Philosophy of Science Association

Similar documents
Philosophy of Science, Vol. 43, No. 4. (Dec., 1976), pp

Mind Association. Oxford University Press and Mind Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Mind.

What is it like to be a quantum observer? And what does it imply about the nature of consciousness?

Master Projects (EPFL) Philosophical perspectives on the exact sciences and their history

Quantum Mechanics: Interpretation and Philosophy

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

The American Mathematical Monthly, Vol. 100, No. 8. (Oct., 1993), pp

The College Mathematics Journal, Vol. 24, No. 4. (Sep., 1993), pp

HSSP Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics 08/07/11 Lecture Notes

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

On the role of Decoherence in Bohmian Mechanics

Hardy s Paradox. Chapter Introduction

Bohmian Quantum Mechanics and the Finite Square Potential Barrier

Singlet State Correlations

The College Mathematics Journal, Vol. 21, No. 4. (Sep., 1990), pp

Measurement: still a problem in standard quantum theory

What does it feel like to be in a quantum superposition?

Quantum Measurements: some technical background

Delayed Choice Paradox

A Rejoinder to Mackintosh and some Remarks on the. Concept of General Intelligence

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Biometrika Trust. Biometrika Trust is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Biometrika.

Decoherence and The Collapse of Quantum Mechanics. A Modern View

The Measurement Problem of Quantum Mechanics Click to edit Master title style. Wells Wulsin SASS 24 September 2008

09a. Collapse. Recall: There are two ways a quantum state can change: 1. In absence of measurement, states change via Schrödinger dynamics:

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Instant Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics

ON THE FAITHFUL INTERPRETATION OF PURE WAVE MECHANICS

PHILOSOPHY OF PHYSICS THE METAPHYSICS OF QUANTUM THEORY

Evidence and Theory in Physics. Tim Maudlin, NYU Evidence in the Natural Sciences, May 30, 2014

Phil Notes #7: Time Travel

Deep Metaphysical Indeterminacy

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

The Born Rule. Chapter Classical Random Walk

The hybrid-epistemic model of quantum mechanics and the solution to the measurement problem

226 My God, He Plays Dice! Entanglement. Chapter This chapter on the web informationphilosopher.com/problems/entanglement

On the possibility of nonlinear quantum evolution and superluminal communication

146 Philosophy of Physics: Quantum Mechanics

Journal of the American Mathematical Society, Vol. 2, No. 2. (Apr., 1989), pp

Response to Wiseman, Rieffel, and Cavalcanti on Bell s 1964 Paper

The nature of Reality: Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen Argument in QM

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

COPENHAGEN INTERPRETATION:

The Foundations of Quantum Mechanics and The Limitations of Human Being

Lecture 4. QUANTUM MECHANICS FOR MULTIPLE QUBIT SYSTEMS

ON THE NOTION OF PRIMITIVE ONTOLOGY. Andrea Oldofredi Université de Lausanne MCMP (LMU) 29 Oct. 2014

Introduction to Bell s theorem: the theory that solidified quantum mechanics

Quantum decoherence. Éric Oliver Paquette (U. Montréal) -Traces Worshop [Ottawa]- April 29 th, Quantum decoherence p. 1/2

How Quantum Mechanics can consistently describe the use of itself

A proof of Bell s inequality in quantum mechanics using causal interactions

How big is the Milky Way? Introduction. by Toby O'Neil. How big is the Milky Way? about Plus support Plus subscribe to Plus terms of use

Proceedings of the American Mathematical Society, Vol. 17, No. 5. (Oct., 1966), pp

An Improved Approximate Formula for Calculating Sample Sizes for Comparing Two Binomial Distributions

On the origin of probability in quantum mechanics

10. Physics from Quantum Information. I. The Clifton-Bub-Halvorson (CBH) Theorem.

CLASSICAL AND NON-RELATIVISTIC LIMITS OF A LORENTZ-INVARIANT BOHMIAN MODEL FOR A SYSTEM OF SPINLESS PARTICLES.

