl-Turyna. Winter 2017/2018. Institute for Analytical Economics Vienna University of Economics and Business

Strategic Learning and Information Transmission

Hierarchical Bayesian Persuasion

Hierarchical cheap talk

. Introduction to Game Theory Lecture Note 8: Dynamic Bayesian Games. HUANG Haifeng University of California, Merced

Known Unknowns: Power Shifts, Uncertainty, and War.

Wars of Attrition with Budget Constraints

Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium

Cheap Talk With Two-Sided Private Information

Competition relative to Incentive Functions in Common Agency

Endogenous Persuasion with Rational Verification

Organizational Barriers to Technology Adoption: Evidence from Soccer-Ball Producers in Pakistan

Sender s Small Concern for Credibility and Receiver s Dilemma

Communication and Voting With Double-Sided Information

Selecting Cheap-Talk Equilibria

Credible Ratings. Ettore Damiano, Li, Hao University of Toronto. Wing Suen The University of Hong Kong. March 7, 2008

Cheap Talk with Correlated Signals

Good Lies. May Abstract. Decision makers often face uncertainty about the ability and the integrity of their

Using Cheap Talk to Polarize or Unify a Group of Decision Makers

Persuasion Under Costly Lying

Online Appendix for Sourcing from Suppliers with Financial Constraints and Performance Risk

Sequential Games with Incomplete Information

Benefits from non-competing persuaders

Online Appendix for "Auctions in Markets: Common Outside Options and the Continuation Value Effect" Not intended for publication

Iterative Weak Dominance and Interval-Dominance Supermodular Games

Online Appendices for Large Matching Markets: Risk, Unraveling, and Conflation

Accept or Reject? : An Organizational Perspective

Game Theory. Wolfgang Frimmel. Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium

Introduction. 1 University of Pennsylvania, Wharton Finance Department, Steinberg Hall-Dietrich Hall, 3620

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion

Almost Fully Revealing Cheap Talk with Imperfectly Informed Senders

A Model of Gossip. Wei Li. June, Abstract

The Social Value of Credible Public Information

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion

On the Pareto Efficiency of a Socially Optimal Mechanism for Monopoly Regulation

Online Appendix for. Breakthroughs, Deadlines, and Self-Reported Progress: Contracting for Multistage Projects. American Economic Review, forthcoming

Online Addendum for Dynamic Procurement, Quantity Discounts, and Supply Chain Efficiency

EconS Microeconomic Theory II Homework #9 - Answer key

Strategic Information Transmission under Reputation Concerns

Changing One s Mind when the Facts Change: Incentives of Experts and the Design of Reporting Protocols

Pre-Bayesian Games. Krzysztof R. Apt. CWI, Amsterdam, the Netherlands, University of Amsterdam. (so not Krzystof and definitely not Krystof)

ONLINE APPENDICES. Paternalism, Libertarianism, and the Nature of Disagreement Uliana Loginova and Petra Persson

Models of Reputation with Bayesian Updating

Strongly Consistent Self-Confirming Equilibrium

Communication and Voting with Double-Sided Information

Renegotiation proof mechanism design with imperfect type veri cation

Discussion of "Persuasion in Global Games with an Application to Stress Testing" by Nicolas Inostroza and Alessandro Pavan

MULTISTAGE INFORMATION TRANSMISSION WITH VOLUNTARY MONETARY TRANSFER

n Communication and Binary Decisions : Is it Better to Communicate?

Notes on Mechanism Designy

Discussion Paper Series Number 222

Microeconomics II Lecture 4: Incomplete Information Karl Wärneryd Stockholm School of Economics November 2016

The Art of Conversation

Hierarchical cheap talk

Notes on Blackwell s Comparison of Experiments Tilman Börgers, June 29, 2009

Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium. Definition. The single-crossing property. This is a draft; me with comments, typos, clarifications, etc.

