Class Notes for Math 921/922: Real Analysis, Instructor Mikil Foss

Similar documents
MATHS 730 FC Lecture Notes March 5, Introduction

THEOREMS, ETC., FOR MATH 515

Integration on Measure Spaces

MATH MEASURE THEORY AND FOURIER ANALYSIS. Contents

Measure Theory & Integration

Chapter 6. Integration. 1. Integrals of Nonnegative Functions. a j µ(e j ) (ca j )µ(e j ) = c X. and ψ =

MA359 Measure Theory

Review of measure theory

L p Spaces and Convexity

MTH 404: Measure and Integration

3 (Due ). Let A X consist of points (x, y) such that either x or y is a rational number. Is A measurable? What is its Lebesgue measure?

2 (Bonus). Let A X consist of points (x, y) such that either x or y is a rational number. Is A measurable? What is its Lebesgue measure?

II - REAL ANALYSIS. This property gives us a way to extend the notion of content to finite unions of rectangles: we define

Real Analysis Notes. Thomas Goller

Lebesgue Integration on R n

The Caratheodory Construction of Measures

1/12/05: sec 3.1 and my article: How good is the Lebesgue measure?, Math. Intelligencer 11(2) (1989),

Real Analysis Problems

Measure Theory on Topological Spaces. Course: Prof. Tony Dorlas 2010 Typset: Cathal Ormond

(U) =, if 0 U, 1 U, (U) = X, if 0 U, and 1 U. (U) = E, if 0 U, but 1 U. (U) = X \ E if 0 U, but 1 U. n=1 A n, then A M.

INTRODUCTION TO MEASURE THEORY AND LEBESGUE INTEGRATION

MATH & MATH FUNCTIONS OF A REAL VARIABLE EXERCISES FALL 2015 & SPRING Scientia Imperii Decus et Tutamen 1

A note on some approximation theorems in measure theory

18.175: Lecture 3 Integration

Chapter 5. Measurable Functions

2 Measure Theory. 2.1 Measures

Dual Space of L 1. C = {E P(I) : one of E or I \ E is countable}.

Measure and integration

CHAPTER I THE RIESZ REPRESENTATION THEOREM

36-752: Lecture 1. We will use measures to say how large sets are. First, we have to decide which sets we will measure.

Reminder Notes for the Course on Measures on Topological Spaces

Functional Analysis, Stein-Shakarchi Chapter 1

REAL AND COMPLEX ANALYSIS

l(y j ) = 0 for all y j (1)

Math 209B Homework 2

(1) Consider the space S consisting of all continuous real-valued functions on the closed interval [0, 1]. For f, g S, define

Math 4121 Spring 2012 Weaver. Measure Theory. 1. σ-algebras

MATH41011/MATH61011: FOURIER SERIES AND LEBESGUE INTEGRATION. Extra Reading Material for Level 4 and Level 6

Daniel Akech Thiong Math 501: Real Analysis Homework Problems with Solutions Fall Problem. 1 Give an example of a mapping f : X Y such that

A List of Problems in Real Analysis

Chapter 4. Measure Theory. 1. Measure Spaces

Riesz Representation Theorems

Measures and Measure Spaces

Probability and Random Processes

Annalee Gomm Math 714: Assignment #2

Measurable functions are approximately nice, even if look terrible.

MATH 202B - Problem Set 5

Partial Solutions to Folland s Real Analysis: Part I

It follows from the above inequalities that for c C 1

THEOREMS, ETC., FOR MATH 516

g 2 (x) (1/3)M 1 = (1/3)(2/3)M.

Lebesgue Measure. Dung Le 1

Lebesgue measure and integration

Measures. 1 Introduction. These preliminary lecture notes are partly based on textbooks by Athreya and Lahiri, Capinski and Kopp, and Folland.

Continuous Functions on Metric Spaces

It follows from the above inequalities that for c C 1

3. (a) What is a simple function? What is an integrable function? How is f dµ defined? Define it first

CHAPTER 6. Differentiation

Measure Theory. John K. Hunter. Department of Mathematics, University of California at Davis

L p Functions. Given a measure space (X, µ) and a real number p [1, ), recall that the L p -norm of a measurable function f : X R is defined by

1 Measurable Functions

Homework 11. Solutions

Product measures, Tonelli s and Fubini s theorems For use in MAT4410, autumn 2017 Nadia S. Larsen. 17 November 2017.

FUNDAMENTALS OF REAL ANALYSIS by. IV.1. Differentiation of Monotonic Functions

Recall that if X is a compact metric space, C(X), the space of continuous (real-valued) functions on X, is a Banach space with the norm

ABSTRACT INTEGRATION CHAPTER ONE

Problem Set 2: Solutions Math 201A: Fall 2016

212a1214Daniell s integration theory.

Lebesgue-Radon-Nikodym Theorem

3 Integration and Expectation

MAT 571 REAL ANALYSIS II LECTURE NOTES. Contents. 2. Product measures Iterated integrals Complete products Differentiation 17

Measures. Chapter Some prerequisites. 1.2 Introduction

REAL ANALYSIS ANALYSIS NOTES. 0: Some basics. Notes by Eamon Quinlan. Liminfs and Limsups

Real Analysis Chapter 1 Solutions Jonathan Conder

MAT 570 REAL ANALYSIS LECTURE NOTES. Contents. 1. Sets Functions Countability Axiom of choice Equivalence relations 9

Functional Analysis Winter 2018/2019

PROBLEMS. (b) (Polarization Identity) Show that in any inner product space

Three hours THE UNIVERSITY OF MANCHESTER. 24th January

Chapter 1. Measure Spaces. 1.1 Algebras and σ algebras of sets Notation and preliminaries

LECTURE NOTES FOR , FALL Contents. Introduction. 1. Continuous functions

02. Measure and integral. 1. Borel-measurable functions and pointwise limits

Notions such as convergent sequence and Cauchy sequence make sense for any metric space. Convergent Sequences are Cauchy

Differentiation of Measures and Functions

+ 2x sin x. f(b i ) f(a i ) < ɛ. i=1. i=1

Bounded and continuous functions on a locally compact Hausdorff space and dual spaces

Defining the Integral

MEASURE AND INTEGRATION. Dietmar A. Salamon ETH Zürich

consists of two disjoint copies of X n, each scaled down by 1,

Chapter 8. General Countably Additive Set Functions. 8.1 Hahn Decomposition Theorem

x 0 + f(x), exist as extended real numbers. Show that f is upper semicontinuous This shows ( ɛ, ɛ) B α. Thus

1.1. MEASURES AND INTEGRALS

Compendium and Solutions to exercises TMA4225 Foundation of analysis

Analysis Comprehensive Exam Questions Fall 2008

+ = x. ± if x > 0. if x < 0, x

Measure and Integration: Concepts, Examples and Exercises. INDER K. RANA Indian Institute of Technology Bombay India

Problem Set 5: Solutions Math 201A: Fall 2016

MEASURE THEORY AND LEBESGUE INTEGRAL 15

FUNDAMENTALS OF REAL ANALYSIS by. II.1. Prelude. Recall that the Riemann integral of a real-valued function f on an interval [a, b] is defined as

Real Analysis Chapter 3 Solutions Jonathan Conder. ν(f n ) = lim

4 Integration 4.1 Integration of non-negative simple functions

Transcription:

University of Nebraska - Lincoln DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln Math Department: Class Notes and Learning Materials Mathematics, Department of 200 Class Notes for Math 92/922: Real Analysis, Instructor Mikil Foss Laura Lynch University of Nebraska-Lincoln, llynch@ccga.edu Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.unl.edu/mathclass Part of the Science and Mathematics Education Commons Lynch, Laura, "Class Notes for Math 92/922: Real Analysis, Instructor Mikil Foss" (200). Math Department: Class Notes and Learning Materials. 4. http://digitalcommons.unl.edu/mathclass/4 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Mathematics, Department of at DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. It has been accepted for inclusion in Math Department: Class Notes and Learning Materials by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln.

