Fallbacks and push-ons

Similar documents
DDL UNLIMITED: DYNAMIC DOXASTIC LOGIC FOR INTROSPECTIVE AGENTS* Sten Lindström and Wlodek Rabinowicz

From Onions to Broccoli: Generalizing Lewis s counterfactual logic

Belief revision: A vade-mecum

BOUNDED REVISION: TWO-DIMENSIONAL BELIEF CHANGE BETWEEN CONSERVATISM AND MODERATION. Hans Rott

Remarks on Kratzer s Ordering- Premise Semantics of Modalities and Conditionals. Norry Ogata Osaka University. Contents

Doxastic Logic. Michael Caie

Conditional Logic and Belief Revision

A Unifying Semantics for Belief Change

Reasoning with Inconsistent and Uncertain Ontologies

HELP US REMOVE OUTDATED BELIEFS?

Bisimulation for conditional modalities

Ranking Theory. Franz Huber Department of Philosophy University of Toronto, Canada

Comment on Leitgeb s Stability Theory of Belief

Definability of Horn Revision from Horn Contraction

Towards A Multi-Agent Subset Space Logic

Moody conditionals: Hamburgers, switches, and the tragic death of an American president

cis32-ai lecture # 18 mon-3-apr-2006

Belief Revision II: Ranking Theory

On iterated revision in the AGM framework

Principles of Knowledge Representation and Reasoning

Rational Partial Choice Functions and Their Application to Belief Revision

Modal and temporal logic

Iterated Belief Change: A Transition System Approach

Agent Communication and Belief Change

Segerberg on the Paradoxes of Introspective Belief Change

Formal Epistemology: Lecture Notes. Horacio Arló-Costa Carnegie Mellon University

Axiomatic characterization of the AGM theory of belief revision in a temporal logic

Departamento de Computación, Universidad de Buenos Aires, Argentina

CL16, 12th September 2016

. Modal AGM model of preference changes. Zhang Li. Peking University

Non-Analytic Tableaux for Chellas s Conditional Logic CK and Lewis s Logic of Counterfactuals VC

Nested Epistemic Logic Programs

Relations. Carl Pollard. October 11, Department of Linguistics Ohio State University

Partial Meet Revision and Contraction in Logic Programs

Some Non-Classical Approaches to the Brandenburger-Keisler Paradox

An Action Description Language for Iterated Belief Change

On the Relation Between Remainder Sets and Kernels

Approximations of Modal Logic K

Base Revision in Description Logics - Preliminary Results

Proving Completeness for Nested Sequent Calculi 1

Lecture 3: Semantics of Propositional Logic

PLAYING WITH KNOWLEDGE AND BELIEF

Applied Logic. Lecture 1 - Propositional logic. Marcin Szczuka. Institute of Informatics, The University of Warsaw

General Patterns for Nonmonotonic Reasoning: From Basic Entailments to Plausible Relations

Conflict-Based Belief Revision Operators in Possibilistic Logic

Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic

Belief Revision and Progression of KBs in the Epistemic Situation Calculus

First Steps Towards Revising Ontologies

Imperative Logic, Moods and Sentence Radicals

Universal Algebra for Logics

Towards Tractable Inference for Resource-Bounded Agents

Argumentation and rules with exceptions

A Unifying Framework for Probabilistic Belief Revision

What is DEL good for? Alexandru Baltag. Oxford University

Maximal Introspection of Agents

Inverse Resolution as Belief Change

Default Reasoning and Belief Revision: A Syntax-Independent Approach. (Extended Abstract) Department of Computer Science and Engineering

Conceivability and Modal Knowledge

A natural sequent calculus for Lewis logic of counterfactuals

Preference and its Dynamics

Counterfactuals and comparative similarity

127: Lecture notes HT17. Week 8. (1) If Oswald didn t shoot Kennedy, someone else did. (2) If Oswald hadn t shot Kennedy, someone else would have.

