Notes IV General Equilibrium and Welfare Properties

Similar documents
Second Welfare Theorem

The Fundamental Welfare Theorems

First Welfare Theorem

Differentiable Welfare Theorems Existence of a Competitive Equilibrium: Preliminaries

The Fundamental Welfare Theorems

Introduction to General Equilibrium: Framework.

In the Name of God. Sharif University of Technology. Microeconomics 1. Graduate School of Management and Economics. Dr. S.

The Consumer, the Firm, and an Economy

Market Equilibrium and the Core

Microeconomics II. MOSEC, LUISS Guido Carli Problem Set n 3

1 General Equilibrium

EC487 Advanced Microeconomics, Part I: Lecture 5

Introduction to General Equilibrium

Adding Production to the Theory

Public Economics Ben Heijdra Chapter 9: Introduction to Normative Public Economics

Economics 501B Final Exam Fall 2017 Solutions

Competitive Equilibrium

Economics 101 Lecture 5 - Firms and Production

Notes I Classical Demand Theory: Review of Important Concepts

Regularity of competitive equilibria in a production economy with externalities

The Debreu-Scarf Theorem: The Core Converges to the Walrasian Allocations

Lecture 7: General Equilibrium - Existence, Uniqueness, Stability

1 Jan 28: Overview and Review of Equilibrium

Lecture #3. General equilibrium

Welfare Economics: Lecture 12

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program May 2012

Advanced Microeconomics Problem Set 1

Pareto Efficiency (also called Pareto Optimality)

Microeconomic Theory -1- Introduction

Market Outcomes: Efficient or Fair?

Question 1. (p p) (x(p, w ) x(p, w)) 0. with strict inequality if x(p, w) x(p, w ).

Equilibrium in Factors Market: Properties

The Utility Frontier

Fundamental Theorems of Welfare Economics

Hicksian Demand and Expenditure Function Duality, Slutsky Equation

General Equilibrium. General Equilibrium, Berardino. Cesi, MSc Tor Vergata

Economics 201B Second Half. Lecture 12-4/22/10. Core is the most commonly used. The core is the set of all allocations such that no coalition (set of

ECONOMICS 001 Microeconomic Theory Summer Mid-semester Exam 2. There are two questions. Answer both. Marks are given in parentheses.

Volume 29, Issue 3. Existence of competitive equilibrium in economies with multi-member households

Department of Economics The Ohio State University Final Exam Questions and Answers Econ 8712

Problem Set Suggested Answers

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2016

Notes on General Equilibrium

Problem Set 1 Welfare Economics

Core. Ichiro Obara. December 3, 2008 UCLA. Obara (UCLA) Core December 3, / 22

Positive Theory of Equilibrium: Existence, Uniqueness, and Stability

Alp Simsek (MIT) Recitation Notes: 1. Gorman s Aggregation Th eorem2. Normative Representative November 9, Household Theorem / 16

GARP and Afriat s Theorem Production

Can everyone benefit from innovation?

Economics 101. Lecture 2 - The Walrasian Model and Consumer Choice

Lecture Notes October 18, Reading assignment for this lecture: Syllabus, section I.

Implementation of Marginal Cost Pricing Equilibrium Allocations with Transfers in Economies with Increasing Returns to Scale

Economic Core, Fair Allocations, and Social Choice Theory

problem. max Both k (0) and h (0) are given at time 0. (a) Write down the Hamilton-Jacobi-Bellman (HJB) Equation in the dynamic programming

The Ohio State University Department of Economics. Homework Set Questions and Answers

Short correct answers are sufficient and get full credit. Including irrelevant (though correct) information in an answer will not increase the score.

4 Lecture Applications

Equilibrium and Pareto Efficiency in an exchange economy

General Equilibrium with Production

Firms and returns to scale -1- John Riley

Duality. for The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics, 2nd ed. Lawrence E. Blume

WELFARE: THE SOCIAL- WELFARE FUNCTION

Lecture 2 The Centralized Economy

Competitive Market Mechanisms as Social Choice Procedures

General Equilibrium and Welfare

Microeconomics, Block I Part 1

where u is the decision-maker s payoff function over her actions and S is the set of her feasible actions.