Violation of the Born Rule: Implications for the Classical Electromagnetic Field. R. E. Kastner 1 16 Aprll 2016

Critical Notice: Bas van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective Oxford University Press, 2008, xiv pages

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Quotations from other works that I have written

MAKING BOHMIAN MECHANICS COMPATIBLE WITH RELATIVITY AND QUANTUM FIELD THEORY. Hrvoje Nikolić Rudjer Bošković Institute, Zagreb, Croatia

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

15 Skepticism of quantum computing

ON THE POSSIBILITY OF NONLINEAR QUANTUM EVOLUTION AND SUPERLUMINAL COMMUNICATION

The College Mathematics Journal, Vol. 16, No. 2. (Mar., 1985), pp

Popper School Methodological Disproof of Quantum Logic

Sklar s Maneuver. Bradford Skow ABSTRACT

Journal of Applied Probability, Vol. 13, No. 3. (Sep., 1976), pp

arxiv:gr-qc/ v1 15 Apr 1997

about Quantum Physics Bill Poirier MVJS Mini-Conference Lawrence Hall of Science July 9, 2015

Introducing Proof 1. hsn.uk.net. Contents

Stochastic Histories. Chapter Introduction

Detection of Influential Observation in Linear Regression. R. Dennis Cook. Technometrics, Vol. 19, No. 1. (Feb., 1977), pp

arxiv: v1 [physics.hist-ph] 10 Mar 2009

The Role of the Wave Function in the GRW Matter Density Theory

QUASI-CLASSICAL MODEL FOR ONE-DIMENSIONAL POTENTIAL WELL

TYPICALITY IN PURE WAVE MECHANICS. 1. introduction

Biometrika Trust. Biometrika Trust is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Biometrika.

PHYS 121: Work, Energy, Momentum, and Conservation Laws, Systems, and Center of Mass Review Sheet

Time in Bohmian Mechanics

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

The American Mathematical Monthly, Vol. 104, No. 8. (Oct., 1997), pp

Against the field ontology of quantum mechanics

Euclidean Geometry. The Elements of Mathematics

0. Introduction 1 0. INTRODUCTION

A Note on a Method for the Analysis of Significances en masse. Paul Seeger. Technometrics, Vol. 10, No. 3. (Aug., 1968), pp

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Topic 10: Bohm s Theory

arxiv:quant-ph/ v2 6 Sep 1995

Finding the Nucleoli of Large Cooperative Games: A Disproof with Counter-Example

An interpretation of the squared amplitude of a solution of the Schrodinger wave equation. Tim C Jenkins.

Proceedings of the American Mathematical Society, Vol. 88, No. 1. (May, 1983), pp

Mathematics of Operations Research, Vol. 2, No. 2. (May, 1977), pp

Hugh Everett III s Many Worlds

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Quantum Information & Quantum Computation

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

The Econometric Society is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Econometrica.

Transcription:

Philosophy of Science Association Why Bohm's Theory Solves the Measurement Problem Author(s): Tim Maudlin Source: Philosophy of Science, Vol. 62, No. 3 (Sep., 1995), pp. 479-483 Published by: The University of Chicago Press on behalf of the Philosophy of Science Association Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/188499 Accessed: 01/03/2009 00:24 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showpublisher?publishercode=ucpress. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit organization founded in 1995 to build trusted digital archives for scholarship. We work with the scholarly community to preserve their work and the materials they rely upon, and to build a common research platform that promotes the discovery and use of these resources. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. The University of Chicago Press and Philosophy of Science Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Philosophy of Science. http://www.jstor.org

DISCUSSION: WHY BOHM'S THEORY SOLVES THE MEASUREMENT PROBLEM* TIM MAUDLINt Department of Philosophy Rutgers University Abraham Stone recently has published an argument purporting to show that David Bohm's interpretation of quantum mechanics fails to solve the measurement problem. Stone's analysis is not correct, as he has failed to take account of the conditions under which the theorems he cites are proven. An explicit presentation of a Bohmian measurement illustrates the flaw in his reasoning. Given that David Bohm's interpretation of quantum mechanics was rather roundly ignored by the philosophical community for some time, it is gratifying to find a discussion of it recently in the pages of this journal. Unfortunately, Abraham Stone's "Does the Bohm Theory Solve the Measurement Problem?" (1994) contains some severe misunderstandings and misstatements regarding the theory. This note is intended to set the record straight. Stone makes two sorts of observations about Bohm's theory. One is that the particle trajectories postulated by the theory may not be unique (i.e., other trajectories, given by a different dynamics, could give the same empirical predictions). That claim will not be considered in this note. It is irrelevant to the stated subject of the paper, since the fact that other theories might solve the measurement problem in no way impeaches the capacity of Bohmian mechanics to do so. The more radical claim contained in Stone's paper is that Bohm fails to solve the problem at all. That assertion rests on a manifold of confusions. Let me briefly review the relevant background. Since Bohm's theory posits no real collapse of the universal wave function, and since the uncollapsed universal wave function is never actually employed in making any experimental predictions, the theory faces the task of showing when, why, and how it is legitimate to ascribe wave functions to subsystems of the universe and to use those wave functions to make statistical predictions (via Born's rule). This problem is solved by the notion of the effective wave function of a subsystem. Stone follows Diirr, Goldstein and Zanghi (1992) in his discussion, and we can do no *Received September 1994. tsend reprint requests to the author, Department of Philosophy, P.O. Box 270, Rutgers University, New Brunswick, NJ 08903-0270 Philosophy of Science, 62 (1995) pp. 470-000 Copyright? 1995 by the Philosophy of Science Association. 479

