The Arrow Impossibility Theorem Of Social Choice Theory In An Infinite Society And Limited Principle Of Omniscience

Similar documents
A topological approach to Wilson s impossibility theorem

Arrow s General (Im)Possibility Theorem

On the topological equivalence of the Arrow impossibility theorem and Amartya Sen s liberal paradox

Coalitionally strategyproof functions depend only on the most-preferred alternatives.

A Role of Common Morality in Social Choice

Research Article A Constructive Analysis of Convex-Valued Demand Correspondence for Weakly Uniformly Rotund and Monotonic Preference

Multi-profile intertemporal social choice: a survey

Quasi-transitive and Suzumura consistent relations

Finite Dictatorships and Infinite Democracies

ADJOINTS, ABSOLUTE VALUES AND POLAR DECOMPOSITIONS

Constructive Proof of the Fan-Glicksberg Fixed Point Theorem for Sequentially Locally Non-constant Multi-functions in a Locally Convex Space

Note on social choice allocation in exchange economies with Cobb-Douglas preferences

Social Choice Theory. Felix Munoz-Garcia School of Economic Sciences Washington State University. EconS Advanced Microeconomics II

Antonio Quesada Universidad de Murcia. Abstract

13 Social choice B = 2 X X. is the collection of all binary relations on X. R = { X X : is complete and transitive}

Constructive (functional) analysis

Lecture Notes, Lectures 22, 23, 24. Voter preferences: Majority votes A > B, B > C. Transitivity requires A > C but majority votes C > A.

Arrow s Paradox. Prerna Nadathur. January 1, 2010

JUDGMENT AGGREGATORS AND BOOLEAN ALGEBRA HOMOMORPHISMS

Comparing impossibility theorems

Constructive analysis

Strategic Manipulability without Resoluteness or Shared Beliefs: Gibbard-Satterthwaite Generalized

Microeconomic foundations of representative agent models by means of ultraproducts

Coalitional Structure of the Muller-Satterthwaite Theorem

Constructive (functional) analysis

Social Choice. Jan-Michael van Linthoudt

CONVEXITY AND OSCULATION IN NORMED SPACES

Follow links for Class Use and other Permissions. For more information send to:

Non-deteriorating Choice Without Full Transitivity

Arrovian Social Choice with Non -Welfare Attributes

Arrow s Theorem as a Corollary

A General Impossibility Result on Strategy-Proof Social Choice Hyperfunctions

Separating Variants of LEM, LPO, and MP

Non-Manipulable Domains for the Borda Count

Approximation Algorithms and Mechanism Design for Minimax Approval Voting 1

Whitney topology and spaces of preference relations. Abstract

1 Introduction FUZZY VERSIONS OF SOME ARROW 0 S TYPE RESULTS 1. Louis Aimé Fono a,2, Véronique Kommogne b and Nicolas Gabriel Andjiga c

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 24: Decisions in Groups

Two Factor Additive Conjoint Measurement With One Solvable Component

THREE BRIEF PROOFS OF ARROW S IMPOSSIBILITY THEOREM JOHN GEANAKOPLOS COWLES FOUNDATION PAPER NO. 1116

Preference and Utility

TitleNo-Envy, Efficiency, and Collective.

Approximation Algorithms and Mechanism Design for Minimax Approval Voting

APPLIED MECHANISM DESIGN FOR SOCIAL GOOD

Social Welfare Functions that Satisfy Pareto, Anonymity, and Neutrality: Countable Many Alternatives. Donald E. Campbell College of William and Mary

"Arrow s Theorem and the Gibbard-Satterthwaite Theorem: A Unified Approach", by Phillip Reny. Economic Letters (70) (2001),

Expected utility without full transitivity

arxiv: v2 [math.co] 14 Apr 2011

GROUP DECISION MAKING

Efficiency and converse reduction-consistency in collective choice. Abstract. Department of Applied Mathematics, National Dong Hwa University

Separable Discrete Preferences

On the relation between Sion s minimax theorem and existence of Nash equilibrium in asymmetric multi-players zero-sum game with only one alien

The Uniform Distributions Puzzle

Stat 451: Solutions to Assignment #1

The Axiomatic Method in Social Choice Theory:

Online Appendix to Strategy-proof tie-breaking in matching with priorities

Abstract Arrowian Aggregation *

OUTER MEASURE AND UTILITY

Strategy-Proofness on the Condorcet Domain

MATHEMATICAL ENGINEERING TECHNICAL REPORTS. Induction of M-convex Functions by Linking Systems

AN IMPOSSIBILITY THEOREM IN MATCHING PROBLEMS

Utility Representation of Lower Separable Preferences

Hans Peters, Souvik Roy, Ton Storcken. Manipulation under k-approval scoring rules RM/08/056. JEL code: D71, D72

Rationality and solutions to nonconvex bargaining problems: rationalizability and Nash solutions 1

Arrow s Impossibility Theorem and Experimental Tests of Preference Aggregation

A Note on the McKelvey Uncovered Set and Pareto Optimality

Algorithmic Game Theory and Applications

Approval Voting for Committees: Threshold Approaches

First-Order Logic Formalisation of Impossibility Theorems in Preference Aggregation

Theories of justice. Harsanyi s approach, Rawls approach, Unification

Probabilistic Aspects of Voting

The uniform distributions puzzle

Dependence and Independence in Social Choice Theory

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved.

Near convexity, metric convexity, and convexity

Michel Le Breton and John A. Weymark

Paretian evaluation of infinite utility streams: an egalitarian criterion

Existence Theorems of Continuous Social Aggregation for Infinite Discrete Alternatives

Introduction to Formal Epistemology Lecture 5

The Beach Party Problem: An informal introduction to continuity problems in group choice *

Chaitin Ω Numbers and Halting Problems

A Systematic Approach to the Construction of Non-empty Choice Sets

COUNTABLY COMPLEMENTABLE LINEAR ORDERINGS

Talking Freedom of Choice Seriously

DIFFERENCE DENSITY AND APERIODIC SUM-FREE SETS. Neil J. Calkin Department of Mathematical Sciences, Clemson University, Clemson, SC 29634, USA

INTEGER PROGRAMMING AND ARROVIAN SOCIAL WELFARE FUNCTIONS

The Non-Existence of Representative Agents

arxiv:math/ v1 [math.gr] 24 Oct 2005

MATH 31BH Homework 1 Solutions

A MAXIMAL DOMAIN FOR STRATEGY-PROOF AND NO-VETOER RULES IN THE MULTI-OBJECT CHOICE MODEL

Math 421, Homework #6 Solutions. (1) Let E R n Show that = (E c ) o, i.e. the complement of the closure is the interior of the complement.

On the Chacteristic Numbers of Voting Games

Strategy-proof allocation of indivisible goods

A Constructive Examination of Rectifiability

Partial lecture notes THE PROBABILITY OF VIOLATING ARROW S CONDITIONS

Political Economy of Institutions and Development. Lectures 2 and 3: Static Voting Models

3.1 Arrow s Theorem. We study now the general case in which the society has to choose among a number of alternatives

The Tale of the Tournament Equilibrium Set. Felix Brandt Dagstuhl, March 2012

FAIR REALLOCATION IN ECONOMIES WITH SINGLE-PEAKED PREFERENCES

Economics Bulletin, 2012, Vol. 32 No. 1 pp Introduction. 2. The preliminaries

Transcription:

Applied Mathematics E-Notes, 8(2008), 82-88 c ISSN 1607-2510 Available free at mirror sites of http://www.math.nthu.edu.tw/ amen/ The Arrow Impossibility Theorem Of Social Choice Theory In An Infinite Society And Limited Principle Of Omniscience Yasuhito Tanaka Received 2 February 2007 Abstract This paper is an attempt to examine the main theorems of social choice theory from the viewpoint of constructive mathematics. We examine the Arrow impossibility theorem ([1]) in a society with an infinite number of individuals (infinite society). We will show that the theorem that there exists a dictator or there exists no dictator for any binary social choice rule satisfying transitivity, Pareto principle and independence of irrelevant alternatives in an infinite society is equivalent to LPO (Limited principle of omniscience). Therefore, it is non-constructive. A dictator is an individual such that if he strictly prefers an alternative to another alternative, then the society must also strictly prefer the former to the latter. 1 Introduction This paper is an attempt to examine the main theorems of social choice theory from the viewpoint of constructive mathematics 1. Arrow s impossibility theorem ([1]) shows that, with a finite number of individuals, for any social welfare function (transitive binary social choice rule) which satisfies Pareto principle and independence of irrelevant alternatives (IIA) there exists a dictator. A dictator is an individual such that if he strictly prefers an alternative to another alternative, then the society must also strictly prefer the former to the latter. On the other hand, [5], [6] and [7] show that, in a society with an infinite number of individuals (infinite society), there exists a social welfare function satisfying Pareto principle and IIA without dictator 2. In this paper we will show that the theorem that there exists a dictator or there exists no dictator for any social welfare function satisfying Pareto principle and IIA in an infinite society is equivalent to LPO (Limited principle of omniscience). Therefore, it is non-constructive. Mathematics Subject Classifications: 03F65, 91B14. Faculty of Economics, Doshisha University, Kamigyo-ku, Kyoto, 602-8580, Japan. 1 In other papers, for example [13], we study the relationships of some other theorems of social choice theory with LPO. 2 [14] is a recent book that discusses social choice problems in an infinite society. 82

Y. Tanaka 83 The omniscience principles are general statements that can be proved classically but not constructively, and are used to show that other statements do not admit constructive proofs 3. This is done by showing that the statement implies the omniscience principle. The strongest omniscience principle is the law of excluded middle. A weaker one is the following limited principle of omniscience (abbreviated as LPO). LPO (Limited principle of omniscience) Given a binary sequence a n, n N, where N is the set of positive integers, either a n = 0 for all n or a n = 1 for some n. In the next section we present the framework of this paper and some preliminary results. In Section 3 we will show the following results. 1. There exists a dictator or there exists no dictator for any social welfare function satisfying Pareto principle and IIA, and in the latter case all co-finite sets of individuals (sets of individuals whose complements are finite) are decisive sets (Theorem 1). 2. Theorem 1 is equivalent to LPO (Theorem 2). A decisive set is a set of individuals such that if individuals in the set prefer an alternative (denoted by x) to another alternative (denoted by y), then the society prefers x to y regardless of the preferences of other individuals. 2 The framework and preliminary results There are more than two (finite or infinite) alternatives and a countably infinite number of individuals. The set of individuals is denoted by N. The set of alternatives is denoted by A. N and A are discrete sets 4. For each pair of elements i, j of N we have i = j or i j, and for each pair of elements x, y of A we have x = y or x y. Each subset of N is detachable. Thus, for each individual i of N and each subset I of N we have i I or i/ I. The alternatives are represented by x,y,z,w and so on. Denote individual i s preference by i. We denote x i y when individual i prefers x to y. Individual preferences over the alternatives are transitive weak orders, and they are characterized constructively according to [2]. About given three alternatives x, y and z individual i s preference satisfies the following properties. 1. If x i y, then (y i x). 2. If x i y, then for each z A either x i z or z i y. Preference-indifference relation i and indifference relation i are defined by x i y if and only if z A(y i z x i z), x i y if and only if x i y and y i x. 3 About omniscience principles we referred to [3], [4], [8] and [9]. 4 About details of the concepts of discrete set and detachable set, see [3].

84 Arrow Impossibility Theorem Then, the following results are derived. (x i x). x i y entails x i y. The relations i, i are transitive, and x i y i z entails x i z. x i y if and only if (y i x). As demonstrated by [2] we can not prove constructively that x i y if and only if (y i x). A combination of individual preferences, which is called a profile, is denoted by p(= ( 1, 2, )), p (= ( 1, 2, )) and so on. We consider a binary social choice rule which determines a social preference corresponding to each profile. Social preferences are defined similarly to individual preferences. We denote x y when the society strictly prefers x to y. The social preference is denoted by at p, by at p and so on, and it satisfies the following conditions. 1. P1: If x y, then (y x). 2. P2: If x y, then for each z A either x z or z y. x y and x y are defined as follows. x y if and only if z A(y z x z), x y if and only if x y and y x. Then, the following results are derived. (x x) x y entails x y. The relations, are transitive, and x y z entails x z. x y if and only if (y x). Social preferences are further required to satisfy Pareto principle and independence of irrelevant alternatives (IIA). The meanings of these conditions are as follows. Pareto principle When all individuals prefer x to y, the society must prefer x to y. Independence of irrelevant alternatives (IIA) The social preference about every pair of two alternatives x and y is determined by only individual preferences about these alternatives. Individual preferences about other alternatives do not affect the social preference about x and y.