Core equivalence and welfare properties without divisible goods

Mathematical models in economy. Short descriptions

Lecture 1. History of general equilibrium theory

Economic Growth: Lecture 8, Overlapping Generations

Implementation of marginal cost pricing equilibrium allocations with transfers in economies with increasing returns to scale

Patryk Pagacz. Equilibrium theory in infinite dimensional Arrow-Debreu s model. Uniwersytet Jagielloński

E 600 Chapter 4: Optimization

On the (Non-)Differentiability of the Optimal Value Function When the Optimal Solution Is Unique

Macroeconomic Theory and Analysis V Suggested Solutions for the First Midterm. max

Microeconomics I. September, c Leopold Sögner

General equilibrium with externalities and tradable licenses

0 Aims of this course

Macroeconomic Theory and Analysis Suggested Solution for Midterm 1

Microeconomics, Block I Part 2

KIER DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES

Firms and returns to scale -1- Firms and returns to scale

1 Two elementary results on aggregation of technologies and preferences

1 Second Welfare Theorem

Econ 401A: Economic Theory Mid-term. Answers

ECO 317 Economics of Uncertainty Fall Term 2009 Slides to accompany 13. Markets and Efficient Risk-Bearing: Examples and Extensions

Department of Agricultural Economics. PhD Qualifier Examination. May 2009

No Equilibrium in Infinite Economies: Two Examples*

Introductory Microeconomics

Unlinked Allocations in an Exchange Economy with One Good and One Bad

Advanced Microeconomic Theory. Chapter 6: Partial and General Equilibrium

Walras-Lindahl-Wicksell: What equilibrium concept for public goods provision? I - The convex case

Market Failure: Externalities

THE OBJECTIVE OF A PRIVATELY OWNED FIRM UNDER IMPERFECT COMPETITION

Economic Growth: Lectures 5-7, Neoclassical Growth

Short correct answers are sufficient and get full credit. Including irrelevant (though correct) information in an answer will not increase the score.

Graduate Macroeconomics 2 Problem set Solutions

Notes on Consumer Theory

Increasingly, economists are asked not just to study or explain or interpret markets, but to design them.

Transcription:

Notes IV General Equilibrium and Welfare Properties In this lecture we consider a general model of a private ownership economy, i.e., a market economy in which a consumer s wealth is derived from endowments and from claims to profit shares of firms. Denote the claim of consumer i to a share of (the profits of) firm j by θ ij. Then, θ ij [0, 1], and I i=1 θ ij = 1 for all j = 1,..., J. The notes are based on MWG, chapter 16. 1 Basic Model I > 0, J > 0, L > 0, all of them are finite. Consumers are characterized by consumption sets X i R L, and preferences i. Each firm is characterized by a production set Y j R L. Initial endowments are given by a vector ω = ( ω 1,..., ω L ) R LI. Definition 1 An economy, P, is defined by P ({X i, i } I i=1, {Y j } J j=1, { ω i, θ i1,..., θ ij } I i=1). Definition 2 An allocation (x,y) is a consumption vector x i for each consumer i = 1,..., I, and a production vector y j for each firm j = 1,..., J. An allocation is feasible if i x li = ω l + j y l,j for every good l. The set of feasible allocations is denoted by A, where A = {(x, y) : i x li = ω l + j y l,j}. Be aware that the set A lives in R L(I+J) space! Notice the following: The set A is closed and bounded (i.e. compact under the Euclidean topology) if: every X i is closed and bounded below; every Y j is closed, convex, admits the possibility of inaction (0 Y j ), satisfies the no-free-lunch property (there is no y j Y j for which y j 0), and satisfies irreversibility (for any y j 0, y j Y j implies y j is not an element of Y j ). Please study Appendix A in MWG (p. 573 f) carefully to understand the argument. A feasible allocation is Pareto efficient 1 if there is no other allocation (x, y ) A that Pareto dominates it. I.e., if there is no feasible allocation 1 (Pareto) efficient is synonymous to Pareto optimal. However, you should not confuse Pareto optimality with (social) optimality, which is a pretty different concept. In order to clearly distinguish Pareto efficiency from social optimality, we will refer to Pareto efficiency (or Pareto optimality) as efficiency, and we ll refer to social optimality as optimality. Ronald Wendner IV-1 v1.5