A modal perspective on defeasible reasoning

Logics for Belief as Maximally Plausible Possibility

Bounded revision: Two-dimensional belief change between conservative and moderate revision. Hans Rott

02 Propositional Logic

Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic

Logical and Probabilistic Models of Belief Change

A Propositional Typicality Logic for Extending Rational Consequence

Neighborhood Semantics for Modal Logic Lecture 3

Modal Logic. UIT2206: The Importance of Being Formal. Martin Henz. March 19, 2014

Notes on Quantum Logic

Non-Monotonic Formalisms

Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Update As Evidence: Belief Expansion

First-Degree Entailment

Adding Modal Operators to the Action Language A

Logic via Algebra. Sam Chong Tay. A Senior Exercise in Mathematics Kenyon College November 29, 2012

Logic and Artificial Intelligence Lecture 22

Decision procedure for Default Logic

Dialetheic deontic logic and language-created reality

Default Logic Autoepistemic Logic

Introduction to Metalogic

The logic of subset spaces, topologic and the local difference modality K

The modal logic of forcing

ON THE SOLVABILITY OF INDUCTIVE PROBLEMS: A STUDY IN EPISTEMIC TOPOLOGY

A Semantic Approach for Iterated Revision in Possibilistic Logic

Belief Revision in Social Networks

Subgoal Semantics in Agent Programming

Lecture 1: Overview. January 24, 2018

CS 486: Applied Logic Lecture 7, February 11, Compactness. 7.1 Compactness why?

Reducing Belief Simpliciter to Degrees of Belief

arxiv: v1 [cs.lo] 27 Mar 2015

Priorities and Preferences: A Study Based on Contraction

Laboratoire d'informatique Fondamentale de Lille

Model Theory of Modal Logic Lecture 1: A brief introduction to modal logic. Valentin Goranko Technical University of Denmark

Logics above S4 and the Lebesgue measure algebra

Modal logics: an introduction

Revisit summer... go to the Fitzwilliam Museum!

Explanations, Belief Revision and Defeasible Reasoning

Transcription:

Fallbacks and push-ons Krister Segerberg September 22, 2006 1 Background Grove showed in effect that, in the theory of belief change initiated by Alchourrón, Gärdenfors and Makinson, belief states may be represented as sphere systems in the sense of David Lewis ([1], [2], [3]). A sphere system is essentially a linearly ordered family of subsets of a given space. In Lewis s own favourite interpretation of his sphere systems the elements corresponded to degrees of similarity with a given point ( possible world ), an interpretation that is not well suited to the theory of belief change. 1 Lindström and Rabinowicz proposed instead a more congenial interpretation under which the elements of a sphere system represent theories of varying strength: the strongest one is the current belief set of the agent, while the others are weaker theories on which the agent may fall back if he is challenged by new information that is inconsistent with what he currently believes ([4]). Those weaker theories were accordingly called fallbacks. The term fallback is apt. A rational agent not in possession of indubitable knowledge must be prepared to give up some of his beliefs if new information makes his doxastic position untenable. He would then look for the most suitable fallback a default theory, weaker than the theory representing his current beliefs, but as strong as possible under the circumstances. But isn t it also possible, even for a rational agent, to favour certain views (conjectures, hunches ) without believing that they are true? If fallbacks model an agent s disposition to shed old beliefs, couldn t there be a dual concept that models his disposition to subscribe to new beliefs? Probably many students of Grove s modelling have, at some time or other, toyed with the idea of extending 1 Which is not to rule out the use of sphere systems in an analysis of verisimilitude. This paper was written while the author was a fellow-in-residence at N.I.A.S. (Netherlands Institute for Advanced Study) 1 Printed from: Hommage à Wlodek. Philosophical Papers Dedicated to Wlodek Rabinowicz. Ed. T. Rønnow-Rasmussen, B. Petersson, J. Josefsson & D. Egonsson, 2007. www.fil.lu.se/hommageawlodek