Abstract We analyze how communication and voting interact when there is uncertainty about players' preferences. We consider two players who vote on fo

A Model of Gossip. Wei Li Massachusetts Institute of Technology. November 14, Abstract

On Bayesian Persuasion with Multiple Senders

Reputational Concern with Endogenous Information Acquisition. Haibo Xu Washington University in Saint Louis. December 28, 2011

Are Two a Good Representative for Many?

Contracts under Asymmetric Information

Revenue Maximization in Multi-Object Auctions

WHEN ARE SIGNALS COMPLEMENTS OR SUBSTITUTES?

EC319 Economic Theory and Its Applications, Part II: Lecture 7

Non-Existence of Equilibrium in Vickrey, Second-Price, and English Auctions

Transcription:

Giving Advice vs. Making Decisions: Transparency, Information, and Delegation Online Appendix A Definitions and Proofs A. The Informational Environment The set of states of nature is denoted by = [, ], and the state of nature,, is determined according to the Uniform distribution on [, ]. 3 Upon realization of, each individual i {A, P } receives a conditionally independent (and private) signal s i {, } according to the following probability mass function: if x =, Pr[s i = x ] = if x =. After observing a single signal s i {, }, i s posterior beliefs about are characterized by the following probability density function: g i (ts i ) = ( t) if s i =, (t) if s i =. More generally, player i s posterior beliefs conditional upon observing m signals {s,...,s m } with k = m j= s j (i.e., k occurrences of s = and m k occurrences of s = ) is characterized by a Beta(k +,m k + ) distribution, so that E( k,m) = V ( k,m) = k + m +, and (k + )(m k + ) (m + ) (m + 3). 3 This assumption greatly simplifies the calculations and allows us to focus on the key institutional and strategic tradeoffs. In addition, note that the uniform distribution is a useful baseline, as it maximizes the ex ante informativeness of each agent s signal. In other words, this is the case in which information aggregation is most important to all agents from an ex ante perspective. Accordingly, this baseline amplifies the importance of our results when they indicate that information is not aggregated in equilibrium or that optimal institutional design limits information aggregation. 3

Accordingly, the optimal policy choice for a player i N, given k and m, is y i (k,m) = k + m + + i. A. Strategies A (pure) strategy for P is P = (a, z P ), where a [, ] is a feasible assignment of authority to A (and P s authority is a), and z P R R maps observed policy choices by A into policy choices by P. A pure strategy for A is A = z i [, ] {, } R specifies a policy choice, given A s authority a and signal s A {, }. Our notion of equilibrium throughout is perfect Bayesian equilibrium. A.3 Beliefs A s beliefs are straightforward in our setting: we require them to be consistent with the informational structure defined above and the strategies of P. P s beliefs are technically more complex, in that P has a continuum of information sets. When considering separating equilibria, we restrict attention to those in which A assigns positive probability only to the sequentially rational policy choices when choosing y A. We provide further justification for this refinement below, and then consider equilibria ruled out by it. Taking this refinement as given for the moment, it follows from Equation () that in a separating equilibrium, P assigns positive probability only to the following policies: y A { 3 + A, 3 + A } () in the opaque case, and y A { + A, + A, 3 + A } (5) in the top-down transparency case. 3