(x, y ) such that x i x i for all i, and x i x i for some i. Notice that no price vector is involved in defining Pareto efficiency. Now we ll define a concept, which we ll employ over and over again... Definition 3 (Price Equilibrium with Transfers) Given an economy P, a price vector p and an allocation (x, y ) constitute a price equilibrium with transfers (PET) if there is an assignment of wealth levels (w 1,..., w I ) with i w i = i p ω + j p y j such that (i) for every j, yj maximizes profits in Y j, (ii) for every i, x i is maximal for i in the respective budget set, (iii) i x i = ω + j y j. Please do not hesitate to think about this definition for a while (until tomorrow). In short, a PET comes from optimization and equilibrium. Query. Is a Walrasian equilibrium a PET? Proposition 1 (First Fun Theorem of Welfare Economics) If preferences are locally nonsatiated, and if (p, y, x ) is a PET, then allocation (y, x ) is Pareto efficient. In particular, any Walrasian equilibrium is Pareto efficient. Query. In Proposition 1 we (only) need that i be locally nonsatiated. Show that strong monotonicity implies monotonicity implies local nonsatiation. Second Fun Theorem of Welfare Economics. We ll progress in two steps. First, we ll state a result showing that under convexity assumptions, every Pareto efficient allocation can be supported by a price vector as a price quasiequilibrium with transfers (PQET). Second, we show that under a rather innocent condition ( cheaper consumption condition ), every PQET is a PET. PQET. Define: (ii ): for every i, x i minimizes expenditure on the set {x i X i : x i i x i }, which is the no-worse-than set with respect to x i. Then, Definition 3, where (ii) is replaced by (ii ) defines a PQET. (Again, feel free to rest for a day or two, to contemplate about the meaning of a PQET.) Clearly every PET is a PQET (however, not vice versa), as utility maximization (a consumption bundle being maximal on the budget set) always implies expenditure minimization (a consumption bundle minimizing expenditure on the no-worse-than set). However, the converse may fail to hold if Ronald Wendner IV-2 v1.5

some prices are zero and/or some preferences are not monotone (see Figure 16.D.2 in MWG, p.555). Proposition 2 (Second Fun Theorem of Welfare Economics) Consider an economy P where every production set Y j is convex, every preference relation is convex and locally nonsatiated, and every consumption set is convex. Then, for every Pareto efficient allocation (x, y ) there exists a price vector p such that (x, y, p) is a PQET. Please study the separating hyperplane theorem before working through the proof of Proposition 2 (in MWG, p. 552 ff.). Proposition 3 (Cheaper Consumption Condition) X i is convex and i is continuous. Suppose x i i x i implies p x i w i. Then, if there is a consumption vector x i X i such that p x i < w i (i.e., x i is a cheaper consumption vector for (p, w i )), it holds that x i i x i implies p x i > w i. Corollary 1 Suppose that for every i, X i is convex, 0 X i, and i is continuous. If w 0, then any PQET is a PET. So, Corollary 1 tells us that if w 0, utility maximization is equivalent to expenditure minimization (or alternatively, a PQET is equivalent to a PET). So, under the assumptions of Proposition 2, for every Pareto efficient allocation (x, y ) there exists a price vector p such that (x, y, p) is a PET. 2 Pareto Efficiency and Optimality Consider an economy ({X i, i } I i=1, {Y j } J j=1, ω). Each feasible allocation (x, y) gives rise to a utility vector u i (x i ) for i = 1,..., I. The utility possibility set, U, provides all attainable vectors of utility levels: U = {(u 1,..., u I ) R I : there exists a feasible allocation (x, y) such that u i u i (x i ), i = 1,..., I}. The Pareto frontier, UP, is the set of all vectors in U that are not Pareto dominated: UP = {u U : there is no u U such that u i u i for all i and u i > u i for some i}. Consequently, a feasible allocation (x, y) is Pareto efficient if and only if u(x) UP. Besides efficiency, another normative criterion is optimality. Before discussing optimality, we need to define the concept of a social welfare function (SWF). Ronald Wendner IV-3 v1.5

A social welfare function W (u 1,..., u I ) assigns a social utility value to every vector from the utility possibility set. A special case of a W is the linear social welfare function: W (u 1,..., u I ) = i λ i u i, for some constant welfare weights λ = (λ 1,..., λ I ). In the following, we ll focus on this specification of a social welfare function: W (u) = λ u. Denote the solution of the social welfare maximization problem (SWMP) by u = max u U λ u. u is considered optimal according to the specific SWF. Certainly, different SWF (e.g., different welfare weights) may give raise to different solutions to the SWMP. There exist relations between the normative notions of Pareto efficiency and (social) optimality. If λ >> 0, u UP. This result resembles the First Fun Theorem. If λ >> 0, the solution to a SWMP is Pareto efficient. There is a relation to the Second Fun Theorem as well. If U is convex, then for any ũ UP there is a vector of welfare weights λ 0 such that ũ is a solution to the SWMP. 3 First Order Conditions and Pareto Efficiency Suppose, preferences i can be represented by utility functions that are twice continuously differentiable and are strongly monotone: u i (x i ) 0 at all x i. All firms production frontiers are twice continuously differentiable, with F j (y j ) 0 for all y j R L. For a Pareto efficient allocation, we need to maximize utility of a household without loss of generality, utility of household i = 1 subject to the constraint that utility of all other households are equal to some predetermined level ū i (or, more precisely, must not be smaller than some predetermined level ū i ). Formally: max u 1 (x 11,..., x L1 ) s.t. u i (x 1i,..., x Li ) ū i, x li ω l + y lj, i j F j (y 1j,..., y Lj ) 0. Denote the Lagrange multipliers of these restrictions by (δ i, µ l, γ j ) 0 for i = 2,..., I, l = 1,..., L, j = 1,..., J respectively, and define δ 1 = 1. So, δ i Ronald Wendner IV-4 v1.5