Class Notes for Math 92/922: Real Analysis, Instructor Mikil Foss Topics include: Semicontinuity, equicontinuity, absolute continuity, metric spaces, compact spaces, Ascoli s theorem, Stone Weierstrass theorem, Borel and Lebesque measures, measurable functions, Lebesque integration, convergence theorems, L p spaces, general measure and integration theory, Radon- Nikodyn theorem, Fubini theorem, Lebesque-Stieltjes integration, Semicontinuity, equicontinuity, absolute continuity, metric spaces, compact spaces, Ascoli s theorem, Stone Weierstrass theorem, Borel and Lebesque measures, measurable functions, Lebesque integration, convergence theorems, Lp spaces, general measure and integration theory, Radon-Nikodyn theorem, Fubini theorem, Lebesque-Stieltjes integration. Prepared by Laura Lynch, University of Nebraska-Lincoln August 200

Course Information Office Hours: :30- MWF Optional Meeting Time: Thursdays at 5pm Assessment Chapter Drawbacks to Riemann Integration Homework 6 Midterm Final 34pts 33pts 33pts (Dec 3 : 3pm). Not all bounded functions are Riemann Integrable. 2. All Riemann Integrable functions are bounded. 3. To use the following theorem, we must have f R[a, b]. Theorem (Dominated Convergence Theorem for Riemann Integrals, Arzela). Let {f n } n= R[a, b] and f R[a, b] be given. Suppose there exists g R[a, b] such that f n (x) < g(x) for all x [a, b] and x [a, b], then lim n b a f n (x)dx = b a f(x)dx. if x = p q in lowest terms with q n on [0, ], Example. Define f n (x) = 0 otherwise. lim f n(x) = f(x) for all n Then f n (x) χ Q [0,] =: f. Notice here f n (x) < 2 for all x [0, ] but f is not Riemann Integrable. Thus we can not use the theorem. 4. The space R[a, b] is not complete with respect to many useful metrics. Good Properties of Riemann Integration. R[a, b] is a vector space 2. The functional f b f(x)dx is linear on R[a, b]. a 3. b f(x)dx 0 when f(x) 0 for all x [a, b]. a 4. Theorem holds.. Measurable and Topological Spaces Definition (p 3,9). Let be a nonempty set.. A collection T of subsets of is called a topology of if it possesses the following properties: (a) T and T. (b) If {U j } n j= T, then n U j T. (c) If {U α } α A T, then α A U α T. 2. If T is a topology on, then (, T ) is called a topological space. If T is understood, we may just call itself a topological space. The members of T are called open sets in. The complements of open sets in are called closed sets.

3. If and Y are topological spaces and f : Y, then f is called continuous if f (V) is open in for all V that are open in Y. Examples.. If = R, then {, R} is a topology on R. 2. If = R, then the power set {P(R)} is a topology on R. 3. {, a>0 {( a, a)}, R} is a topology on R. 4. {, a<b R {(a, b)}, a R {(, a), (a, )}, R} is a topology on R = R {± }. Definition (pg2,25,43).. A collection M of subsets of is called a σ algebra if (a) M and M. (b) If E M, then E C M. (c) If {E j } j= M, then j= E j M. 2. If M is a σ algebra on, then (, M) is called a measurable space. If M is understood, then we may just call itself a measurable space. The members of M are called measurable sets. 3. If (, M) and (Y, N ) are measurable spaces, then f : Y is called (M, N ) measurable or measurable if f (E) M whenever E N. Examples.. (R, {, R}) is a σ algebra 2. (R, {, {}, R \ {}, R}) is a σ algebra 3. (R, {E R E or E C is countable}) is a σ algebra Lemma. If {E j } j= P(), then {F j} j= P() defined by F j = E j \ j k= E k is a sequence of mutually disjoint sets and j= E j = j= F j. Note. As a result of Lemma, we can actually modify part (c) of our definition of a σ algebra to say (c) If {E j } M is a sequence of mutually disjoint sets, then E j M. Remarks.. Property (a) of our definition for σ algebra could be replaced with M or M. 2. If {E j } j= M, then {EC j } j= M and j= E j = [ j= EC j ]C M. 3. If E, F M, then E \ F = E F C M. Theorem 2. If E is a collection of subsets of, then there exists a unique smallest σ algebra M(E) that contains the members of E. Note: By smallest, we mean any other σ algebra will contain all the sets in M(E). Proof. Let Ω be the family of all σ algebras containing E. Note Ω as P() Ω. Define M(E) = M Ω M. We want to show M(E) is a σ algebra.., M(E) since, M for all M Ω. 2. Let E M(E). Then E M for all M Ω which implies E C M for all M Ω which implies E C M(E). 3. If {E j } j= M(E), then {E j} j= M for all M Ω which implies E j M for all M Ω which implies E j M(E).

Remark. M(E) is called the σ algebra generated by E. Definition. Let (, T ) be a topological space. The σ algebra generated by T is called the Borel σ algebra on and is denoted B. The members of a Borel σ algebra are called Borel sets. Proposition (p 22). B R is generated by each of the following:. E = {(a, b) : a < b} 2. E 2 = {[a, b] : a < b} 3. E 3 = {(a, b] : a < b} or E 4 = {[a, b) : a < b} 4. E 5 = {(a, ) : a R} or E 6 = {(, a) : a R} 5. E 7 = {[a, ) : a R} or E 8 = {(, a] : a R} Proof. In text. Remark. The Borel σ algebra on R is B R = {E R : E R B R }. It can be generated by E = {(a, ] : a R}. Proposition 2. If (, M) is a measurable space and f : R, then TFAE. f is measurable 2. f ((a, )) M for all a R 3. f ([a, )) M for all a R 4. f ((, a)) M for all a R 5. f ((, a]) M for all a R Proposition 3 (p 43). Let (, M) and (Y, N ) be measurable spaces. If N is generated by E P(Y), then f : Y is (M, N ) measurable if and only if f (E) M for all E E. Proof. ( ) Since E N, if f is measurable then f (E) M for all E E by definition. ( ) Define O = {E Y : f (E) M}. Want to show O is a σ algebra. Then since E O and N is generated by E, we will be able to conclude N O. Recall (p4 of text) f (E C ) = [f (E)] C and f ( E j ) = f (E j ). Claim: O is a σ algebra. Proof:. Since f ( ) = and f (Y) = f ( C ) = (f ( )) C = ( ) C = M, we have, Y O. 2. Suppose F O. Then f (F ) M by definition of O and f (F C ) = [f (F )] C M since M is a σ algebra. 3. Suppose {F j } j= O. Then {f (F j )} j= M and f ( j= F j) = j= f (F j ) M as M is a σ algebra. Thus j= F j O. Hence O is a σ algebra on Y, which contains E. Then N O implies f is measurable. Definition. Let be a nonempty set and let {Y α, N α } be a family of measurable spaces. If f α : Y α is a map for all α A (some index set), then the σ algebra on generated by {f α } α A is the unique smallest σ algebra on that makes each f α measurable. It is generated by {f (E) : α A and E N α }. Proposition 4. If (, M) is a measurable space, then f : R is measurable if and only if f ((a, ]) M. Theorem 3. Let (, M) be a measurable space, let Y, Z be topological spaces. Let φ : Y Z be a continuous function. If f : Y is (M, B Y ) measurable, then φ f is (M, B Z ) measurable.

Proof. By definition, we need to check (φ f) (E) M for all E B Z. By Proposition 3, we need only to check (φ f) (E) M for all E open in Z. Let E be open in Z. Then φ (E) is open in Y since φ is continuous. Since f is (M, B Y ) measurable and φ (E) is open in Y, we have f (φ (E)) M. Fact. If V is an open set in R 2, then there exists a family {R j } j= of open rectangles in R2 satisfying. R j V for all j =, 2, 3... 2. j= R j = V Proposition 5. Let (, M) be a measurable space. Let u, v : R be (M, B R ) measurable. If φ : R 2 R is continuous, then h : R defined by h(x) = φ(u(x), v(x)) is (M, B R ) measurable. Proof. Define f : R 2 by f(x) = (u(x), v(x)). Since h = φ f and φ is continuous, by Theorem 3 it is enough to show that f is (M, B R 2) measurable. First we show that if R R 2 is an open rectangle, then f (R) M. Let (a, b), (c, d) R be open intervals such that R = {(y, z) R 2 a < y < b, c < z < d}. If (u(x), v(x)) R, then u(x) (a, b) and v(x) (c, d) implies x u ((a, b)) v ((c, d)). Hence f (R) = u ((a, b)) v ((c, d)). Since u, v are (M, B R ) measurable, we see f (R) M as M is closed under countable intersections. Now let V be an open ( set in R 2. By the above fact, there is a family {R j } j= of open rectangles such that ) R j = V. So f (V) = f R j = f (R j ) M. Thus f is (, B R 2) measurable. By Theorem 3, h = φ f is (, B R ) measurable. Proposition 6 (p45). Let (, M) be a measurable space. If c R and f, g : R are (M, B R ) measurable, then. cf is (M, B R ) measurable 2. f + g is (M, B R ) measurable 3. fg is (M, B R ) measurable Proof.. Define φ : R R by φ(y) = cy. Then φ f = cf and by Theorem 3, cf is measurable. 2. Define φ : R 2 R by φ(y, z) = y + z. Then φ(f, g) = f + g and since φ is continuous, by Proposition 5, f + g is measurable. 3. Define φ : R 2 R by φ(y, z) = yz. Then φ(f, g) = fg and since φ is continuous, by Prop 5, fg is measurable. Note. In the above proposition, points () and (2) imply its a vector space and adding on point (3) implies it is an algebra. Also, the proposition is true if we consider f, g : R. Proposition 7. If {f j } j= is a sequence of R valued measurable functions on (, M) then g (x) = sup j f j (x) g 2 (x) = inf j f j (x) g 3 (x) = lim sup j f j (x) g 4 (x) = lim inf j f j (x) are all (M, B R ) measurable. Moreover, if f(x) = lim j f j(x) exists for all x, then f is measurable. Proof. Let a R be given. Then {x : g (x) > a} = since f j is measurable. Thus g is measurable. Also {x : g 3 (x) > a} = j= k=j {x : f j (x) > a} implies g ((a, ]) = f j ((a, ]) M j= j= k=j {x : f k (x) > a} implies g ((a, ]) = f k ((a, ]) M. So g 3 is measurable. Since g 2 (x) = inf j f j (x) = sup j f j (x) and g 4 (x) = lim sup f j (x), we see g 2 and g 4 are measurable. Corollary. If f, g : R are measurable functions, then max{f, g} and min{f, g} are also measurable. 3