Y. Tanaka 85 A binary social choice rule which satisfies transitivity is called a social welfare function. Arrow s impossibility theorem ([1]) shows that, with a finite number of individuals, for any social welfare function satisfying Pareto principle and IIA there exists a dictator. In contrast [5], [6] and [7] show that when the number of individuals in the society is infinite, there exists a social welfare function satisfying Pareto principle and IIA without dictator. A dictator is an individual such that if he strictly prefers an alternative to another alternative, then the society must also strictly prefer the former to the latter. According to definitions in [11] we define the following terms. Almost decisiveness If, when all individuals in a (finite or infinite) group G prefer an alternative x to another alternative y, and other individuals (individuals in N \ G) prefer y to x, the society prefers x to y (x y), then G is almost decisive for x against y. Decisiveness If, when all individuals in a group G prefer x to y, the society prefers x to y regardless of the preferences of other individuals, then G is decisive for x against y. Decisive set If a group of individuals is decisive about every pair of alternatives, it is called a decisive set. A decisive set may consist of one individual. If an individual is decisive about every pair of alternatives for a social welfare function, then he is a dictator of the social welfare function. Of course, there exists at most one dictator. First about decisiveness we show the following lemma. LEMMA 1. If a group of individuals G is almost decisive for an alternative x against another alternative y, then it is decisive about every pair of alternatives, that is, it is a decisive set. PROOF. See Appendix. The implications of this lemma are similar to those of Lemma 3 a in [11] and Dictator Lemma in [12]. Next we show the following lemma. LEMMA 2. If G 1 and G 2 are decisive sets, then G 1 G 2 is also a decisive set. PROOF. Let x, y and z be given three alternatives, and consider the following profile. 1. Individuals in G 1 \ G 2 (denoted by i): z i x i y 2. Individuals in G 2 \ G 1 (denoted by j): y j z j x 3. Individuals in G 1 G 2 (denoted by k): x k y k z 4. Other individuals (denoted by l): z l y l x Since G 1 and G 2 are decisive sets, the social preference is x y and y z. Then, by transitivity the social preference about x and z should be x z. Only individuals

86 Arrow Impossibility Theorem in G 1 G 2 prefer x to z, and all other individuals prefer z to x. Thus, G 1 G 2 is almost decisive for x against z. Then, by Lemma 1 it is a decisive set. Note that G 1 and G 2 can not be disjoint. Assume that G 1 and G 2 are disjoint. If individuals in G 1 prefer x to y, and individuals in G 2 prefer y to x, then neither G 1 nor G 2 can be a decisive set. This lemma implies that the intersection of a finite number of decisive sets is also a decisive set. 3 Existence of social welfare function satisfying Pareto principle and IIA without dictator and LPO Consider profiles such that one individual (denoted by i) prefers x to y to z, and all other individuals prefer z to x to y. Denote such a profile by p i. By Pareto principle the social preference about x and y is x y. By the property of constructively defined social preference (P2) the social preference is x z or z y. If it is x z at p i for some i, then by IIA individual i is almost decisive for x against z, and by Lemma 1 he is a dictator. On the other hand, if the social preference is z y at p i for all i N, then there exists no dictator. In this case by IIA, Lemma 1 and 2 all co-finite sets (sets of individuals whose complements are finite sets) are decisive sets. Thus, we obtain THEOREM 1. For any social welfare function satisfying Pareto principle and IIA there exists a dictator or there exists no dictator, and in the latter case all co-finite sets are decisive sets. But we can show the following theorem. THEOREM 2. Theorem 1 is equivalent to LPO. PROOF. Define a binary sequence (a i ) as follows. a i = 1 for i N if the social preference about x and z at p i is x z a i = 0 for i N if the social preference about y and z at p i is z y The condition of LPO for this binary sequence is as follows. LPO (Limited principle of omniscience) a i = 0 for all i N or a i = 1 for some i N From the arguments before Theorem 1 it is clearly equivalent to Theorem 1. Note x z and z y are not consistent at p i for each i. Assume x z and z y at p i, and consider the following profile. 1. Individual i: y i x i z 2. Other individuals (denoted by j): z j y j x By IIA the social preference is x z and z y. Then, by transitivity the social preference about x and y must be x y. It means (y x). But by Pareto principle the social preference must be y x. Therefore, x z and z y are not consistent at p i.