Now consider P s beliefs about A s signal, as induced by A s policy choice. Denote this belief as h(y A ) = Pr[s A = y A ]. Suppose without loss of generality that A P. 3 Given our equilibrium refinement, these beliefs are defined as follows: for y A < 3 + A, for y h(y A ) = A 3 + A. for y A < s P + + A, for y A s P + + A. A. The Agent s Best Response in the opaque case. in the top-down transparent case. (6) The following proposition justifies our focus on the choices defined in () and (5), above. Proposition Suppose that A > P, A >, and the principal s beliefs satisfy Equation 6. Then the agent s best response y A satisfies the restrictions in () in the opaque case and (5) in the top-down transparent case. Proof : Given the principal has beliefs that satisfy (6), A s expected payoff from choosing policy y A after observing s A = is ( P A ) A (y A 3 U A (y A h, s A = ) = A) if y A < 3 + A, ( P + A) A (y A 3 A) if y A 3 + A. Note that, except at y A = 3 + A, U A (y A h, s A = ) varies with y A only through the term A (y A 3 A). Accordingly, it follows that, if y A < 3 + A, then y A = 3 + A since A (y A 3 A) is maximized by this choice and, since A (y A 3 A) is decreasing in y A for y A > 3 + A, if y A 3 + A, then y A = 3 + A. We omit derivation of the case when s A =, as it is symmetric. Turning to the top-down transparency case, given the principal has beliefs that satisfy (6), A s 3 The arguments that follow are symmetric in case A < P. 3

expected payoff from choosing policy y A after observing s A = (and leaving s P arbitrary) is ( P A ) A (y A +s P A ) if y A < s P + + A, U A (y A h, s A =,s P ) = ( P + 5 A) A (y A +s P A ) if y A s P + + A. The reasoning explained for the opaque case can be applied immediately to this case as well, and leads to the analogous conclusion that if y A < s P + + A, then y A = +s P + A and if y A s P + + A, then y A = s P + + A. Accordingly, the beliefs defined in (6) induce the agent s best response (regardless of whether the incentive compatibility conditions hold or not) to be restricted to the choices defined in () and (5), as was to be shown. A.5 The Equilibrium Set There are three classes of equilibria in this model:. Pooling equilibria. In a pooling equilibrium, A s decision is uninformative in the sense that P s beliefs are independent of y A. Such a profile can be an equilibrium if and only if A =, as otherwise such beliefs give the agent a strict incentive to set y A truthfully based on his or her signal.. Separating equilibria. In a separating equilibrium, P s beliefs (correctly) assign probability one to the signal that was observed by the agent based on y A. Such a profile can be an equilibrium only if there are exactly two choices of y A that are observed with positive probability on the equilibrium path of play. Equation (6) refines this set of equilibria, a point to which we return below (Section A.6). 3. Semi-separating equilibria. A semi-separating profile is one in which A uses a strategy of 33

the following form: y y with probability p if s A = and with probability q if s A =, (s A ) = y with probability p if s A = and with probability q if s A =. Such a strategy can be part of an equilibrium profile only if either p = or q =. 3 (7) Furthermore, given our normalization that A > P, such a profile can be part of an equilibrium profile only if q =. Any strategy-belief profile not falling into one of those three categories cannot be an equilibrium in this setting: unless A =, the agent must be assign positive probability to exactly two choices of y A in equilibrium. A.6 What Equilibria Are Eliminated by the Refinement in Equation (6)? As stated above, we consider only those separating equilibria in which the principal holds beliefs consistent with Equation (6). There are two qualitative cases to consider when asking what other equilibria are ruled out by our refinement, corresponding to A = and A >, respectively. We treat each in turn. A =. In this case, the game is equivalent to a cheap talk game. Accordingly, when the incentive compatibility conditions are satisfied, there are uncountably infinite separating equilibria (including ones in which the agent might use more than two messages ). However, these equilibria are all payoff equivalent to both players, and accordingly, eliminating them is irrelevant. Semi-separating and pooling equilibria which are not payoff-equivalent to the separating equilibrium considered in our analysis can also exist. However, when the incentive compatibility conditions for the separating equilibrium are satisfied, it Pareto dominates (in terms of ex ante expected payoffs) any other, non-separating equilibrium. 33 The principal s ex ante preferences are clear because, conditional on the agent s 3 Of course, if p = q =, then this is a separating strategy. 33 This is obvious from Crawford and Sobel (98), but for completeness we include another argument demonstrating this here. 3