Corollary 2. If f : R is measurable, then so are f + = max{f, 0} and f = min{f, 0}. Corollary 3. If f : R is measurable, then so is f = f + + f..2 Simple Functions (Generalized Step Functions) Recall that for E, the characteristic function of E is if x E, χ E (x) = 0 if x / E. Definition (p46). A simple function on is a measurable function whose range consists of a finite number of values in R. If φ is a simple function with range {a,..., a n }, then for all j =, 2,..., n, the set E j = φ (a j ) is measurable. The n standard representation for φ is φ(x) = a j χ Ej (x). j= Theorem 4 (p47). Let (, M) be a measurable space.. If f : [0, ] is a measurable function, then there exists a sequence {φ n } n=0 of simple functions such that 0 φ 0 φ... f φ n (x) f(x) for all x φ n converges uniformly to f on the sets where f is uniformly bounded. 2. If f : C is measurable, there is a sequence {φ n } of simple functions such that 0 φ φ 2 f, φ n f pointwise and φ n f uniformly on any set on which f is bounded. Proof. (of ) For all n = 0,, 2,... and k = 0,,..., 2 2n, set En k = f ((k2 n, (k + )2 n ]) and F n = f ((2 n, ]). Define φ n (x) = 2 2n k=0 k2 n χ E k n + 2 n χ Fn (x). We see that ( En k = f ((k2 n, k + ) ]) ((( 2 n f k + ) )) 2 n, (k + ) 2 n = En+ 2k En+ 2k+ 2 2. On the set En, k we see φ n = k2 n χ E k n and φ n+ = (2k)2 n χ E 2k n+ +(2k +)2 n χ E 2k+ = k2 n χ n+ E 2k n+ +(k + 2 )2 n χ E 2k+. n+ So φ n+ φ n on each En. k Also, we can see φ n+ φ n on F n. Therefore φ n+ φ n. Since φ n f, on each En k we see 0 f φ n (k + )2 n k2 n. It follows that φ n f and on the sets where f is bounded, it converges uniformly (as these sets fall into some E k n.)

Definition. Let (, M) be a measurable space.. A positive measure on M is a function µ : M [0, ] with the properties µ( ) = 0 and if {E j } j= M is a sequence of mutually disjoint sets, then µ = µ(e j ). To avoid trivialities, we assume µ(e) < for some E M. Usually, we refer to a positive measure as just a measure. 2. A measure space is a triple (, M, µ) where µ is a measure on M. Theorem 5. Let (, M, µ) be a measure space. Then. µ( ) = 0 2. (monotonicity) If E, F M and E F, then µ(e) µ(f ). 3. (subadditivity) If {E j } j= M, then µ E j µ(e j ). j= E k j= j= j= 4. (continuity from above) If {E j } j= M and E E 2..., then µ( E j ) = lim j µ(e j ). 5. (continuity from below) If {E j } j= M and E E 2... and µ(e ) <, then µ( E j ) = lim j µ(e j ). Proof.. Since there exists E M such that µ(e) <, we see µ(e) = µ(e ) = µ(e) + µ( ) since E and are disjoint. Now, subtracting µ(e) from both sides, we see µ( ) = 0. 2. Let E, F M such that E F. Then F = E (F \ E). Since E and F \ E are disjoint, we see µ(f ) = µ(e (F \ E)) = µ(e) + µ(f \ E) µ(e). 3. Use Lemma 4. Let {E j } j= M satisfying E E 2 with E 0 =. Define F j = E j \ j k= E k = E j \ E j. By Lemma, j= F j = j= E j. Thus as µ(e 0 ) = 0. 5. Similar µ( E j ) = µ( F j ) = µ(f j ) = µ(e j \ E j ) = µ(e j ) µ(e j ) = lim n µ(e n) Definition.. Let (, M, µ) be a measure space. Then a µ null set, or simply null set, is a set in M that has measure 0. 2. If some statement P is true for all points in except possibly those points in a null set, then we say P holds almost everywhere (a.e.) or we may say P holds for almost every x or P holds µ a.e..3 Integration Let (, M, µ) be a measure space. We set L + = {f : [0, ] : f is measurable}. Definition. Let φ L + be a simple function. Then there exists {a, a 2,..., a n } [0, ) and {E j } n j= M such that φ = n j= a jχ Ej. We define the Lebesgue Integral of φ with respect to µ by φdµ := n j= a jµ(e j ). More generally, if A M is measurable, then we define the Lebesgue Integral of φ over A with respect to µ as A φdµ := φχ Adµ = n j= a jµ(e j A).

Definition. Let f L + be any function. Then the Lebesgue Integral of f with respect to µ is { } fdµ = sup φdµ 0 φ f, φ L +, φ is simple. Also, if A M is measurable, then the Lebesgue Integral of f over A with respect to µ is given by A fdµ = fχ Adµ. Proposition 8. Let f, g L + and c [0, ]. Then. If f g, then fdµ gdµ. 2. If A, B M and A B then A fdµ B fdµ. 3. If A M, then A cfdµ = c A fdµ. 4. If f(x) = 0 for all x A M, then fdµ = 0. A 5. If A M and µ(a) = 0, then fdµ = 0. A Proposition 9. Let φ L + be a simple function. Define λ : M [0, ] by λ(e) = φdµ. Then λ is a measure on M. E Proof. Since φ is simple, there exists {a, a 2,..., a n } [0, ) and {E j } n j= M such that φ = n j= a jχ Ej. Let {A k } M be mutually disjoint sets. Then ( ) λ A k k= = = = = = = = φdµ k= A k φχ k= A dµ k ( ( n )) a j µ E j A k ( k= n ) a j µ (E j A k ) j= j= n j= a j k= j= k= k= k= µ(e j A k ) n a j µ(e j A k ) A k φdµ = λ(a k ) k= Theorem 6 (Monotone Convergence Theorem). Let {f n } n= L + be given. Suppose that. f j f j+ for all j =, 2... 2. f(x) = lim n f n (x) for all x Then f L + and fdµ = lim n f ndµ. Proof. Since f(x) = sup n f n (x), by Prop 7, f L +. By Prop 8(), we see { f ndµ} n= [0, ] is a nondecreasing sequence of real numbers and thus by the MCT for R, there exists M [0, ] such that lim n f ndµ = M. Since f n f for all n, Prop 8() also tells us f ndµ fdµ. Thus M fdµ. Thus we just need to show M fdµ. Let α (0, ) and φ L + be a simple function such that 0 φ f. Set E n := {x f n (x) αφ(x)}. Since f j f j+, we see E E 2. Since αφ f, we also have n=e n =. Thus f n dµ f n dµ α φdµ. () E n E n

By Prop 9 and Thm 5(4), lim n E n φdµ = φdµ. Thus, taking the limit of Equation M = lim n f ndµ α φdµ. By definition of the Lebesgue Integral for f, taking the sup over φ and α gives us M fdµ. Proposition 0. Let φ, ψ L + be simple functions. Then (φ + ψ)dµ = φdµ + ψdµ. Proof. Let n j= a jχ Ej and m k= b kχ Fk be the standard representations for φ and ψ respectively. Clearly, E j = m k= (E j F k ) for each j and F k = n j= (E j F k ) for each k. So (φ + ψ)dµ = = = = = n m (a j + b k )µ(e j F k ) j= k= n m a j j= j= µ(f k E j ) + k= m n b k k= j= µ(f k E j ) k= ( n m ) m n a j µ F k E j + b k µ F k E j n m a j µ(e j ) + a k µ(f k ) j= k= φdµ + ψdµ k= j= Theorem 7. If {f n } n= L + and f(x) = f n (x) for all x, then fdµ = f n dµ. n= n= Proof. First we will show for a sum of two functions, then n functions, then an infinite series of functions. So let f, f 2 L +, then by Theorem 4, there exists {φ j } j=, {ψ j} j= L+ such that φ j, ψ j are simple with 0 φ φ 2... f and 0 ψ ψ 2... f 2 lim φ j = f and lim ψ j = f 2. From these it follows that 0 φ + ψ φ 2 + ψ 2... f + f 2 lim φ j + ψ j = f + f 2. By the Monotone Convergence Theorem and Proposition 0, (f + f 2 )dµ = lim j (φ j + ψ j )dµ = lim φ j dµ + ψ j dµ = f dµ + f 2 dµ j Using Induction, we can show for n functions. To show for an infinite series, note that 0 lim f n n= N n= 2 f n... n= N f n (x) = f(x) n= Thus, applying the Monotone Convergence Theorem again, we see f n fdµ = lim N N f n dµ = lim n= N N n= f n dµ = n= f n dµ. Lemma (Fatou s Lemma- P.52). If {f n } n= L +, then (lim inf f n)dµ lim inf f ndµ.

