On Urquhart s C Logic

Similar documents
Hypersequent Calculi for some Intermediate Logics with Bounded Kripke Models

A Schütte-Tait style cut-elimination proof for first-order Gödel logic

Hypersequent calculi for non classical logics

Labelled Calculi for Łukasiewicz Logics

Non-classical Logics: Theory, Applications and Tools

FROM AXIOMS TO STRUCTURAL RULES, THEN ADD QUANTIFIERS.

Bounded Lukasiewicz Logics

5-valued Non-deterministic Semantics for The Basic Paraconsistent Logic mci

Kamila BENDOVÁ INTERPOLATION AND THREE-VALUED LOGICS

Classical Gentzen-type Methods in Propositional Many-Valued Logics

Display calculi in non-classical logics

TR : Binding Modalities

A CUT-FREE SIMPLE SEQUENT CALCULUS FOR MODAL LOGIC S5

Automated Support for the Investigation of Paraconsistent and Other Logics

CHAPTER 11. Introduction to Intuitionistic Logic

General Patterns for Nonmonotonic Reasoning: From Basic Entailments to Plausible Relations

Proof Theoretical Reasoning Lecture 3 Modal Logic S5 and Hypersequents

Canonical Calculi: Invertibility, Axiom expansion and (Non)-determinism

On interpolation in existence logics

Uniform Rules and Dialogue Games for Fuzzy Logics

cse371/mat371 LOGIC Professor Anita Wasilewska Fall 2018

AN ALTERNATIVE NATURAL DEDUCTION FOR THE INTUITIONISTIC PROPOSITIONAL LOGIC

185.A09 Advanced Mathematical Logic

Uninorm Based Logic As An Extension of Substructural Logics FL e

Gödel Logics a short survey

Equivalents of Mingle and Positive Paradox

Nonclassical logics (Nichtklassische Logiken)

Proof Theoretical Studies on Semilattice Relevant Logics

Rasiowa-Sikorski proof system for the non-fregean sentential logic SCI

Substructural Logics and Residuated Lattices an Introduction

Some consequences of compactness in Lukasiewicz Predicate Logic

Propositional Logic Language

From Frame Properties to Hypersequent Rules in Modal Logics

SOME REMARKS ON MAEHARA S METHOD. Abstract

On Refutation Rules. Tomasz Skura. 1. Introduction. Logica Universalis

A GENTZEN SYSTEM EQUIVALENT TO THE BCK-LOGIC

(Algebraic) Proof Theory for Substructural Logics and Applications

Přednáška 12. Důkazové kalkuly Kalkul Hilbertova typu. 11/29/2006 Hilbertův kalkul 1

Chapter 11: Automated Proof Systems (1)

CHAPTER 10. Gentzen Style Proof Systems for Classical Logic

TRANSLATING A SUPPES-LEMMON STYLE NATURAL DEDUCTION INTO A SEQUENT CALCULUS

First-Order Intuitionistic Logic with Decidable Propositional Atoms

Uniform Schemata for Proof Rules

Fuzzy Logics and Substructural Logics without Exchange

1. Propositional Calculus

Chapter 11: Automated Proof Systems

PROPOSITIONAL MIXED LOGIC: ITS SYNTAX AND SEMANTICS

Fuzzy Logics Interpreted as Logics of Resources

Logics preserving degrees of truth and the hierarchies of abstract algebraic logic

KRIPKE S THEORY OF TRUTH 1. INTRODUCTION

Embedding formalisms: hypersequents and two-level systems of rules

Marie Duží

A Cut-Free Calculus for Second-Order Gödel Logic

RELATIONS BETWEEN PARACONSISTENT LOGIC AND MANY-VALUED LOGIC

Interpolation via translations

On Sequent Calculi for Intuitionistic Propositional Logic

SIMPLE LOGICS FOR BASIC ALGEBRAS

Deep Sequent Systems for Modal Logic

CONTRACTION CONTRACTED

Non-Analytic Tableaux for Chellas s Conditional Logic CK and Lewis s Logic of Counterfactuals VC

Extending the Monoidal T-norm Based Logic with an Independent Involutive Negation

Partially commutative linear logic: sequent calculus and phase semantics

Subminimal Logics and Relativistic Negation

The Blok-Ferreirim theorem for normal GBL-algebras and its application

Paraconsistent Semantics for Pavelka Style Fuzzy Sentential Logic

Resolution for mixed Post logic

Implicational F -Structures and Implicational Relevance. Logics. A. Avron. Sackler Faculty of Exact Sciences. School of Mathematical Sciences