signal, s A, the principal prefers a separating equilibrium regardless of the realization of the signal. To see that the agent also prefers a separating profile from an ex ante perspective, Consider any strategy profile where there is some policy z such that Pr[y A = zs A = ] = p > and Pr[y A = zs A = ] = p >. When the principal observes z, his or sequentially rational response is y P (z,s P ) = P + p +p p +p if s P =, P + p +3p p +p if s P =. Substituting A = and P =, the agent s state-unconditional expected payoff from playing z in equilibrium (i.e., prior to observing s A ) is ( A P ) P + p + p p + p A ( ) + P + p + 3p p + p A d. which reduces to ( A P ) 3p + p p + p (p + p ) + p + p p + 3p (p + p ) (8) This is maximized by p = p and achieves a value of ( A P ) 8. This is, of course, equivalent to the pooling equilibrium. The agent s ex ante payoff from the separating equilibrium is ( A P ). Note, also, that (8) must equal the agent s unconditional, ex ante payoff if the strategy is part of an equilibrium because the agent must be indifferent between z and any other policy he or she chooses with positive probability. Thus, in ex ante terms, the agent strictly prefers a separating equilibrium. A >. In this case, there is no equilibrium in which the principal does not condition his or her policy on the agent s policy. If the principal ignored the agent s decision, then A > implies that the agent would have a strict best response of setting y A = s A+ 3 + A in the opaque case and y A = s A+s P + A in the transparent case. Of course, if the agent does that, then the principal should not ignore the agent s decision when making his or her own policy choice. 35

Moving to non-babbling equilibria, matters become more complicated. As with the cheap-talk case of A =, the existence of a semi-separating equilibrium for a given A and implies that an ex ante Pareto superior separating equilibrium also exists, so we set semi-separating equilibria aside. However, the real complication arises because there are other separating equilibria. Specifically, with the proper specification of beliefs, it is always possible to construct a separating equilibrium, regardless of the players biases. The next proposition, drawn from Patty and Penn (), demonstrates that beliefs can always be properly constructed so that it is incentive compatible for the agent to truthfully reveal his or her signal through his or her policy choice. The proposition applies to the opaque information case, but the logic and calculations can be straightforwardly applied to the top-down transparency case. Proposition (Patty and Penn ()) For any A > and ( A, P ) R, there exists a belief h( A, A, P ) such that a separating equilibrium exists. Proof : Suppose that A > P and that there exists some such that P s sequentially rational strategy as a function of his or her signal, s P, and the policy chosen by A, y A, given beliefs h(y A A, A, P ), is s P + if y A < 3 y P (y A ; ) = + + A, s P + if y A 3 + + A. (9) Given the behavior described by (9), there are only policy choices that are potentially optimal for A and informative to P : y A { 3 + A, 3 + + A}. Let ya = 3 + A and ya = 3 + + A denote these two policies. Note that ya y A = 3 +. The expected payoff difference between these two choices is U A (y As A ) U A (y As A ) = = P A P + + A 3 + P ( A P ) if s A =, P ( A P ) + A A 3 P A P if s A =, P 6 ( A P ) + A 3 + if s A =, A 9 P 6 P ( A P ) if s A =. Because A > P, consider first the incentive compatibility condition in the case of s A = (this is the only one that can bind for sufficiently small ). In this case, truthfulness is incentive compatible with 36

these beliefs if and only if P 6 + A 3 + P ( A P ), P P 6 + A 3 + A P, 8 + A P 3 + A P, () so that, as intuition suggests, for any fixed A and P, truthfulness is incentive compatible under the supposition that player must choose between ya and y A for sufficiently demanding beliefs (i.e., for sufficiently large values of ). However, as alluded to above, setting too large can lead to a violation of incentive compatibility when s A =. In particular, player could choose his or her sequentially rational policy following s A = even if that leads to player inferring that s A =. Doing so optimally (given ) involves choosing y A = s A+ 3 + A. The resulting incentive compatibility condition in this situation is based on the following expected payoff difference calculation: U A s A + 3 + A s A = U A (y As A = ) = P ( A P ) + A P A P, = A P 6 P ( A P ), so that incentive compatibility is satisfied only if P A 6 + A P, () So, suppose that = P A 6 + ( A P ). Then substituting this into inequality, 8 + A P 3 + P A 6 + ( A P ) A P, 37