Proof. Define g k (x) = inf f n(x) for all k and for all x. By Proposition 7, g k L + for all k. Also (g k ) k= is a monotone n k sequence with g(x) := lim g k(x) = lim inf f n(x). By the Monotone Convergence Theorem, k n We also see lim g k dµ = k lim k g k dµ = lim inf k lim g kdµ = k lim inf n f ndµ. g k dµ lim inf f k dµ k since g k f k for all k. Combining these two equations, we get what we wanted. Proposition (P 5). If f L +, then fdµ = 0 if and only if f = 0 a.e. Proof. First, we will show for simple functions. Let φ L + be a simple function and say φ = n j= a jχ Ej. Suppose φ = 0 a.e. Then either a j = 0 or µ(e j ) = 0 for all j =,..., n. Thus φdµ = n j= a jµ(e j ) = 0. Now suppose φdµ = 0. Then a j µ(e j ) = 0 for all j =,..., n, which implies either a j or µ(e j ) = 0 for all j. Thus φ = 0 a.e. Now let f L +. Suppose f = 0 a.e. Then for all simple φ L + such that 0 φ f, φ = 0 a.e. Then φdµ = 0 and by the definition of a Lebesgue Integral, fdµ = sup{ φdµ : φ L+, 0 φ f, and φ is simple} = 0. Now suppose f 0 a.e. Then for sufficiently large n, µ({x : f(x) > n }) > 0. Set E = {x : f(x) > n }. Then µ(e) > 0. Consider the simple functions n χ E. We see 0 n χ E f. By Proposition 8(), fdµ n χ Edµ = µ(e) > 0. n Remark. This shows for f L +, the Lebesgue Integral does not see values of f on the null sets. Corollary 4. If {f n } n= L + and lim inf f n(x) f(x) a.e. with f L +, then fdµ lim inf n n Proof. Set E = {x : lim inf f n (x) < f}. By hypothesis, µ(e) = 0. Thus we have lim inf n f nχ E C fχ E C for all x, and ( ) fχ E = 0 a.e. implies fχ E dµ = 0. Using these together with Fatou s Lemma, we see ( ) lim inf f ndµ lim inf f nχ E C dµ by Proposition 8() lim inf f nχ E C dµ by Fatou fχ EC dµ by Proposition 8() and ( ) = fχ E C dµ + fχ Edµ by Prop = fχ E C + fχ Edµ by ( ) = fdµ. f n dµ. Definition. Let (, M, µ) be a measure space. Then the measure µ is complete if whenever E M is a nullset, we find F M for all F E. Note. If µ is complete, then for E M with µ(e) = 0 and F E, we must have µ(f ) = 0. Theorem 8. Suppose (, M, µ) is a measure space. Set N = {N N µ(n) = 0} and M = {E F E M, F N for some N N }. Then M is a σ algebra and there exists a unique extension of µ to a measure µ on M. Say µ is the completion of µ.

Proof.. Clearly, M. 2. Let G M. Want to show G C M. Find E M and F N N such that G = E F. Define N = N \ E and F = F \ E. Then G = E F and E N = E F =. Also F N N. Then E F = E F = (E N C ) F = ((E N) N C ) ((E N) F ) = (E N) (N C F ). So G C = (E F ) C = [(E N) (N C F )] C = (E N) C (N C F ) C = (E N) C (N F C ). Now E N M which implies (E N) C M. Also N F C N. So G C M by definition. 3. If {G j } j= M, then there exists {E j} j= M and {N j} j= M and {F j} j= such that F j N j and G j = E j F j. Then G j = E j F j =. Notice that F j N j and µ( N j ) µ(n j ) = 0. So j= j= F j N N. So G j M. j= j= E j j= F j Definition. Define µ : M [0, ] by µ(e) = µ(e) for all E M and µ(e F ) = µ(e) for all E M and F N N. Notes.. µ defines a measure. (prove) 2. µ is well-defined and unique. Well-defined: Suppose E F = E 2 F 2 with E, E 2 M and F N N, F 2 N 2 N. Then µ(e F ) = µ(e ) µ(e 2 N 2 ) = µ(e 2 ) = µ(e 2 F 2 ). Similarly,. So µ(e F ) = µ(e 2 F 2 ). Unique: Suppose ν : M [0, ] is another completion. Let E F M. Then ν(e F ) ν(e N) = µ(e N) = µ(e) = µ(e F ) = µ(e) = ν(e) ν(e F ). Thus ν(e F ) = µ(e F ). Definition. Let (, M, µ) be a measure space. If E = σ finite. j= E j j= j= with {E j } j= M and µ(e j) < for all j, then E is Proposition 2 (p. 52). If f L + and fdµ <, then {x f(x) = } is a null set and {x f(x) > 0} is a σ finite set. Proof. Set E = {x f(x) = }. Then > fdµ fdµ = µ(e), which implies µ(e) = 0. Also for all j, set E E j = {x f(x) > j }. Then {x f(x) > 0} = E j and > fdµ E j fdµ > j µ(e j), which says µ(e j ) <. Definition. Let (, M, µ) be a measure space. Define L (, M, µ) to be the collection of all measurable functions f : R such that f dµ <. Note. If f is measurable, so is f L + and f = f + + f. Thus f ± dµ f dµ < if f L. Definition. If f L (, M, µ), then f is integrable and define fdµ = f + dµ f dµ. Proposition 3 (p. 53). If f L (, M, µ), then fdµ f dµ. Proof. By Theorem 7, fdµ = f + dµ f dµ f + dµ + f dµ f dµ = f dµ. Proposition 4 (p. 54). If f, g L (, M, µ), then TFAE. E fdµ = gdµ for all E M. E 2. f g dµ = 0

3. f = g a.e. Proof. (2) (3) By Prop (3) (2) If f = g a.e., then f g = 0 a.e. which implies f g = 0 a.e. and thus f g dµ = 0 by Prop. (2) () If f g dµ = 0, then for all E M Thus E fdµ = E gdµ. E fdµ gdµ = (f g)χ E dµ E f g χ E dµ f g dµ = 0. () (3) Contrapositive. Then µ({x f(x) g(x) 0}) > 0. Define E = {x f(x) g(x) > 0} and E 2 = {x f(x) g(x) < 0}. Then either µ(e ), µ(e 2 ) or both are > 0. Suppose µ(e ) > 0. Then (f g)χ E L + and so E (f g)dµ > 0. This implies E fdµ > E gdµ and so() does not hold. Similarly for µ(e 2 ) > 0. Note. We say f and g are related if f = g µ a.e. This defines an equivalence relation between functions in L (, M, µ). Definition. Let (, M, µ) be a measure space. Define L (, µ) to be the collection of all equivalence classes of integrable functions with respect to the relation just described. Notation. If we write f L (µ), then we really mean f is a representative for its equivalence class. Proposition 5 (p.47). Suppose µ is a complete measure. Then. If f is measurable and g = f µ a.e., then g is measurable. 2. If {f n } n= is a sequence of measurable functions and lim n f n (x) = f(x) a.e., then f is measurable. Proposition 6 (p.48). Let (, M, µ) be a measure space and (, M, µ) be its completion. If f : R is (M, B R ) measurable, then there exists an (M, B R ) measurable function g such that f = g µ a.e. Note. We identify L (µ) with L (µ). Definition. Let (, M, µ) be a measure space. Define ρ : L (µ) L (µ) [0, ) by ρ (f, g) = f g dµ where f, g L (, M, µ) are representatives for the equivalence classes f and g. Proposition 7. The function ρ is a metric on L (µ). Proof. Clearly, ρ (f, g) = ρ (g, f). Also if f, g, h L (µ), then ρ (f, g) = f g dµ = f h + h g dµ f h + h g dµ = ρ (f, h) + ρ (h, g). Finally, let f, g L (µ) and f, g L (, M, µ) be representatives for f and g. Then ρ (f, g) = f g dµ = 0 if and only if f = g a.e. which happens if and only if f, g are in the same equivalence class. Definition. If {f n } n= L (µ) and f L (µ) satisfies lim n ρ (f n, f) = 0, then we write f n f in L (µ) and say f n converges (strongly) to f in L (µ). Theorem (Lebesgue s Dominated Convergence Theorem). Let {f n } n= L (µ) be a sequence such that lim f n(x) = n f(x) µ a.e. and there exists g L (µ) such that f n (x) g µ a.e. for all n. Then f L (µ) and fdµ = lim f n dµ. n