represents the gain in household 1 s utility upon a reduction of ū i by one unit (so, it is an exchange rate between consumer i s and consumer 1 s utilities). Next, µ l shows the rise in household 1 s utility upon a rise in (a) the initial endowment of some good l, and (b) the rise of production of good l (so, it represents consumer 1 s shadow price of good l [= price of good l in terms of consumer 1 s utility]). Finally, γ j represents the shadow cost to household 1 of a tightening of firm j s production constraint (so, it converts a change in F j into units of consumer 1 s utility), by, e.g., a rise in production of y lj. First order conditions: for all x li > 0 : δ i ( u i / x li ) = µ l, (1) µ l = γ j ( F j / y lj ). (2) First order condition (1) considers a marginal increase in the available resource x l (either by an increase of ω l or by an increase of production of good l). If the additional amount of x l is given to consumer 1, its utility rises by µ l. If the additional amount of x l is given to consumer i, its utility rises by ( u i / x li ). So, for given ū i, we can relax consumer i s utility constraint by ( u i / x li ) units. This, however, translates to an increase in consumer 1 s utility by δ i ( u i / x li ) units. In optimum, both consumer 1 s utility gains must be equal. 2 Next, first order condition (2) deals with an increase in production of good l by firm j, y lj, and passing on the additional amount of good l to consumer 1. In doing so, consumer 1 s utility rises by µ l. However, at the same time, firm j must produce less of all other outputs, which incurs losses for consumer 1 in terms of γ j ( F j / y lj ). In optimum, FOC (2) must hold, otherwise consumer 1 s utility could be increased by a change in the production plan of firm j. 2 Otherwise, if δ i ( u i / x li ) > µ l, one could pass on the additional amount of x l to consumer i. Then one could lower consumer i s utility constraint by more than what amounts to consumer 1 s shadow price of x l, and consumer 1 could do better (which contradicts (1) being a solution to the optimization problem. Ronald Wendner IV-5 v1.5

Notice that (1) and (2) also imply a different set of first order conditions: u i / x li u i / x l i F j / y lj F j / y l j u i / x li u i / x l i = u i / x li u i / x l i, (3) = F j / y lj F j / y l j, (4) = F j/ y lj. (5) F j / y l j FOC (3) says that that the marginal rate of substitution between two goods, l and l, is equal among consumers. FOC (4) requires the marginal rate of transformation of l for l to be equal between any firms j and j. Finally, FOC (5) says that, a Pareto efficient allocation is characterized by equality between the marginal rate of substitution of l for l (for any i) and the marginal rate of transformation of l for l (for any j). 4 More on the Basics... Nonconvex Production Technologies and Marginal Cost Pricing Obviously, the Second Fun Theorem runs into trouble when production sets are not convex. However, there is a (weaker) result, paralleling the Second Fun Theorem, for nonconvex production sets. Proposition 4 (Marginal Cost Price Equilibrium with Transfers) Suppose, the basic assumptions of the previous section hold, except for convexity of production sets. Suppose further that appropriate differentiability assumptions hold. Then, if (x, y ) is Pareto efficient, there exists a price vector p = (p 1,..., p L ) and wealth levels (w 1,..., w I ) with i w i = p ω + j p y j such that: (i) For any firm j: p = α j F j (y j ) for some α j > 0, (ii) for any i, x i is maximal for i in the budget set {x i X i : p x i w i }, (iii) i x i = ω + j y j. Notice, that the definition of a marginal cost price equilibrium with transfers closely resembles that of a PET (with the exception of (i)). Query: Suppose there is just one input and one output. What exactly is (i) saying in this case? Ronald Wendner IV-6 v1.5

The Set of Feasible Allocations Suppose that (i) every X i is closed, and bounded below, and (ii) every Y j is closed, and (iii) Y is convex, admits the possibility of inaction, satisfies the free lunch property, and is irreversible. Then, the set of feasible allocations is closed and bounded. Moreover, it is nonempty if we allow for free disposal. 3 3 To be precise:... and, in addition, we can choose ˆx X i for every i such that i ˆx i ω. Ronald Wendner IV-7 v1.5