and letting M 8 + A P 3 + P A 6 + ( A P ), M > 8 + A P 9 + P A 6 + ( A P ) A P, + A + A P A P. 9 P Accordingly, setting = P A 6 + ( A P ) implies that inequalities and are simultaneously satisfied. We now turn to the question of the principal s preferences over the equilibria for >. Specifically, we show that the principal prefers the equilibrium we consider (defined by O A 6) to all of the other equilibria covered by Proposition A.6. in Proposition A.7 The Principal s Preferences over Equilibria We establish the optimality (from the principal s perspective) of the equilibria considered in the paper in two steps. First, we consider the separating equilibria in which the principal s beliefs do not satisfy Equation (6). Then, we demonstrate that any semi-separating equilibrium is dominated by a separating equilibrium from the perspective of the principal s ex ante equilibrium expected payoff. A.7. Equilibria that do not satisfy Equation (6) While incentive compatibility can always be obtained, it is not necessarily the case that obtaining incentive compatibility is in P s interests. That is, it is not clear that the value of the agent s information for the principal in setting his or her own policy is sufficient to outweigh the distortion that the agent must impose on his or her policy choice to sustain incentive compatibility of truthfulness. Based on the analysis above, we can establish an upper bound on the preference divergence between the principal and agent, above which the principal receives a strictly higher payoff from setting A = and the two players playing a babbling equilibrium of the resulting cheap talk signaling game. 38

Proposition 5 For all, the Principal s equilibrium expected payoff from choosing O A ( ), given that the equilibrium strategies and beliefs satisfy Equation (6) is strictly higher than any equilibrium following any other choice A. Proof : To establish this bound, note the cheapest pure strategy separating equilibrium in terms of, is constructed by setting so as to satisfy inequality () with equality. This value is (, if A P 8 ) = A 9 P, P A ( A P ) 6 otherwise. () Note that player s expected payoff from the pure strategy separating equilibrium supported by the beliefs based on equation (9), with = (, ) as defined in (), is U P ( (, )) = P + A 8 + ( (, ) + A P ) + ( A P ), = P + A 8 + ( A P ) + (, ) + (, )( A P ) (3) Presuming without loss of generality that A P > 8, substituting (, ) = P A ( A P ) 6, P A, and B A P into (3) yields U P ( (, )) = A A 8 AB ( A ) B 3 B = A B B 3 88 B 96 B ( A ) A B 6, ( A ) A B 6, which is decreasing in A for all A [, ]. The principal s equilibrium payoff from the equilibrium constructed in our analysis for the 39

opaque case (Proposition 6) is U P ( O A ( ); ) = 8( A P ) 79 + 8( A P ) 7 + ( A P ), and comparing this with () evaluated at A = yields the following: 3 U P ( O A ( ); ) U P ( (, )), 8( A P ) 79 + 8( A P ) 7 + ( A P ) A P 96, 8 A P 3 + 5.86 >.. These inequalities imply (as shown in Proposition 6) that, in the opaque case, the preference divergence must be greater than the maximal amount of divergence for which the principal prefers to delegate any authority to the agent. To verify this further, note that the principal s expected equilibrium payoff in the babbling equilibrium of the cheap talk case ( A = ) is greater than () evaluated at A = whenever 8 A P 96, A P 3 7.8. Thus, the principal strictly prefers delegating A O ( ) to the agent and playing the equilibrium described in the article to delegating any other value A and playing the equilibrium with beliefs described by supported by the beliefs based on equation (9) with = ( A, ), as defined in (). 3 Evaluating () at A is actually inconsistent with equilibrium for A P > 8, but this values equals the supremum of the principal s best possible equilibrium payoff using the beliefs based on equation (9), which is sufficient for our purposes here.