Proof. By Propositions 5 and 6, we may assume f is measurable. By hypothesis, we see f(x) g(x) µ a.e. which implies f dµ gdµ <. So f L (µ). Since f n (x) < g(x) µ a.e., we also see that g +f n 0 and g f n 0 µ a.e. for all n. Notice that since lim f n = f µ a.e., lim inf (g + f n)(x) = g(x) + f(x) µ a.e. and lim inf (g f n)(x) = g(x) f(x) n n n µ a.e. By the corollary to Fatou s Lemma (Corollary 4), (g +f)dµ lim inf (g +f n )dµ = gdµ+lim inf f n dµ and n n (g f)dµ lim inf (g f n )dµ = gdµ lim sup n n is obvious, we see they are all = and thus fdµ = lim n f ndµ. f n dµ. Thus lim sup n f n dµ fdµ lim inf n f n dµ. Since Corollary 5. Suppose {f n } n= L (µ) satisfies the hypotheses of the LDC Theorem. Then f n f in L (µ), that is, lim n f n f dµ = 0. Proof. Notice lim n f n (x) f(x) = 0 µ a.e. f n (x) f(x) 2g(x) µ a.e. for all n. Then by the LDC Theorem, f n f dµ = 0dµ = 0. Theorem 9 (p 55). Suppose {f n } n= L (µ) satisfies function f L (µ) and f n dµ = f n dµ. n= n= Proof. Define g(x) = n= f n(x) for all x. By Theorem 7 and our hypotheses g(x)dµ = n= n= f n dµ = f n dµ <. Then n= f n converges µ a.e. to some n= f n dµ <. Then g L (µ). By Proposition 2, n= f n(x) < µ a.e. Hence f n convergence absolutely µ a.e. So we may put f(x) = n= f n(x) for those x where the series converges and f(x) = 0 everywhere else (i.e., on a null set). Moreover, n= f n(x) n= f n(x) g(x) µ a.e. By the LDC Theorem, f L (µ) and lim N N f n (x) = Types of Convergence f n dµ. f n f pointwise if lim n f n(x) = f(x) for all x. f n f a.e. if lim n f n(x) = f(x) µ a.e. fdµ = lim N n= f n f uniformly if for all ɛ > 0 there exists N ɛ such that for all n > N ɛ we have f n f < ɛ for all x. f n f in L if lim f n f dµ = 0. (strong convergence) n f n f in measure if for all ɛ > 0 we have lim n µ({x f n(x) f(x) ɛ}) = 0. Definition. We say that {f n } n= L (µ) is Cauchy in measure if for all ɛ > 0 we have f m (x) ɛ}) = 0. Proposition 8. Suppose {f n } n= L (µ) and f L (µ). If f n f in L, then f n f in measure. Proof. Let ɛ > 0 be given. Set E n = {x f n (x) f(x) ɛ}. Now Thus µ(e n ) = 0. 0 = ɛ lim f n f dµ lim f n f dµ lim ɛdµ = lim n n ɛ E n n ɛ µ(e n) 0. E n n N f n (x) = lim µ({x f n(x) m,n

Theorem 0. Suppose that {f n } n= is a sequence of measurable functions that are Cauchy in measure. Then there exists a measurable function f such that f n f in measure. Proof. Choose {g j } j= = {f n j } j= {f n} j= such that for all j we have µ({x : g j (x) g j+ (x) 2 j }) 2 j. }{{} E j Set F k = j=k E j. Then µ(f k ) j=k µ(e j) 2 j = 2 k. For x F k, we have for all i j k g j (x) g i (x) i l=j g l+(x) g l (x) i l=j 2 l 2 j. It follows that {g j } j= is pointwise Cauchy on F k C for all k. Then there exists f : R such that g j f on Fk C for all k, that is, g j f pointwise on \ ( F k) and f = 0 on the null set. Since µ(f ) = µ(e j ) 2 j = and F F 2 F 3, we find that 0 µ( F k) = lim µ(f k ) lim 2 k = 0. Thus µ( F k) = 0. Thus g j f µ a.e. and by Proposition 5, f is measurable. For each x F j we see g j (x) f(x) lim g j (x) g i (x) + lim g i (x) f(x) lim i i i i l=j i g l+ (x) g l (x) lim i l=j 2 l 2 j. (We know lim g i (x) f(x) = 0 as x F j implies x F i.)thus g j f in measure. Observe f n (x) f(x) f n (x) g j (x) + g j (x) f(x). So if f n (x) f(x) ɛ then either f n (x) g j (x) ɛ 2 g j (x) f(x) ɛ 2. Thus ({ µ ({x : f n (x) f(x) ɛ}) µ x x : f n (x) g j (x) ɛ }) ({ + µ x : g j (x) f(x) ɛ }). 2 2 or So taking the limit of both sides as n, j, we get lim µ({x : f n(x) f(x) ɛ} = 0 n since lim µ ({ x : f n (x) g j (x) ɛ 2}) = 0 for fn is Cauchy in measure and lim µ ({ x : g j (x) f(x) ɛ 2}) = 0 for f n converges in measure. Theorem. Suppose {f n } n= is a sequence of measurable functions such that f n f in measure with f measurable. Then there exists {f nj } j= {f n} n= such that f nj f µ a.e. Proof. Choose a subsequence {f nj } j= such that µ({x C : f n j f 2 j }) }{{} 2 j. Setting F k = j=k E j, µ(f k ) 2 k. E j For x F k and j k we see that f nj (x) f(x) 2 j. It follows that f nj f pointwise in \ k= F k. Thus f nj fµ a.e. since µ( k= F k) = 0. Theorem 2. Suppose {f n } n= is a sequence of measurable functions and f n f and f n g in measure for some measurable f and g. Then f = g µ a.e. Corollary 6. If {f n } n= L (µ) and f L (µ) with f n f in L, then there exists a subsequence {f nj } j= f nj f µ a.e. such that Examples. Take = N, M = P(N), µ(e) = the number of elements in E. (that is, the counting measure). If f L + (µ), then fdµ = f(k) If f L (µ), then k= f(k) = N f dµ <. So k= f(k) is absolutely convergent. Suppose that f n (k) = k n. Then f n(k) 0 pointwise (and thus µ a.e.), but not uniformly (as for all ɛ > 0, k n ɛ when k nɛ) and not in measure (as µ({k N : k n ɛ}) = ) Suppose that f n (k) = n. Then f n(k) 0 pointwise, uniformly, in measure, and µ a.e., but not in L.

k n for k n, Suppose that f n (k) = 2 0 otherwise. Then f n (k) 0 pointwise, uniformly, µ a.e., and in measure, but not in L. Theorem (Egoroff s Theorem). Suppose µ() < and f, f 2,..., f are complex valued and measurable functions on such that f n fa.e. Then for all ɛ > 0 there exists E such that µ(e) < ɛ and f n f uniformly on \ E. Proof. Let N be the set of all points where f n (x) f(x). So µ(n) = 0. For each k, n N, define E n,k = m=n{x \ N : f m (x) f(x) k }. Observe for all k that E n+,k E n,k and n=e n,k =. Since µ(e,k ) µ() <, we may use Theorem 5 to conclude that 0 = µ( n=e n,k ) = lim µ(e n,k ). So for all k there exists n k such that µ(e nk,k) < 2 k ɛ. Set E = N ( k= E n k,k). Then µ(e) µ(n) + µ( E nk,k) ɛ k= 2 k < ɛ. If x E, then for all n > n k, f n (x) f(x) < k, that is, f n f uniformly on \ E..4 L p Spaces Definition. A function F : (a, b) R is convex on (a, b) R if F (λx + ( λ)y) λf (x) + ( λ)f (y) for all λ [0, ] and x, y (a, b). Theorem 3. If F is convex on (a, b) R, then for all [x, y] (a, b) with x < y, we find that there exists M < such that F (s) M for all s [x, y]. Proof. Suppose there does not exist M <. Then for all n N there exists s n [x, y] such that F (s n ) < n. Since [x, y] is compact, there exists a subsequence (call it s n for simplicity) such that s n s for some s [x, y]. Let s [x, y] \ {s } be given. For each λ [0, ), we have F (λs + ( λ)s n ) λf (s) + ( λ)f (s n ) < λf (s) + ( λ)( n). It follows that F (λs + ( λ)s ) = for all λ [0, ). So F (s) = for all s [x, y] \ {s }, which contradicts the fact that F : (a, b) R. Theorem 4. If F is convex on (a, b) R, then F is continuous on (a, b). Proof. We will first prove a claim. Claim: For each x, y, z (a, b) satisfying x < y < z, we have Proof: Let y = λx + ( λ)z with λ = z y z x. Then F (y) F (x) y x < F (z) F (y) z y. as F is convex. This implies and thus Thus F (y) z y z x F (x) + y x z x F (z) F (x) z x z y F (y) y x z y F (z) y x F (x) z y F (z) z x (y x)(z y) F (y). F (y) F (x) y x y x F (y) + z y F (z) z x (y x)(z y) F (y) = y z F (y) + F (z) F (y) z y F (z) = z y. Let [x, y] (a, b) with x < y be given. Then F is uniformly bounded from below by Theorem 3. Let s (x, y) and t (s, y). So x < s < t < y. Then F (s) F (x) s x F (t) F (s) t s F (y) F (t) y t