the sphere systems by introducing push-ons ( inside the belief set) to correspond to the fallbacks (which are outside the belief set). 2 It is certainly possible to develop an abstract modelling of that kind; here we offer one example. 2 Formalia Let (U, T) be a Stone space (that is, a compact, totally separated topological space). 3 We say that (I, O) is an onion pair if (i) I and O are nonempty families of closed subsets of U, (ii) O is linearly ordered by the subset relation and closed under arbitrary nonempty intersection, (iii) there is a subset B of U such that B I O and B = I = O, (iv) there is a subset K of U such that K O and K = C O. The sets B and K are called the belief set and the commitment set, respectively. The elements of O other than B are called fallbacks and those of I other than B push-ons. If C is a maximal chain of elements of I we call C a possible conjecture. 4 If (I, O) is an onion pair we refer to I as the inner onion and to O as the outer onion. A frame is a structure (U, T, Q, R, E, J) such that (U, T) is a Stone topology, Q is a quantity of onion pairs, while R = {R P : P is a clopen subset of U} and E = {E P : P is a clopen subset of U} and J = {J P : P is a clopen subset of U} are families of binary relations in Q satisfying certain conditions: if ((I, O), (I, O )) R P then either O overlaps with P and O = P Z, where Z is the smallest element in {X O : P X }, or else O does not overlap with P and O = {, K}; 2 Our perspective is semantic, not syntactic! 3 For more in the way of explanation of and motivation for the technical terminology in this paper, see for example [5] or [6]. We use the term onion in place of David Lewis s more dignified but unwieldy sphere system. Our onions differ from his in some respects. 4 Those who are reluctant to use the term conjecture for a theory may wish to refer to C as a conjectured theory. 2

if ((I, O), (I, O )) E P then I = {P X : X I} {C X I(P X)} and O {C X I(P X)} O ; if ((I, O), (I, O )) J P then I = {X I : X B }, where B = C {X I : X P}. The set U is called the universe of the frame. The elements of R are referred to a revision relations, those of E as expansion relations and those of J as jumps (or jumping-to-conclusion relations). We assume a language for classical propositional logic with some additional modal (unary propositional) operators: B, K, C, D (doxastic) and [...], [+...], [...] (dynamic). Two restrictions apply: (i) a doxastic operator operates only on pure Boolean formulæ, and (ii) in a dynamic operator the three dots must be replaced by a pure Boolean formula. (A pure Boolean formula is a formula all of whose operators are truth-functional.) We write b, k, c, d,..., +...,... for the duals of B, K, C, D, [...], [+...], [...]. A valuation (in (U, T)) is a function from the set of propositional letters to the set of clopen subsets of U. Given a frame and a valuation, let us write φ for the truth-set of a pure Boolean formula, that is, the subset of U at which the formula in question is true under the valuation. (We omit details since only classical notions are involved so far.) By a reference point we mean a triple (I, O, u) where (I, O) is an onion pair and u is an element of the universe of the frame. We define the notion of truth of a formula in a frame under a valuation at a reference point as follows (denoted by the symbol ): for any onion pair (I, O), point u in U, pure Boolean formula φ and formula θ, (I, O, u) φ iff u φ, if φ is pure Boolean, [obvious conditions for the truth-functional operators] (I, O, u) Bφ iff O φ, (I, O, u) Kφ iff O φ, (I, O, u) Cφ iff, for all maximal chains C in I, C φ, (I, O, u) Dφ iff, for some maximal chain C in I, C φ, (I, O, u) [+φ]θ iff it is the case that, for all onion pairs (I, O ) such that ((I, O), (I, O )) E φ, (I, O, u) θ, 3