Fuzzy filters and fuzzy prime filters of bounded Rl-monoids and pseudo BL-algebras

Structural extensions of display calculi: a general recipe

Cut-Elimination and Quantification in Canonical Systems

Herbrand s Theorem, Skolemization, and Proof Systems for First-Order Łukasiewicz Logic

Paraconsistent Semantics for Pavelka Style Fuzzy Sentential Logic

Forcing-based cut-elimination for Gentzen-style intuitionistic sequent calculus

MONADIC FRAGMENTS OF INTUITIONISTIC CONTROL LOGIC

An Introduction to Proof Theory

Applied Logics - A Review and Some New Results

What is an Ideal Logic for Reasoning with Inconsistency?

Lecture Notes on Combinatory Modal Logic

ON THE DENSITY OF TRUTH IN GRZEGORCZYK S MODAL LOGIC

U-Sets as a probabilistic set theory

A Fuzzy Formal Logic for Interval-valued Residuated Lattices

A Deep Inference System for the Modal Logic S5

Piotr Kulicki The Use of Axiomatic Rejection

Proof-Theoretic Methods in Nonclassical Logic an Introduction

Natural Deduction for Propositional Logic

SIMPLE DECISION PROCEDURE FOR S5 IN STANDARD CUT-FREE SEQUENT CALCULUS

A note on fuzzy predicate logic. Petr H jek 1. Academy of Sciences of the Czech Republic

On the Complexity of the Reflected Logic of Proofs

The Skolemization of existential quantifiers in intuitionistic logic

Chapter I: Introduction to Mathematical Fuzzy Logic

Fuzzy attribute logic over complete residuated lattices

Expanding the realm of systematic proof theory

Propositional Logics and their Algebraic Equivalents

AN ALGEBRAIC STRUCTURE FOR INTUITIONISTIC FUZZY LOGIC

Embedding logics into product logic. Abstract. We construct a faithful interpretation of Lukasiewicz's logic in the product logic (both

Linear Logic Pages. Yves Lafont (last correction in 2017)

LOGIC OF CLASSICAL REFUTABILITY AND CLASS OF EXTENSIONS OF MINIMAL LOGIC

Structuring Logic with Sequent Calculus

Preuves de logique linéaire sur machine, ENS-Lyon, Dec. 18, 2018

INFERENCE RULES FOR PROBABILITY LOGIC. Marija Boričić

Transcription:

On Urquhart s C Logic Agata Ciabattoni Dipartimento di Informatica Via Comelico, 39 20135 Milano, Italy ciabatto@dsiunimiit Abstract In this paper we investigate the basic many-valued logics introduced by Urquhart in [15] and [16], here referred to as and Ò Û, respectively We define a cut-free hypersequent calculus for Ò Û and show the following results: (1) and Ò Û are distinct versions of Gödel logic without contraction (2) Ò Û is decidable (3) In Ò Û the family of axioms µ µµ µ µ, with ¾, is in fact redundant 1 Introduction The logic was introduced by Urquhart in the chapter devoted to many-valued logic of the Handbook of Philosophical Logic [15] turns out to be a basic many-valued logic being contained in the most important formalizations of fuzzy logic [7], namely infinite-valued Gödel, Łukasiewicz and product logic (see [3]) In [9, 10] was shown to be a particular Gödel logic without contraction A cut-free calculus for was defined in [3] This calculus uses hypersequents that are a natural generalization of Gentzen sequents Due to semantical motivations, in the second edition of his handbook paper [16], Urquhart presented a new version of We shall refer to this logic as Ò Û Semantically, Ò Û is characterized by model structures on ordered abelian monoids and is therefore contained in Łukasiewicz logic which is characterized by ordered Abelian groups [4, 16] In this paper we introduce a cut-free hypersequent calculus for Ò Û As a corollary, we prove that Ò Û is decidable Moreover, for each ¾, we show the redundancy in Ò Û of the axiom µ µµ µ µµ, where stands for µ µµ ßÞ Ð Ø Ñ In order to define a calculus for Ò Û we shall consider three different contraction-free versions of Avron s hypersequent calculus for Gödel logic [1] and we shall relate them with their corresponding logics, here after named and and, already investigated in [3], are respectively Urquhart s logic and its residuated version As we shall show, turns out to coincide with Ò Û 2 Urquhart s logics and Ò Û Urquhart s basic many-valued logic consists of the following axioms (see [15]): Ax1 µ Ax2 µ µ µ Ax3 µ µ Ax4 µ Ax5 µ Ax6 µ Ax7 µ Ax8 µ Ax9 µ µ µ Lin µ µ together with the rule of modus ponens In [16] Urquhart introduced a new version of We shall refer to this logic as Ò Û Semantically, Ò Û is characterized by model structures on ordered commutative monoids More precisely, let ¼µ be a (totally) ordered commutative monoid and a total ordering of satisfying the condition Ü Ý implies Ü Þ Ý Þ for all Ü Ý Þ ¾ Let ¼ be the set Ü ¾ Ü ¼ Definition 21 ([16]) A model structure over consists of a subset È ¼ for each atomic formula È in the language The sets È are required to be increasing (a subset is increasing if Ü ¾ and Ü Ý imply that Ý ¾ ) Given a model structure over, we define truth at a point Ü in ¼ by the following inductive stipulation:

1 Ü È iff Ü ¾ È ; Product logic Lukasiewicz logic Goedel Logic 2 Ü µ iff Ü and Ü ; 3 Ü µ iff either Ü or Ü ; BL 4 Ü µ iff, for all Ý ¾ ¼, Ý implies Ü Ý A formula is valid iff ¼ in every model structure over an ordered commutative monoid In [16] a Hilbert-style axiomatization of Ò Û is defined by adding to the above axioms ܾ Ü Ü Lin both: U1 µ µµ µµ U2 µ µµ µ µ for every ¾, where stands for µ µµ ßÞ Ð Ø Ñ Urquhart proved that a formula is valid in the model theory of Definition 21 if and only if Ò Û Remark 22 If in Definition 21 one makes the assumption that the underlying algebra is an ordered abelian group, one obtains model structures characterizing infinite-valued Łukasiewicz logic [4, 16] To put the logics and Ò Û into a broader context, let us introduce the following axioms: Res1 µ µ Res2 µ µ Abs Taking Modus Ponens as the only rule of derivation, we consider the logics: Á ܽ Ü Abs Á Lin Á Á Í ½ Á Lin Á Á Res1 Res2 Á Lin Á Á and have been investigated in [3, 5] Á, Á and Á, are different versions of intuitionistic logic ÁÄ without contraction Notice that Res1 is already derivable in Á In fact, this axiom turns out to be redundant in the presence of ܽ ܾ and Ü Á and Á are incomparable and they strictly extend Á (Corollary 313) Á leads to ÁÄ by adding axiom Res2 to the former coincides with and are incomparable versions of Gödel logic without contraction (Corollary 317) and they strictly extend In Section 4 we show that Ò Û Figure 1 shows proper inclusions among all the previously mentioned logics as well as of other well known logics (Corollary 46) C* a-mll IL C # C + I -* I-# I - Figure 1 Inclusions among various logics Indeed, by extending Á with axiom Ò (involutivity of negation), ie, µ µ one gets the affine multiplicative fragment of linear logic a-mll 1 [6] As shown in [13], Łukasiewicz logic [8] is obtainable by adding to a-mll the axiom µ µ µ µ Hájek s Basic Logic Ä was introduced in [7] as the logical counterpart of continuous Ø-norms As proved in [3], by adding to the axiom µ µ one gets Ä If we add to Ä axiom Ò we get Łukasiewicz logic, while by extending Ä with both axioms µ µµ and µµ we obtain product logic (see [7]) Each of, and Ä yields Gödel logic by adding the axiom µ µ (contraction) Remark 23 Henceforth we shall abuse the names Ò Û and to refer to their proper extensions Ò Û and (ie, µ, respectively 3 Sequent and Hypersequent Calculi In this section we define sequent (and hypersequent) calculi for Á and Hypersequent calculi are a simple and natural generalization of Gentzen sequent calculi See [2] for an overview Definition 31 A hypersequent is an expression of the form ½ ½ Ò Ò, where for all ½ Ò, is an ordinary sequent The intended meaning of the symbol is disjunctive Hypersequent calculi are particularly useful to formalize logics containing axiom Ä Ò (see [3, 5]) 1 In fact, we get a-mll extended with the additive disjunction