which implies t s s x t s [F (s) F (x)] + F (s) F (t) y t [F (y) F (t)] + F (s). Since F is uniformly bounded, the RHS does not blow up, so as t s we see F (t) F (s). Similarly for t (x, s). Thus lim t s F (t) = F (s). Theorem 5 (Jensen s Inequality). Suppose that (, M, µ) is a measure space with µ() <. If F is a convex function on R and f L (µ), then F ( ) fdµ F fdµ. µ() µ() Proof. Since f L (µ), f dµ <. By Proposition 2, {x : f = + } is a nullset. So WLOG we may assume f is R valued (just redefine it to be 0 on the nullset). Put t = µ() fdµ. For each s (, t) and u (t, ), the claim above gives us F (t) F (s) F (u) F (t). t s u t F (t) F (s) Let β = sup s. Then β F (t) F (u) t u t s F (u) F (t) u t which implies F (u) F (t) + β(u t) for u (t, ). If u (, t), then β by definition of supremum. Thus F (t) F (u) + β(t u) which implies F (u) F (t) + β(u t). Let u = f(x). Then F (f(x)) is measurable and F (f(x)) F (t) + β(f(x) t) which implies F (f(x))dµ ( ) ( ) F (t)dµ + β f(x)dµ tdµ = F (t)µ() + β f(x)dµ tµ(). Note that if F (f(x)) is not in L then it integrates to, in which case this inequality is still true. Substituting the value for t, we see F (f(x))dµ F ( µ() ) fdµ µ(). Let = [n], M = P(), µ(k) = a k where n k= a k = and a k > 0. So fdµ = f(k)a k. Put F = e t, which is convex on R. Then by Jensen s Inequality, since µ() =, we have ( ) ( ) exp f(k)ak = exp fdµ e f dµ = a k exp(f(k)). Put y k = e f(k), that is, f(k) = ln y k. Then exp( ln y a k k ) a k exp(ln y k ) which implies n k= y a k n k = a k y k. Theorem (Young s Inequality). Let p + q = with p, q >. Then ab p a p + q b q. Proof. Use the above with α = p, α 2 = q, y = a p, y 2 = b p. Theorem (Hölder s Inequality). Let p + q = with p, q >. Let f, g L+. Then k= ( fgdµ ) /p ( f p dµ g q dµ) /q. Proof. If f p dµ = 0, then f = 0 a.e. which implies fg = 0 a.e. and thus fgdµ = 0. Similarly if g q dµ = 0. So assume f p dµ, g q dµ > 0. If f p dµ = or g q dµ =, the inequality is clear. So assume 0 < f p dµ, g q dµ <.Put F = f ( f p dµ ) /p and G = g ( gq dµ ) /q.

Observe F p dµ = f p dµ f p dµ =. Similarly, G q dµ =. Using Young is Inequality, So F Gdµ fg ( f p dµ) /p ( g q dµ) /q dµ which implies p F p dµ + q Gq dµ = p F p dµ + q G q dµ = p + q =. ( fgdµ ) /p ( f p dµ g q dµ) /q. Theorem (Minkowski s Inequality). Suppose p. Let f, g L + be given. Then ( /p ( (f + g) dµ) p /p ( f dµ) p + g p dµ) /p. Proof. If p =, then it is trivial. So assume p >. Then (f + g) p dµ = f(f + g) p dµ + g(f + g) p dµ ( f p dµ) /p ( (f + g) p dµ) p /p + ( g p dµ) /p ( (f + g) p dµ) p /p. If (f + g) p dµ = 0, clear. If it is then (f + g) p = 2 p ( 2 f + 2 g)p 2 p f p + 2 p g p = 2 p (f p + g p ) (since x p is convex) which implies one of f p and g p is. Thus we can divide by ( (f + g) p dµ) p /p to get Minkowski s Inequality. Definition. For each p [, ) and each measurable function f, define f p = ( f p dµ) /p and f = ess sup x f(x) = {a 0 : µ({x : f(x) > a}) = 0} (where inf =. This is called the essential supremum. Definition. For each p [, ] define L p (, µ) = {f L (µ) : f p < }..5 Normed Vector Spaces Let K denote R or C. Recall that a vector space is a set of elements with addition and scalar multiplication. By a subspace, we mean a vector subspace of. If x, denote by Kx the subspace {kx : k K}. If M and N are subspaces of, then M N = {x + y : x M, y N }. Definition. A seminorm on is a function : [0, ) such that x + y x + y for all x, y. λx = λ x for all x and λ K. If also satisfies x = 0 if and only if x = 0 then is called a norm on. A pair (, ) is called a normed vector space. Examples. R n is a VS and the function x p = ( n k= x k p ) /p for p [, ) is a norm. So is x = max{ x, x 2,..., x n }. For each p [, ], the space L P (µ) is a VS and the function p is a norm on L p. Fact. If (, ) is a NVS, then ρ (x, y) = x y for x, y is a metric on. The topology induced by this metric is called the norm (or strong) topology.

Definition. If ρ is a metric on a set, the topology induced by ρ is generated by E = {U : there exists ɛ > 0, x such that ρ(y, x) < ɛ for all y U}. (In Euclidean Space, these are the open balls of radius ɛ.) If E P(), then the smallest topology T (E) containing E is called the topology generated by E. Note. Each set in E is open in the topology generated by E by definition. Definition. Two norms and are equivalent if there exists constants 0 < c, c 2 < such that c x x c 2 x for all x. Examples. If = R n, then for all p, q [, ], the norms p and q are equivalent. If = R N (that is, the space of infinite sequences of real numbers), then for each p q [, ), the norms p and q are not equivalent. Definition. If (, ) is a NVS that is complete with respect to ρ, then we say that (, ), or just, is a Banach Space. Definition. Let {x n } n= be given. The series n= x N n converges to x if lim N n= x n = x (i.e., lim N N n= x n x = 0). The series x n is absolutely convergent if n= x n <. Theorem 6 (p. 52). A NVS (, ) is complete if and only if every absolutely convergent series is convergent. Proof. ( ) Suppose (, ) is complete. Let {x n } n= such that n= x n <. Then for all N we can define S N = N n= x n. Want to show S N is Cauchy. Let M > N be given. Then S M S N = M N+ x n M N+ x n 0 as M, N. Thus {S N } N= is a Cauchy Sequence in and since is complete there exists x such that lim N S N x = 0. Thus n= x n converges to x. ( ) Suppose every absolutely convergent series converges. Let {x n } n= be a Cauchy Sequence. Select a subsequence {x nj } j= such that for all j and n, m n j, we have x n x m < 2 j. Put y = x n and y j = x nj x nj for all j >. Then x nk = k j= y j. Also, y j = y + y j = x n + x nj x nj x n + 2 j x n + <. j= j=2 j=2 J Then, by hypothesis, there exists x such that lim J j= y j = x. Then lim J x nj = x. Of course x n x x n x nj + x nj x and for n n j, x n x nj 2 j and x nj x 0. Thus x n x 0. Corollary 7. If (, M, µ) is a measure space, then (L (µ), ) is a Banach Space. Theorem 7 (p. 83). For p [, ], the space (L P (µ), p ) is a Banach Space. Proof. Case : p [, ). Suppose that {f k } k= Lp (µ) satisfying k= f k <. Put A p = f k p p and G n = n f k, with G = f k. Clearly, G p < Gp 2 < < Gp and by Minkowski s inequality G n p p = By the Monotone Convergence Theorem, ( n p f k ) dµ n f k p dµ = j=2 n f k p p A p. ( n p lim G ( n p ( ) p n p p = lim f k ) dµ = lim f k ) dµ = f k dµ = G p p A p < n n