480 TIM MAUDLIN better than to directly quote their paper. Suppose we isolate some set of particles in the universe as the x-system, and regard the remainder of the universe (the "environment") as the y-system. Then the universal wavefunction, which is defined over the configuration space of all the particles, can be written T(x,y) and the actual configuration of the particles as (X, Y). [W] e say that a subsystem... has effective wave function x (at a given time) if the universal wave function TP = T(x,y) and the actual coordinates Q = (X, Y) (at that time) satisfy T(x,y) = W(x)O(y) + '-(x,y) with D and T- having macroscopically disjoint y-supports, and Y E supp ). Here, by the macroscopic disjointness of the y-supports of () and T- we mean not only that their supports are disjoint, but that there is a macroscopic function of y whose values for y in the support of ( differ by a macroscopic amount from its values for y in the support of T. (ibid., 864) Since Bohm's equation for the trajectories of particles is local in configuration space, when the two conditions listed above obtain, the value of T-(x,y) plays no role in determining the contemporaneous change in particle positions (since Y is not in its support). The trajectories of particles at that time are determined entirely by the part V(x)D(y), which (by assumption) factorizes into a function of x and a function of y. Dtirr, Goldstein and Zanghi then show, in some detail, why Bohm's theory makes the same predictions for the x-system as one would get using the usual quantum mechanical formalism on xv(x). They further show that it is impossible to improve on those predictions for the following reason. In order to improve on the prediction, one would have to know more about the actual positions X of the x-system particles than can be inferred from the effective wave-function W(x). But no amount of investigation of the environment (the y-system) at that time can provide more information about the positions of the x-particles. That is, when the two conditions stated above hold, conditionalizing on the effective wave function \(x) screens off the positions of the x- particles from all further information about D(y) or about Y. Stone correctly reports this result: If, as we are assuming, all "information" in the environment is encoded in the positions of its particles, then the most the environment can ever "know" about a system, prior to measuring it, is the probability that the measurement in question will come out a certain waythe probability given by Born's rule. (op. cit., 263, boldface emphasis added)

WHY BOHM'S THEORY SOLVES THE MEASUREMENT PROBLEM 481 After repeating this result again several times, Stone continues: By now we know clearly that something is wrong. Besides the obvious questions about the physical nature of particles whose positions carry no information[!], the whole course of our argument seems to contain a basic flaw. We assumed that anything worth calling "information"-in particular, any recording of the outcome of the measurement-was stored in the configurations of the Bohm particles. But we have just proven that these configurations cannot store any information at all. (ibid., 264) This passage contains Stone's argument that Bohm's theory does not solve the measurement problem. The obvious answer to his complaint is that no one ever showed that in Bohm's theory particle positions cannot store information about other particle positions, only that at the beginning of a measurement the positions of particles in the environment store no more information about the particles in the measured system than is reflected in the effective wave function. At the beginning of a z-spin measurement on an x-spin up electron, nothing in the environment can determine whether the incoming electron's position is such as to yield an up or down result. We get that information exactly by coupling the position of the incoming particle to the position of (say) a macroscopic pointer. The Bohmian account of such a coupling is perfectly straightforward: the dynamics, when applied to the measurement situation, implies that for certain initial electron positions the pointer will go one way, for others, another (see Albert 1992, chapter 7 for a clear analysis). At the end of the measurement, the positions of particles in the pointer contain information (in the usual sense of information) about the initial position of the electron. A measurement device exactly creates correlations between positions of particles, such that one can infer from the final state of the positions of particles in the measuring device what the initial state of the measured system was. Bohmian particle positions (in a measurement situation) carry exactly the information that we want them to. Let us go through a measurement in detail. Suppose the environment can itself be divided into a measuring device and the rest of the universe such that d(y) = Xready(u),(v), where Xready(u) is the wave function of a measuring device in its ready state and 0(v) is the wave function of the rest of the universe. The actual coordinates Y similarly split into the positions U of the particles in the measuring device and the positions V of the rest of the universe. Of course, U is in the support of Xready(u) and V is in the support of,(v) since Y is in the support of 0(y). So the initial wave function of the universe is w(x)xready(u)(v) + l-(x,u,v), with U and