In [3] cut-free calculi for the logics Á Á and have been introduced They are called Ä Ä À and À, respectively Ä and Ä turn out to be different contraction-free fragments of the Ä sequent calculus for intuitionistic logic, while À and À are their hypersequent versions with Avron s communication rule [1] More precisely, let us consider the Ä sequent calculus for intuitionistic logic, ie, Ü ÓÑ Ùص ËØÖÙØÙÖ Ð ÊÙÐ Ûµ µ ÄÓ Ð ÊÙÐ Öµ Öµ µ ½ µ ¾ µ ½ ¾ µ µ Öµ µ µ ½ ¾ ½ µ ¾ µ ½ ¾ µ ½ µ ¾ µ ½ ¾ When investigating contraction-free fragments of ÄÂ, we can consider the following alternative formulations for the Öµ and rules: ¼ Öµ µ µ ¼ е ½ ¾ µ ÓÖ ½ ¾ The above rules are called additive, while the corresponding ones in Ä are called multiplicative (see [14]) As is well known, using µ and Ûµ, the additive rules are interderivable with the multiplicative ones, while in absence of µ, they are distinct Remark 32 See [12] for a general investigation on intuitionistic logic without contraction Let us consider the calculi obtained substituting the rules for conjunction in the contraction-free Ä calculus by one of the four possible combinations of the above additive and multiplicative rules The calculus defined by choosing and ¼ Öµ as rules for conjunction shows undesirable properties: it allows to derive contraction, and cuts are not eliminable (see [14]) The calculi obtained using the pairs of rules ¼ е Öµ and Öµ are respectively Ä and Ä of [3] Henceforth we shall investigate the fourth possible system, which we shall call Ä In Ä the rules for conjunction are ¼ е and ¼ Öµ and the remaining ones are those of LJ except contraction µ Let us introduce the hypersequent versions of the above calculi In À and À axioms, internal structural rules and logical rules are directly obtained from those of Ä and ÄÂ, respectively: the only difference is the presence of dummy contexts and ¼ representing (possibly empty) hypersequents For instance, the rules for implication are Öµ ½ µ ¼ ¾ µ ¼ ½ ¾ Additional structural rules are external weakening (EW) and contraction (EC) Ï µ µ µ ¼ µ ¼ together with Avron s communication rule [1] ½ ½ µ µ µ ¼ ¾ ¾ µ ¼ ½ ¾ µ ½ ¾ µ µ See [3] for a detailed description on these calculi The hypersequent version of Ä shall be called À In À axioms, internal structural rules and logical rules are obtained from those of ÄÂ, as seen for À and À Additional structural rules are (EW), (EC) and (com) Remark 33 By adding the µ rule to À À or À one gets Avron s Ä calculus [1] for Gödel logic 31 Cut-elimination In [3] it was proved that the cut-elimination theorem holds for Ä Ä À and À This is true also for À Indeed Theorem 34 Ä admits cut-elimination Proof: See, eg, [12] Definition 35 A sequent calculus is single-conclusion iff in all the involved sequents µ, the succedent contains at most one formula Theorem 36 If a single-conclusion sequent calculus admits cut-elimination then its hypersequent version with as additional rule admits cut-elimination Proof: See [3, 5]