since G n p p A p for all n. This implies that ( f k ) p < a.e. and so f k < a.e. Thus for almost every N x there exists F (x) < such that F (x) = lim N f k(x). Define F (x) = 0 for those x where the sum is infinite. We need to show F L p (µ) and lim F N f k = 0. We have p F p dµ = f k (x) dµ ( ) p f k dµ = G p p A p <. Thus F L p (µ). Finally, for all n, F n f k p = n+ f k p ( f k ) p = G L. Also lim n F (x) f k (x) = 0 a.e. So by the Dominated Convergence Theorem, Thus by Theorem 6, L p (µ) is complete. lim F n f k p p = lim n n F n f k p dµ = 0. Case 2: p =. Let {f k } L (µ) satisfying f k <. For each k, set A k = {x : f k (x) > f k }. By the definition of, each A k is a null set. Also A = A k is a null set. For each x \ A, f k(x) f k <. So there exists F such that F (x) = f k(x) < for all x \ A. Put F (x) = 0 for all x A. N So F = lim N f k(x) µ a.e. Now for x \ A, F (x) = f k(x) f k(x) f k <. So F L as µ(a) = 0. Finally since f k <. lim F n f k = lim f k lim n n n+ n n+ f k = 0 Proposition 9. Let S = {simple functions on }. For each p [, ], the set S L P is dense in L P. Proof. The case p = is covered by Theorem 4. Suppose p [, ) and let f L p (µ) be given. Want to find a sequence {f n } n= S L p such that lim n f n f p = 0. By Theorem 4 (applied to f + and f ), there exists a sequence {f n } n= S such that f n f and lim n f n (x) = f(x) for all x. Since f L p, we find that f n p dµ f p dµ < which implies f n L p for all n. So {f n } n= S L p. Moreover, f n f p ( f n + f ) p 2 p f p L and f n f p 0 for all x. By the LDC, lim n f n f p dµ = 0 which implies lim f n f p = 0. Proposition 20. If p q r, then L p L r L q and f q f λ p f λ q where q = λ p + λ r. Proof. If p = q = r =, trivial. If p < and q = r = then clearly L p L L and if we take λ = 0, then we see f q f r = f 0 p f r. So suppose p, q <. If r =, then ( /q f dµ) q = ( ( q p q = f = f p/q p ) /q f p f q p dµ f p f q p dµ ( f p dµ f p/q. Let λ = p q. If f Lp L, then f p, f <, so f q f λ p f λ ) /q ) /q <. Thus f L q. Now suppose r <. Note

that λq < p. ( /q f dµ) q = = ( ) /q f λq f ( λ)q dµ ( ( f λq ) ) q p/λq ( λq p ) ( ( dµ f ( λ)q) ( ) λ/p ( f p dµ ) λ f r r dµ p p λq ) q ( p λq p ) dµ by Holder s Inequality = f λ p f λ r. By the same argument as above, f L P L implies f L q. Proposition 2. If µ() <, then for all p q, we have L q L p and f p f q µ() p q. Proof. If q <, then ( /p ( ) /p f dµ) p = f p dµ ( ) p ( f p ) q/p q ( p ) ( dµ = f q µ() p q. ) q f q p dµ p ( q p q ) 2 Measure Theory The Lebesgue Measure on R n. Suppose (R n, M, m n ) is a measure space where the measure m n : M [0, ] with M P(R n ) is the unique measure such that ( n ) m n (a k, b k ) = (b k a k ) k= where (a k, b k ) R for all k. What can we say about M if we want to measure all the open boxes (a k, b k )? Since any open set is a countable union of open boxes, all open sets in the usual topology must be in M. The smallest σ algebra M must be the Borel σ algebra. So we want to somehow extend m n from the boxes to all of B R n. Definition. Let. A family of sets C P() is a semialgebra if., C 2. If E, E 2 C, then E E 2 C (and thus all finite intersections are in C). 3. If E C, then there exists a finite sequence {E i } k i= C with E i E j = for all i j such that E C = k i= E i. Examples. The following are semialgebras: I = { open, half-open, closed intervals on R}. I n = {crossproduct of any n elements of I}. Notation. Denote any interval with endpoints a and b by I(a, b). Definition. Let. A family of sets F P() is an algebra if., F 2. If E, E 2 F, then E E 2 F (and thus all finite intersections are in F).

3. If E F, then E C F. Note that by 2 and 3, we are only allowing finite unions to be in F, unlike in a σ algebra. Examples. The following are algebras F(I) = {E R E = l k= I k, I k I, I j I k = for j k}. F(I) n = {E R n E = l k= I k, I k I n, I j I k = for j k}. In general, if C is a semialgebra, then is an algebra. F(C) = { E E = } l E k, E k C, E j E k = for j k k= Definition. Let C P(). A set function µ : C [0, ] is called monotone if for all A, B C satisfying A B, we have µ(a) µ(b). finite additive if {E k } l k= C such that E j E k = and l k= E k C implies µ( l k= E k) = l k= µ(e k). countably additive if {E k } k= C such that E j E k = and k= E k C implies µ( k= E k) = k= µ(e k). countably subadditive if {E k } k= C such that k= E k C implies µ( k= E k) k= µ(e k). st Goal: Given a monotone countably additive set function µ defined on a semialgebra C, we want to extend µ to a monotone countably additive function µ defined on an algebra F(C) generated by C. Proposition 22. Let C P(). Then there exists a unique algebra F(C) P() such that C F(C) and if A P() is an algebra such that C A, then F(C) A. So F(C) is the smallest algebra containing C. Proof. Define F(C) = {A C A P(), A is an algebra}. Definition. Given C P(), the algebra F(C) provided by Prop 22 is called the algebra generated by C. Proposition 23. If C is a semialgebra, then the algebra generated by C is F(C) := {E : E = l k= E k, E j E k =, j k, E k C}. Example. Recall I was a semialgebra. What kind of properties does m : I [0, ] defined by m(i(a, b)) = b a have? It is monotone, finitely additive, countably additive (2 cases: if the union is an interval which is finite or infinite), countably subadditive (by monotonicity, countable additivity and Lemma ). Theorem 8. Suppose µ is a finitely additive and countable subadditive set function on a semialgebra C such that µ( ) = 0. Then there exists a unique countably additive set function µ on F(C) such that µ(e) = µ(e) for all E C. Proof. For all E F(C), by Prop 23, there exists {E k } n k= C such that E = n k= E k and E j E k = if j k. Define µ(e) = n k= µ(e k). Claim : µ is well-defined. Proof : Let E F(C) and suppose there exists {E k } n k= and {F l} m l= C such that E j E k = for j k and F j F l = for j l and n k= E k = E = m l= F l. Then for all l =, 2,..., m, F l = F l E = F l ( n k= E k) = n k= (F l E k ) and for all k =, 2,..., n, E k = E k E = E k ( F l ) = m l= (E k F l ). So µ(e) = n k= µ(e l) = n k= µ( m l= E k F l ) = n k= m l= µ(e k F l ) = m l= n k= µ(e k F l ) = m l= µ( n k= E k F l ) = m l= µ(f l).