A.7. Semi-separating Equilibria When A >, any equilibrium must involve the agent assigning positive probability to exactly two distinct policy choices. Therefore, suppose that the agent plays a strategy of the following form for some value p [, ]: y (s A ) = A + 3 with probability p if and only if s A =, A + 3 with probability p if s A = or with probability if s A =. () Because d Pr[s A = s P = ] = d +, ( )d = 3, the principal s on-the-path beliefs regarding s A are h(s A y A,s P ) Pr[s A = y A,s P ] = if y A = A + 3, +p if y A = A + 3 and s P =, and +p if y A = A + 3 and s P =. U P (zy A = A + 3,s P ) = (z +p 3 ) + 3 8 + p (z +p ) + if s P =, and (z +p ) + + p (z +p ) + 3 8 if s P =. @ @z U P (zy A = A + 3,s P ) = +p (z ) + p +p (z ) if s P =, and +p (z 3 ) + p +p (z ) if s P =.

Solving the FOC for s P = : + p z + p + p z =, z = + p ( + p), and solving the FOC for s P = : + p z 3 + p + p z =, z = 3 + p ( + p). Setting @ @z U P (zy A = A + 3,s P ) = implies that y P (y A = A + 3,s P ) is as follows: y P (y A = A + 3,s P ) = +p (+p) + P 3+p if s P =, and (+p) + P if s P =. Solving with an uninformed principal. If the principal receives no signal, the principal s beliefs after observing (on the path values of) y A are h(s A y A ) Pr[s A = y A ] = if y A = A + 3, +p if y A = A + 3. Given these beliefs, the principal s sequentially rational response to observing y A = A + 3 is derived as follows: U P (zy A = A + 3 ) = + p z 3 P + 8 + p + p z 3 P + 8

@ @z U P (zy A = A + 3 ) = + p z 3 P + p + p z 3 P Solving the FOC: + p z 3 P + p + p z 3 P =, z = P + + p 3( + p), Thus, y P (y A = A + 3 ) = P + + p 3( + p). Solving for the Agent s IC Conditions. Omitting the variance terms, the agent s expected payoff from choosing y A = A + 3 when s A = is U A ( A + 3 s A = ) = P P + + p 3( + p) 3 A + A 9 and the agent s expected payoff from choosing y A = A + 3 when s A = is U A ( A + 3 s A = ) = P ( P A ). The agent must be indifferent between these two policies after s A = for the semi-separating strategy to be a best response. Thus, it must be the case that the equilibrium mixing probability, p, satisfy the following: P P + + p 3( + p ) 3 A + A 9 = P ( P A ). 3

Substituting P = A to solve for p only as a function of A, A, and P yields p ( A, ) = 3( A)( A P ) A ± ( A )(( A )(9( A P ) ) A ) A. Equivalently, A is uniquely identified by a choice of p (given P and A ) as follows: A (p ) = The Principal s Expected Welfare. 6 A (p + ) 6 P (p + ) 6 A + p + 6 A p 6 P (p + ) + p. By choosing A, the principal can effectively determine the equilibrium mixing probability for the agent. The principal s equilibrium ex ante expected payoff as a function of p is EU P (p) = ( A (p)) A (p) = A P + 36 6 A + p 3( + p)! (! + p(!)) d! ( A (p)) A + 3 P! (! + p(!)) d! A (p) p p 3! ( p)(!) d! A + 3 P! ( p)(!) d!, 6 A + p + 6 A p 6 P (p + ) + p + p + 6 P ( A + p ) 6 A p p Substituting P = without loss of generality, this reduces to EU P (p) = A + 36 6 (p A( p) ) p 6 A + p + 6 A p + p + p p. Notice that @EU P (p) @p = (3 A + )(8 A + p (6 (3 A + A) + ) + 6p A (6 A + )) 9 (6 A + p + 6 A p + p), where A > P and p imply that the numerator is positive and the denominator is positive, so that @EU P (p) @p <.