Y. Tanaka 87 4 Concluding Remarks We have examined the Arrow impossibility theorem of social choice theory in an infinite society, and have shown that the theorem that there exists a dictator or there exists no dictator for any social welfare function satisfying Pareto principle and IIA in an infinite society is equivalent to LPO (Limited principle of omniscience), and so it is non-constructive. The assumption of an infinite society seems to be unrealistic. But [10] presented an interpretation of an infinite society based on a finite number of individuals and a countably infinite number of uncertain states. Acknowledgment This research was partially supported by the Ministry of Education, Science, Sports and Culture, Grant-in-Aid in Japan. Appendix: Proof of Lemma 1 1. Case 1: There are more than three alternatives. Let z and w be alternatives other than x and y, and consider the following profile. (a) Individuals in G (denoted by i): z i x i y i w. (b) Other individuals (denoted by j): y j x, z j x and y j w. Their preferences about z and w are not specified. By Pareto principle the social preference is z x and y w. Since G is almost decisive for x against y, the social preference is x y. Then, by transitivity the social preference should be z w. This means that G is decisive for z against w. From this result we can show that G is decisive for x (or y) against w, for z against x (or y), for y against x, and for x against y. Since z and w are arbitrary, G is decisive about every pair of alternatives, that is, it is a decisive set. 2. Case 2: There are only three alternatives x, y and z. Consider the following profile. (a) Individuals in G (denoted by i): x i y i z. (b) Other individuals (denoted by j): y j z, y j x, and their preferences about x and z are not specified. By Pareto principle the social preference is y z. Since G is almost decisive for x against y, the social preference is x y. Then, by transitivity the social preference should be x z. This means that G is decisive for x against z. Similarly we can show that G is decisive for z against y considering the following profile. (a) Individuals in G (denoted by i): z i x i y. (b) Other individuals (denoted by j): z j x, y j x, and their preferences about y and z are not specified. By similar procedures we can show that G is decisive for y against z, for z against x, for y against x, and for x against y.

88 Arrow Impossibility Theorem References [1] K. J. Arrow, Social Choice and Individual Values, 2 nd ed., Yale University Press, 1963. [2] D. Bridges, Constructive methods in mathematical economics, in Mathematical Utility Theory, 1 21, Springer-Verlag, 1999. [3] D. Bridges and F. Richman, Varieties of Constructive Mathematics (London Mathematical Society Lecture Note Series Vol. 97), Cambridge University Press, 1987. [4] D. Bridges and L. S. Vîţă, Techniques of Constructive Analysis, Springer Verlag, 2006. [5] P. C. Fishburn, Arrow s impossibility theorem: Concise proof and infinite voters, J. Econ. Theory, 2(1970), 103 106. [6] B. Hansson, The existence of group preference functions, Pub. Choice, 28(1976), 89 98. [7] A. P. Kirman and D. Sondermann, Arrow s theorem, many Agents and invisible dictators, J. Econ. Theory, 5(1972), 267 277. [8] M. Mandelkern, Constructive Continuity (Memoirs of American Mathematical Society 277), American Mathematical Society, 1983. [9] M. Mandelkern, Brouwerian counterexamples, Math. Mag., 62(1989), 3 27. [10] R. Mihara, Arrow s theorem and Turing computability, Econ. Theory, 10(1997), 257 276. [11] A. Sen, Collective Choice and Social Welfare, North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1979. [12] K. Suzumura, Welfare economics beyond welfarist-consequentialism, Jap. Econ. Rev., 51(2000), 1 32. [13] Y. Tanaka, The Gibbard-Satterthwaite theorem of social choice theory in an infinite society and LPO(Limited principle of omniscience), Appl. Math. Comp., 193(2007), 475-481. [14] A. Taylor, Social Choice and the Mathematics of Manipulation, Cambridge University Press, 2005.