Claim 2: µ is finitely additive on F(C). Proof : Suppose {E k } n k= F(C) with E k E j = for j k, then n k= E k F(C) since F(C) is an algebra. By Prop 23, there exists {G r } s r= C such that s r=g r = n k= E k. Also, for all k =, 2,..., n, there exist mutually disjoint {F k,l } m k l= C such that E k = m k l= F k,l. Then for all k =,..., n ( n ) ( s ) E k = E k E k = E k G r = k= r= ( n ) ( n Also for all r =,.., s, G r = G r E k = G r ( n ) µ E k k= Claim 3: µ is countably subadditive. k= ( s ) = µ G r = = s r= m k r= k= l= ( mk l= m k k= l= s µ(g r ) = r= n µ(g r F k,l ) = ) ( s ) F k,l G r = F k,l ) = Proof : Same as above, except replace n with and change the = to. n r= m k k= l= m k l= r= G r F k,l. Now ( s n ) m k µ G r F k,l r= ( k= l= n s ) m k µ G r F k,l = k= r= l= Note that the countable additivity of µ follows from the next theorem (Theorem 9) s (F k,l G r ). n µ(e k ). Theorem 9. Let F be an algebra of sets on and µ : F [0, ] be a set function such that µ( ) = 0. Then µ is countably additive if and only if it is both finitely additive and countably subadditive. Proof. First note that if µ is finitely additive, then (since F is an algebra) for A, B F with A B, we see µ(b) = µ(a B \ A) = µ(a) + µ(b \ A) µ(a). Thus µ is monotone. ( :) Suppose µ is countably additive. Clearly µ is finitely additive as µ( ) = 0. To show subadditive, let {E k } k= F such that k= E k F. By Lemma, there exists a sequence {F k } k= of mutually disjoint sets such that F k = E k. Using countable additivity and monotonicity, we see µ( E k ) = µ( F k ) = µ(f k ) µ(e k ). ( ) Suppose µ is finitely additive and countably subadditive. Let {E k } F be mutually disjoint sets such that E k F. Since µ is countably subadditive, µ( E k ) µ(e k). To show the opposite inequality, we use finite additivity and monotonicity to conclude µ( E k ) µ( n E k ) = n µ(e k) for all n. Taking the limit as n, we get µ( E k ) µ(e k). Thus µ( E k ) = µ(e k). Definition. Suppose A P() is an algebra. A function µ : A [0, ] is called a premeasure if µ( ) = 0 and µ is countably additive. Theorem 8 shows how to construct a premeasure on an algebra, generated from a semialgebra, from a finitely additive countably subadditive function on that semialgebra. Notation. Define Ĩ := {(a, b] : a < b R} {(, b] : b R} {(a, ) : a R} {(, )} { }. Note the σ algebra generated by Ĩ is B R. Also Ĩ is a semialgebra. Proposition 24. Let F : R R be an increasing function. Define µ F : Ĩ [0, ] by µ F ((a, b]) = F (b) F (a), µ F ((, b]) = F (b) lim F (x), µ F ((a, )) = lim F (x) F (a), µ F ((, )) = lim F (x) lim F (x), µ F ( ) = 0. Then µ F is welldefined, finitely additive and monotone. Moreover, if F is right continuous, then µ F is countably x x x x subadditive. Proof. It is clear that µ F is well-defined. Suppose {I k } n k= Ĩ are disjoint. First suppose each I k is of the form (a k, b k ] and n k= (a k, b k ] = (a, b) Ĩ. Then WLOG, assume a = a < b = a 2 < b 2 =... = a n < b n = b. So k= n µ F (I k ) = n µ F ((a k, b k ]) = n F (b k ) F (a k ) = F (b) F (a) = µ F ((a, b]).

Now suppose n k= I k = (, b] Ĩ. WLOG, assume I = (, b ] and I k = (a k, b k ] with b = a 2 < b 2 =... = a n < b n = b. So n µ F (I k ) = µ F (I ) + n 2 µ F ((a k, b k ]) = F (b ) lim x F (x) + F (b n ) F (a 2 ) = F (b n ) lim x F (x) = µ F ((, b]). Similarly, the other cases hold. Thus µ F is finitely additive. Monotonicity follows. Thus we need only to show countable subadditivity in the case that F is right continuous. Suppose I = (a, b] k= I k with {I k } k= Ĩ. Let ɛ (0, b a). For each k, define (a k, b k + δ k ) if I k = (a k, b k ], I k = (, b k + δ k ) if I k = (, b k ], otherwise, I k where δ k satisfies F (b k + δ k ) F (b k ) < ɛ2 k. Now {I k } k= is an open cover for [a + ɛ, b]. Since compact, Heine Borel says there exists a finite subcover, call it {I k }n k= for simplicity. WLOG, assume a + ɛ I. If b I, then b + δ < b and thus [b + δ, b] n k=2 I k. WLOG, assume b + δ I 2. Then a 2 < b + δ. If b I 2, then b 2 + δ 2 < b and so [b 2 + δ 2, b] n k=3 I k. Continue to find m < n such that a < a + ɛ < b + δ < b 2 + δ 2 < < b < b m + δ m, that is, b I m. Note that this also says a i+ < b i + δ i. Now F (b) F (a) = F (b) F (a + ɛ) + F (a + ɛ) F (a) Letting ɛ 0 +, the right continuity of F yields F (b m + δ m ) F (a ) + F (a + ɛ) F (a) = m k= ((F (b k+ + δ k+ ) F (b k δ k )) + F (b + δ ) F (a ) + F (a + ɛ) F (a) m k= ((F (b k+ + δ k+ ) F (a k+ )) + F (b + δ ) F (a ) + F (a + ɛ) F (a) = m k= ((F (b k + δ k ) F (a k )) + F (a + ɛ) F (a) = m k= ((F (b k + δ k ) F (b k ) + F (b k ) F (a k )) + F (a + ɛ) F (a) m k= ɛ2 k + m k= µ F (I k ) + F (a + ɛ) F (a) ɛ + F (a + ɛ) F (a) + m k= µ F (I k ) µ F (I) = F (b) F (a) µ F (I k ). Now suppose I is an infinite interval. If I = (, b], then for each M >, the same argument shows that µ((m, b]) = F (b) F (M) k= µ F (I k ). Now letting M, we see µ F ((, b]) = F (b) lim M F (M) k= µ F (I k ). Similarly for the other cases. Note. It is also the case that µ F is countably additive, but we don t prove that here. For reference, Folland refers to this as µ 0. This is similar to Prop.5 in Folland. Proposition 25. Let F : R R be increasing and right continuous. Define µ F : Ĩ [0, ] as in Proposition 24. Then µ F : F(Ĩ) [0, ] defined by µ F ( n I k ) = n µ F (I k ) whenever {I j } n k= Ĩ satisfies I j I k = for j k is a premeasure on F(Ĩ). Proof. Follows from Prop 23, Thm 8, and Prop 24. Remark. If F = x, then µ F is the usual length of an interval. Proposition 26. Suppose µ : Ĩ [0, ] is finitely additive and µ((a, b]) < for each a, b R. Then there exists an increasing function F : R R such that µ((a, b]) = F (b) F (a) for all (a, b] R. If µ is also countably additive on Ĩ, then F is right continuous and µ F = µ.

µ((0, x]) if x > 0 Proof. For all x R, define F (x) = 0 if x = 0. We want to verify that µ((a, b]) = F (b) F (a) for all (a, b] R. µ((x, 0]) if x < 0 Since µ is finitely additive, if 0 < a < b µ((a, b]) = µ((0, b] \ (0, a]) = µ((0, b]) µ((0, a]) = F (b) F (a). Similarly for a 0 < b and a < b 0. To show F is increasing, note that for 0 < a < b, F (b) F (a) = µ((a, b]) 0. Similarly for the other two cases. Now, suppose µ is countably additive. We want to show F is right continuous. Let x R and {x k } k= (x, ) such that x k x as k and {x k } k= is decreasing. Notice {F (x k)} k= is decreasing and bounded below by F (x), so it converges. Case : Let x > 0. Then Thus F (x) = lim N F (x N+ ). Similarly if x = 0. F (x ) = µ((0, x ]) = µ((0, x]) + µ( k= (x k+, x k ]) Case 2: Let x < 0. Then for some m N we find x m < 0. Then Thus F (x) = lim n F (x n+ ). = F (x) + lim N N µ((x k+, x k ]) = F (x) + lim N N F (x k) F (x k+ ) = F (x) + lim N F (x ) F (x N+ ). F (x) = µ((x, 0]) = (µ((x m, 0]) + µ((x, x m ])) = F (x m ) µ( k=n (x k+, x k ]) = F (x m ) lim n k=n F (x k) F (x k+ ) = F (x m ) F (x m ) + lim F (x n+ ). To show µ = µ F, we need only to compare µ(i) and µ F (I) on infinite intervals. Suppose I = (, ). Then I = k= (( k, k + ] (k, k]). Since µ(i) 0 we have µ(i) = lim n = lim n n µ(( k, k + ]) + µ((k, k]) n F ( k + ) F ( k) + lim n = lim F ( n) + lim F (n) = µ F (I). n n n F (k) F (k ) 2nd Goal: Given a premeasure on an algebra A, we want to extend a measure on the σ algebra generated by A. Intermediate Goal: Approximate measure of any subset of a nonempty using the premeasure on an algebra A. Idea: Recall m : I [0, ] was given by m(i(a, b)) = b a (where I(a, b) is any interval with endpoints a and b) for a, b R. The algebra generated by I is F(I), which is the collection of all finite unions of disjoint intervals in I. The extension of m to m on F(I) is m(e) = n k= (b k a k ) for E = n k= I(a k, b k ), with {I(a k, b k )} n k= mutually disjoint. Now, we want to extend m to a set function that measures any subset of R. Suppose E R. Then we can find at least one countable family {I k } k= F(I) such that E k= I k (take I k = R for all k). Since E k= I k, we expect the measure of E to be m( k= I k) m(i k). So, in general, we want measure of E m(i k ). k=