This implies that the principal wants to choose A so that the agent uses the minimum feasible equilibrium value of p, given A. Of course, the principal can achieve p = : this is simply the separating equilibrium examined in the article. Accordingly, the principal always strictly prefers the separating equilibrium and therefore prefers the babbling equilibrium to any mixed strategy equilibrium whenever he or she prefers the babbling equilibrium to the separating equilibrium. On a technical note, this is because EU P () does not equal the expected payoff of the babbling equilibrium: when p =, (p ) > for all A P >. But recall that for all A P < 8, A = yields a separating equilibrium. Solving with an Informed Principal: The Opaque Case. Duplicating the analysis above with the principal having a private signal yields the following expression for A (p ): A (p ) = 8(p + ) (7 A 7 P + 7) + p ( A + A p P (p + 5) + 5p + ) and, setting P =, one obtains the following expression for the principal s expected payoff in a p-semi-separating equilibrium: EU P (p) = 7 A 3 (p + )(p + 3) + 3 A (8p3 + 37p + 36p 8) + A (p 3 + p + 6p + ) + (p + ) (p + 9), 3 (5(p) + A (p + )(p + 3) + p + ) such that @EU P (p) @p = (7 A ) + 576 3 A (p + )3 (p + ) + 8 A (p + ) (3p + 3p + 8) + A (37p + 3p 3 + 76p + 88p) + 5p + p 3 + p + p 3 5p + A (p + )(p + 3) + p +. It can be verified that, for A >.5666, @EU P (p) @p <. For A 8, the principal prefers the separating equilibrium that can be achieved with A, so that if the principal can not achieve a separating equilibrium in the cheap-talk case, the principal s payoff is strictly decreasing in p, implying that he or she strictly prefers p = to any p >. 5

B Assorted Proofs This appendix contains proofs of several claims made throughout the body of the paper. B. Optimal Delegation Proposition 6 Letting. denote the first root of f(x) = 68x 3 8x, in the opaque case in which agent A does not observe the principal s information, s P, prior to choosing y A, the principal will delegate discretionary authority to the agent as follows: if ( A P ) < 8, A ( ) = 8( A P ) 79+8( A P ) if ( A P ) 8,, if ( A P ) >. Proof : Note that if A P 8, then agent A will be truthful regardless of A, so that the optimal choice for principal P is clear: A =. Thus, presuming that A P > 8 (so that eliciting truthful communication requires delegating positive discretionary authority to the agent) and recalling that O A ( ) max 8( A P ) 79 + 8( A P ), denotes the minimal level of discretionary authority required to elicit truthful revelation from the message sender when the principal is known to be informed but his or her information is opaque to the message sender, the principal s expected payoff from inducing truthful revelation as cheaply as possible in this setting is U P ( A O ( ); ) = O A ( ) O A ( ) A O ( )( A P ), 8 = O A ( ) 7 + ( A P ), = 8( A P ) 79 + 8( A P ) 7 + ( A P ), 6

whereas the expected payoff from delegating zero discretionary authority is U P ( A = ; ) = 8, so that the delegation of positive discretionary authority is in the principal s interest only if U P U P ( A O ( ); ) U P ( A = ; ), = 8 8( A P ) 79 + 8( A P ) 7 + ( A P ) = 7 8( A P ) 79 + 8( A P ) 7 + ( A P ) which holds if and only if A P., as was to be shown. Proposition 7 In the top-down transparency case in which agent A observes principal P s information, s P, prior to choosing y A, principal P will delegate discretionary authority to agent A as follows: if ( A P ) < 8, A ( ) = 8( A P ) if ( A P ) 8, 3+ 8, if ( A P ) > 3+ 8. Proof : Recalling A T ( ) = max, 8( A P ) denote the minimal level of discretionary authority required to elicit truthful revelation from the message sender, note first that principal P s optimal delegation is A = when A P 8, because agent j s optimal choice is to be truthful even with no discretionary authority in those cases. Thus, presuming that A P > 8, the principal s expected payoff from inducing truthful revelation 7