482 TIM MAUDLIN V in the supports of Zready(u) and 4(v). The effective wave function of the x-system is V/(x). Now suppose (for simplicity) that xy(x) is non-zero in two separated regions (with equal amplitude), and the measuring device is constructed to determine which region the particle is in. It might contain two detectors and a pointer, hooked up such that if one detector is triggered the pointer swings to the right, and if the other is triggered the pointer swings to the left. So I(x) = 1/V\/2tlright(X) + l/v\/2ileft(x), where a particle in the support of right(x) will cause the pointer to swing to the right and one in the support of Xleft(x) will cause it to swing to the left. In terms of wave functions, this means that vright(x)xready(u) will evolve (via Schr6dinger's equation) to Vright(X)Xright(u) and 1left(X)Xready(u) will evolve to eft(x)xleft(u), where Xright(u) and Xleft(u) are the wave functions of a pointer pointing to the right and left respectively. So the initial wave function { l/\/2jright(x) + 1/\/2Xleft(X) } Xready(U)(V) + I(X,U, v) will evolve into { l/\/2vright(x)xright(u) + 1//2/left(X)(left(u) J } (V) + ' -(X,, V). Typically, T'-(x,u, v), (the evolution of WT(x,u, v)), will still have a support disjoint from { 1l//21Vright(x)Xright(u) + 1/\/2\left(X)Xleft(U)} i (v), and the actual positions U and Vwill be in the support of { l//2xvright(x)xright(u) + 1/\/2Wleft(x)Xleft(u)} I'(v). So what is the effective wave function of the x- system at the end of the measurement? Given only the information above, we cannot say. { l/v/2xright(x)xright(u) + 1/V2Wleft(x)Xleft(U )} 4'(v) does not itself factorize in the right way to define any effective wave function for the x-system. But (as can be easily checked) if U is in the support of Xright(u), then the new effective wave function is vright(x), and if U is in the support of Xleft(u) the new effective wave function is vleft(x). Further, given the dynamics, if U is in the support of Xright(u), then X is in the support of vright(x), and if U is in the support of Xleft(U) then Xis in the support of Veft(X). In plain English, if the pointer points to the left then the particle is to the left and the new effective wave function of the particle has its support to the left, and similarly if the pointer points to the right. The position of the pointer carries information about the position of the particle, and it is only because the pointer points where it does that a new effective wave function exists. Where did Stone go wrong? First, he simply dropped without comment the essential qualification, "prior to measuring it," from his initial formulation. Second, he forgot that the analysis he cites only holds when the conditions for the existence of an effective wave function are met. After

WHY BOHM'S THEORY SOLVES THE MEASUREMENT PROBLEM 483 the measurement, the effective wave function of the measured object is not the (Schrodinger) time development of its initial wave function. Indeed, the point of a measurement is to take a situation where the wave functions of the system and environment factorize (v(x)(d(y)) to one where they are entangled. So one cannot repeat the arguments that work for the initial effective wave function to argue that after the measurement there is no information about the position of the x-system's particles contained in the y-system's positions (after one conditionalizes on the Schrodinger time development of the initial effective wave function). If one could so argue, then Stone would be right, and Bohm's theory would solve nothing. But Stone nowhere states, nor takes account of, the conditions under which Dilrr et al. prove their theorems, making no mention of the effective wave function at all. Stone seems to think that particle positions in Bohm's theory are physically meaningless. He compares them to "imaginary points" (ibid., 265), saying that it does not much matter whether they move faster than light. But far from being imaginary, the particle positions are the heart of the theory, they specify the world as we know it. Further, without them the effective wave function cannot be defined (note the function of Y in the definition). If the conditions for a system having an effective wave function are satisfied at some time, we in the environment cannot, at that time, know more about the positions of particles in that system than is given by its effective wave function. If we want to know more, we couple the system to a measuring device which correlates the positions of particles in the measured system to those in the measuring system. Bohm's dynamics shows how this is done, and that the measuring device will indicate different outcomes with the right (Born) probabilities (calculated from the initial effective wave function). If we want to know what happened to the measuring device (e.g., which way the pointer went), we look at it, thereby correlating positions of particles in our brains with the pointer position. If getting the state of our brain correlated with previously unknown external conditions is not getting information about the world, then nothing is. Bohm's theory solves the measurement problem completely and without remainder. REFERENCES Albert, D. (1992), Quantum Mechanics and Experience. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Diirr, D.; Goldstein, S.; and Zanghi, N. (1992), "Quantum Equilibrium and the Origin of Absolute Uncertainty", Journal of Statistical Physics 67: 843-907. Stone, A. (1994), "Does the Bohm Theory Solve the Measurement Problem?", Philosophy of Science 61: 250-266.