Corollary 37 À admits cut-elimination Definition 38 Let ½ Ò µ be a sequent Then the generic interpretation Á of ½ Ò µ is defined as follows: Á µ µ Á ½ Ò µ µ ½ Ò µ µ Á ½ Ò µµ ½ Ò µ µ Let Ë ½ Ë Ò be a hypersequent Its generic interpretation is defined by Á Ë ½ Ë Ò µ Á Ë ½ µ Á Ë Ò µ Definition 39 Sequent (or hypersequent) rules Ë Ë and are called sound for a (Hilbert-style) calculus À iff À Á ˵ Á Ë µ and À Á Ì µ Á Ì ¼ µ Á Ì µµ, respectively If all the rules of a sequent (or hypersequent) calculus Ä Ä are sound for À and À Á ˵ for all the axioms Ë of Ä Ä, then Ä Ä is said to be sound for À A sequent (or hypersequent) calculus Ä Ä is complete for À iff Ä Ä µ µ whenever À Corollary 310 Ì Ì 1 Ä and Ä are proper extensions of ÄÂ Ì ¼ 2 Ä and Ä are incomparable 3 À is a proper extension of À 4 À is a proper extension of À 5 À and À are incomparable which evaluates to Ú È µ ½, for instance, in Gödel logic if Ú µ ¼ Since for each hypersequent Ë which is derivable in À, Á ˵ must be valid in Gödel logic, this concludes the proof 4 Follows by the fact that axiom Res2 is not derivable in À (see [3]) 5 It is immediate to see that À µ Ò À µ Res2 However, neither À derives, nor À derives Res2 The proofs proceed as in cases 3 and 4 above, respectively Corollary 311 Derivability in Ä and À is decidable Proof: (Sketch) Proof search based decision algorithms for sequent calculi without contraction are well known (see, eg, [11]) In the case of hypersequents first note that by the occurrence of the external structural rules, any cut-free proof can be transformed in an equivalent one in which every hypersequent has at most two equal components Thus a bound for the number of hypersequents occurring in the cut-free proofs, as well as for the number of the components in the involved hypersequents, can be obtained in terms of the size of the end hypersequent 32 Correspondences In [3] it was proved that the calculi Ä Ä À À are sound and complete for Á Á and, respectively In this section we relate the logics Á and, as given by their Hilbert-style axiomatizations, to the calculi Ä and À Proof: 1 It is easy to see that Theorem 312 Ä is sound and complete for Á Ä µ Ò Ä µ Res2 By the cut-free completeness of Ä it follows immediately that the above two axioms are not derivable in Ä 2 This trivially follows from the non-derivability of Res2 in Ä and of in Ä 3 It suffices to prove that the formula cannot be derived in À Indeed, À µ if and only if the hypersequent µ µ is derivable in À By Definition 39, this hypersequent translates to the formula È given by µ µ Proof: (Soundness) The axioms of Ä translate into and, respectively The corresponding derivation in Á is straightforward In order to show the soundness of the rules of Ä it suffices to prove that their generic interpretations are derivable in Á As an example we consider the ¼ Öµ rule Its generic interpretation µ is: ½ Ò µ µµ ½ Ò µ µµ ½ Ò µ µµµ For Ò ½ this formula coincides with axiom Ü Thus let Ò ¾ In axiom Í ½ let us replace with ½, with ¾ Ò µ µµ and with ¾ Ò µ µµ Let us denote with Í ½ the resulting formula By induction on Ò one can derive the formula µ Í ½ ½ ¾ Ò

µ µ ½ ¾ Ò µ µ ½ Ò µ µµ For the basic step Ò ½, the derivation is trivial For the inductive step, assuming the claim is true for Ò, applying axioms ܽ ܾ Ü together with modus ponens we can derive µ for Ò ½ Then µ follows by applying to µ both axioms Í ½ and Ê ½ together with modus ponens For the remaining rules see either [3] or Corollary 281 in [12] (Completeness) Observe that Modus Ponens the only rule of Á corresponds to the derivability of and of the cut rule It thus suffices to show that all the axioms of Á are derivable in Ä This is straightforward Corollary 313 The logics Á and Á are incomparable extensions of Á Proof: Immediate from soundness and completeness of the Ä calculus with respect to Á (see [3]), together with Corollary 310 and Theorem 312 Lemma 314 À µ Ä Ò Proof: The derivation proceeds as follows (see [1, 3, 5]): µ µ µ µ µ µ µ µ µ µ µ µ µ µ Theorem 315 À is sound and complete for Proof: (Soundness) In the light of Theorem 312 we must only take care of the external structural rules and of the rule µ corresponds to (EC) µ corresponds to (EW) These formulas are already derivable in Á, and hence also in For the rule, see [3] (Completeness) From Theorem 312 and Lemma 314 Corollary 316 is decidable Corollary 317 The logics and are incomparable versions of Gödel logic without contraction Proof: The proof follows by soundness and completeness of the À calculus with respect to (see [3]), together with Theorem 315 and Corollary 310 4 Ò Û coincides with In this section we prove that Urquhart s Ò Û logic coincides with the contraction-free fragment of Gödel logic Proposition 41 Ò Û Í ¾ Proof: It is immediate to see that Ò Û Í ¾ The converse directly follows from the derivability of axioms ܽ in Ò Û Hence, Ò Û Í ¾ Proposition 42 For ¾, the family of axioms Í ¾ can be derived in À Proof: For all Ò ¼, let us denote with ÒÈ the (possibly empty) set of formulas È È (Ò times) Then, for each ¾, we have the following derivation of axiom Í ¾ in À : µ µ µ µ µ µ µ µ µµ µ µ where, all the (¾ ) upper sequents in µ obtained applying the rule as many times as possible, have the form µ µ Ò Ñ Û Ø Ò Ñ All these sequents are provable in À To see this we shall argue by cases as follows: If Ò we proceed as follows: ½ ½µ µ µ The case Ñ is similar ¼ е If ¼ Ñ Ò, let us denote with È Ò Ñ the sequent È Ò Ñ We can write