as cheaply as possible (i.e., setting j s discretionary authority equal to A T ( )) is U P ( T A ( ); ) = 8( A P ) ( A P ), whereas the expected payoff from delegating zero discretionary authority is U P ( A = ; ) = 8, so that the delegation of positive discretionary authority is in the principal s interest only if U P ( T A ( ); ) U P ( A = ; ) = 7 8( A P ) ( A P ), (5) which holds only only if A P 8 3 +.96, so that the principal will delegate positive discretionary authority equal to ( ) if and only if A P 8, 3 +, 8 as was to be shown. 8

B. Derivation of Equations 5 & 6 and Inequality 7 The Principal s Decision Problem. Given his or her information, (y A,s P ), the principal s expected payoff from a policy choice y P is U P (y P ) = = ( A )(y P P ) + A (y A P ) g( y A,s P )d, ( A ) y P + P + ( (y P P ) + y P P ) g( y A,s P )d A y A + P + ( (y A P ) + y A P ) g( y A,s P )d, = ( A ) y P + P y P P A y A + P y A P ( A ) (y P P ) g( y A,s P )d A (y A P ) g( y A,s P )d, = ( A )(y P P ) ( A ) Var[ y A,s P ] + E[ y A,s P ] E[ y A,s P ](y P P ) A (y A P ) A Var[ y A,s P ] + E[ y A,s P ] E[ y A,s P ](y A P ), = ( A ) (y P P ) E[ y A,s P ](y P P ) A (y A P ) E[ y A,s P ](y A P ) Var[ y A,s P ] + E[ y A,s P ]. The first order necessary condition for maximization of U P (y P ;,y A,s P ) with respect to y P is du P (y P ;,y A,s P ) dy P = ( A ) (y P P E[ y A,s P ]) =, which yields y P = P + E[ y A,s P ]. (6) In the separating equilibrium considered here, the principal s beliefs, E[ y A,s P ], satisfy the following: if s P = and y A = A + 3, E[ y A,s P ] = if s P = and y A = A + 3, if s P = and y A = A + 3, (7) 3 if s P = and y A = A + 3. 9

Substituting (7) into (6) yields equation (): y P ( s A,s P ) = + s A + s P + P. We now turn to the agent s decision problem to obtain the agent s best response to the principal s beliefs (and sequentially rational behavior based on those beliefs) when choosing y A based on s A. The Agent s Decision Problem. Let h(s P ) denote the conditional probability of s P, given. Then, letting y A A + 3 and y A + 3, then the agent s expected payoffs from y A and y A, respectively, given the agent s information, s A, are 35 U A (y A; s A ) = U A (y A; s A ) = s P = s P = ( A ) s P + ( A ) s P + + P A + A (ya A ) h(s P ) g( s A )d, and + P A + A (ya A ) h(s P ) g( s A )d. Focusing on the case of s A = (this is the tempting case for the agent when A > P ) and noting that h(s P = ) =, h(s P = ) =, and g( s A ) = ( ), U A (y A;) = ( A ) + P A + A 3 ( ) ( )d ( A ) + P A + A 3 ( )d, = ( A )( A P ) A 7, U A (ya;) = ( A ) + P A + A 3 ( ) ( )d ( A ) 3 + P A + A 3 ( )d, = ( A )( A P ) + ( A ) A P A 6 5 8, as stated in equations (5) and (6). Following this, a few steps of algebra yields the following 35 The analysis of the principal s incentives can be applied directly to show that, given these beliefs by the principal, either (and only) ya or y A are strictly best responses for the agent. 5

incentive compatibility condition: U A (y A;) U A (y A;), A A P 9 ( A ) + 8, as stated in inequality (7). 5