(I, O, u) [ φ]θ iff it is the case that, for all onion pairs (I, O ) such that ((I, O), (I, O )) J φ, (I, O, u) θ, (I, O, u) [ φ]θ iff it is the case that, for all onion pairs (I, O ) such that ((I, O), (I, O )) R φ, (I, O, u) θ. A formula is valid if it is true at all reference points in all frames under all valuations. The set of valid formulæ forms a modal logic in which each modal operator is normal. 3 Interpretation Of our nonclassical operators, four have standard interpretations: for Bφ and Kφ, read, respectively, the agent believes that φ or (equally accurately) it is one of the agent s revisable beliefs that φ, the agent knows that φ or (more accurately) it is one of the agent s nonrevisable beliefs that φ. And for [ φ]θ and [+φ]θ read, respectively, after the agent has revised his beliefs by φ, it is the case that θ, after the agent has expanded his beliefs by φ, it is the case that θ. In the same vein we may suggest, for Cφ and Dφ, respectively, according to the agent s conjectures it is the case that φ, according to one of the agent s conjectures it is the case that φ. Finally, for [ φ]θ read after the agent has jumped to the conclusion that φ, it is the case that θ. 4

4 Comments The presentation of our modelling leaves many questions unanswered, in particular the most important one: where do the inner onions come from? If (I, O) and (I, O ) are related by some jump J P, then our theory has nothing to say about I if P happens to be incompatible with the agent s current beliefs (that is, if P O = ); even if P is compatible, our theory says little. It is small comfort that the original AGM theory suffered from a similar limitation by failing to describe O in the case just envisaged (beyond the general requirement listed above which gives the new belief set but not the complete outer onion In order to account for the inner onions one must widen the perspective and bring in new parameters or concepts. One alternative might be to turn to Reiter s default logic, which endows the agent with a repertoire of defeasible inference rules and which is known to be congenial to DDL ([8], [9]). A more ambitious alternative would be to try to conceive of a mechanism a research programme? a line of investigation? that would generate plausibilities (the inner onions) in some systematic manner. A beginning would be to represent such mechanisms as functions R from closed sets X (possible belief sets) to families of clopen subsets of X (inner onions). The difficulty would the be to find fruitful conditions to characterize R. Perhaps the ideas in [7] might be useful here. 5 References [1] Carlos Alchourrón, Peter Gärdenfors & David Makinson. On the logic of theory change. The journal of symbolic logic, vol. 50 (1985), pp. 510-530. [2] Adam Grove. Two modellings for theory change. Journal of philosophical logic, vol. 17 (1988), pp. 157-170. [3] David Lewis. Counterfactuals. Oxford: Blackwell, 1973. [4] Sten Lindström & Wlodek Rabinowicz. Epistemic entrenchment with incomparabilities and relational belief revision. In The logic of theory change, edited by André Fuhrmann & Michael Morreau, pp. 93-126. Lecture Notes in Artificial Intelligence, no. 465. Berlin: Springer-Verlag, 1990. 5 This note was written while the author was a fellow-in-residence at N.I.A.S. (The Netherlands Institute for Advanced Study). 5

[5] Sten Lindström & Krister Segerberg. Modal logic and philosophy. To appear in Handbook of modal logic. [6] Hannes Leitgeb & Krister Segerberg. Doxastic dynamic logic: why, whether, how. To appear in Knowledge, rationality and action. [7] Erik J. Olsson & David Westlund. On the role of research agenda in epistemic change. In Modality matters, edited by Henrik Lagerlund, Sten Lindström & Rysiek Sliwinski, pp. 323-337. Uppsala philosophical studies, vol. 53 (2006). [8] Ray Reiter. A logic of default reasoning. Artificial intelligence, vol. 13 (1980), pp. 81-132. [9] Krister Segerberg. Delfault logic as dynamic doxastic logic. Erkenntnis, vol. 50 (1999), pp. 333-352. Envoi For a short period in the early 1990s Uppsala was one of the best places in the world for the study of the logic of belief change. When I arrived there in 1991, Wlodek Rabinowicz was the Head of Department (an office that did not visibly burden him), Sten Lindström and Sven Ove Hansson were already there, John Cantwell and Tor Sandqvist were soon to join as graduate students. Wlodek s never ending enthusiasm (along with Sten s never ending objections) created a unique and wonderful environment. The issues dealt with in this paper could very well have been discussed during those exciting years, even though I don t remember that they were. If they had been, this paper would already have been written. 6