µ Ñ ¼ Ñ Ò Ò ¼ Ò Ò ¼ Ñ ¼ Ñ Ò Ò ¼ ½ Ò ½ Ñ ½ Ò Ñ ½ Ò Ñ Ò Ñ µ µ Ò Ñ where µ and are respectively given by: and µ ¼ е Ò ½ Ò ½ ¼ Ò Ò ¼ Ò Ò ¼ Ò Ò ¼ Ñ ¾ ¼ Ñ ¾ Ò Ò ¼ Ñ ½ ¼ Ñ ½ Ò Ò ¼ Ò Ò ¼ Ñ ½ ¼ Ñ ½ Ò Ò ¼ The case ¼ Ò Ñ is similar This concludes the proof Theorem 43 Ò Û coincides with Proof: By the previous propositions Corollary 44 Ò Û and are distinct versions of Gödel logic without contraction Proof: By the previous theorem and Corollary 317 [2] A Avron The method of hypersequents in the proof theory of propositional nonclassical logics In Logic: from Foundations to Applications, European Logic Colloquium, pages 1 32 Oxford Science Publications Clarendon Press Oxford, 1996 [3] M Baaz, A Ciabattoni, C Fermüller, and H Veith Proof theory of fuzzy logics: Urquart s C and related logics In Mathematical Foundations of Computer Science (MFCS98), Lectures Notes in Computer Science, vol 1450, pages 203 212, 1998 [4] C C Chang Algebraic analysis of many-valued logics Trans of the Amer Math Soc, 88:467 490, 1958 [5] A Ciabattoni Proof-theoretic techniques in many-valued logics PhD thesis, 1999 University of Milan, Italy [6] J Y Girard Linear logic Theoretical Computer Science, 50:1 101, 1987 [7] P Hájek Metamathematics of Fuzzy Logic Kluwer, 1998 [8] J Lukasiewicz Philosophische bemerkungen zu mehrwertigen systemen der aussagenlogik Comptes Rendus de la Societé des Science et de Lettres de Varsovie, pages 51 77, 1930 [9] J Mendéz and F Salto Urquhart s C with intuitionistic negation: Dummett s LC without the contraction axiom Notre Dame J of Formal Logic, 36(3):407 413, 1995 [10] J Mendéz and F Salto A natural negation complementation of urquhart s many-valued logic C J of Philosophical Logic, 27:75 84, 1998 [11] H Ono Proof-theoretic methods in nonclassical logic an introduction In M Takahashi, M Okada, and M Dezani- Ciancaglini, editors, Theories of Types and Proofs, pages 207 254 Mathematical Society of Japan, 1998 [12] H Ono and Y Komori Logics without the contraction rule J of Symbolic Logic, 50:169 201, 1985 [13] A Prijatelj Bounded contraction and gentzen style formulation of Lukasiewicz logics Studia Logica, 57:437 456, 1996 [14] A Troelstra and H Schwichtenberg Basic Proof Theory Cambridge University Press, 1996 [15] A Urquhart Many-valued logic In D Gabbay and F Guenthner, editors, Handbook of Philosophical Logic, Vol III: Alternatives in Classical Logic, pages 71 116 Reidel, Dordrecht, 1986 [16] A Urquhart Basic many-valued logic In D Gabbay and F Guenthner, editors, Handbook of Philosophical Logic: Alternatives in Classical Logic Reidel, Dordrecht, To appear Corollary 45 Ò Û is decidable Proof: Follows by Corollary 316 and Theorem 43 Corollary 46 All inclusions of logics in Figure 1 are proper References [1] A Avron Hypersequents, logical consequence and intermediate logics for concurrency Annals of Mathematics and Artificial Intelligence, 4:225 248, 1991