Deontic Logic and Meta-Ethics

Similar documents
First-Degree Entailment

Propositional logic (revision) & semantic entailment. p. 1/34

LP and Relatives. p p

CHAPTER 11. Introduction to Intuitionistic Logic

COMP219: Artificial Intelligence. Lecture 19: Logic for KR

Deductive Systems. Lecture - 3

Systems of modal logic

Logic and Proofs 1. 1 Overview. 2 Sentential Connectives. John Nachbar Washington University December 26, 2014

Logic for Computer Science - Week 4 Natural Deduction

Philosophy 244: Modal Logic Preliminaries

THE ITE RA TION O F DE O NTI C MO DA L I TI E S L. F. GOBLE

Applied Logic. Lecture 1 - Propositional logic. Marcin Szczuka. Institute of Informatics, The University of Warsaw

COMP219: Artificial Intelligence. Lecture 19: Logic for KR

02 Propositional Logic

Intermediate Logic. Natural Deduction for TFL

Proving Completeness for Nested Sequent Calculi 1

Propositional Logic Arguments (5A) Young W. Lim 11/8/16

Tutorial Exercises 1 (mjs)

Classical Propositional Logic

Overview. Knowledge-Based Agents. Introduction. COMP219: Artificial Intelligence. Lecture 19: Logic for KR

Mathematical Logic Prof. Arindama Singh Department of Mathematics Indian Institute of Technology, Madras. Lecture - 15 Propositional Calculus (PC)

Module 7 D and Equivalent Systems

185.A09 Advanced Mathematical Logic

Geach s problem and a variety of consequence relation

Manual of Logical Style (fresh version 2018)

Introduction: What Is Modal Logic?

A Little Deductive Logic

Handout Lecture 1: Standard Deontic Logic

2. The Logic of Compound Statements Summary. Aaron Tan August 2017

Relevant Logic. Daniel Bonevac. March 20, 2013

127: Lecture notes HT18. Week 3. D.I. Semantic and proof-theoretic approaches to consequence (LfP 1.5)

Propositional and Predicate Logic - V

Manual of Logical Style

Class 29 - November 3 Semantics for Predicate Logic

15414/614 Optional Lecture 1: Propositional Logic

Přednáška 12. Důkazové kalkuly Kalkul Hilbertova typu. 11/29/2006 Hilbertův kalkul 1

Introduction: What Is Modal Logic?

Today. Proof using contrapositive. Compound Propositions. Manipulating Propositions. Tautology

Propositional Logic: Syntax

Propositional Logic. Fall () Propositional Logic Fall / 30

PHIL 50 - Introduction to Logic

A SYSTEMATICS OF DEONTIC ACTION LOGICS BASED ON BOOLEAN ALGEBRA

CHAPTER 1 - LOGIC OF COMPOUND STATEMENTS

Nonclassical logics (Nichtklassische Logiken)

Capturing Lewis s Elusive Knowledge

3 The Semantics of the Propositional Calculus

A Little Deductive Logic

Propositional Logic. Jason Filippou UMCP. ason Filippou UMCP) Propositional Logic / 38

Module 5 K and Equivalent Systems

Mathematics 114L Spring 2018 D.A. Martin. Mathematical Logic

PREFERENCE SEMANTICS FOR DEONTIC LOGIC PART I SIMPLE MODELS LOU GOBLE

Propositional and Predicate Logic

Propositional Logic Arguments (5A) Young W. Lim 10/11/16

Introduction to Metalogic

Propositional Logic Review

Canonical models for normal logics (Completeness via canonicity)

Introduction to Metalogic

Propositional natural deduction

Mathematical Logic Part One

Modal logics: an introduction

Propositional and Predicate Logic

Truth-Functional Logic

Truthmaker Maximalism defended again. Eduardo Barrio and Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereyra

Journal of Applied Logic

Logic - recap. So far, we have seen that: Logic is a language which can be used to describe:

Lecture 7. Logic. Section1: Statement Logic.

Logic: Propositional Logic Truth Tables

Propositional Logic Arguments (5A) Young W. Lim 11/29/16

Modal and temporal logic

S4LP and Local Realizability

Propositional Logic: Part II - Syntax & Proofs 0-0

First Order Logic (1A) Young W. Lim 11/18/13

PL: Truth Trees. Handout Truth Trees: The Setup

Examples: P: it is not the case that P. P Q: P or Q P Q: P implies Q (if P then Q) Typical formula:

Dale Jacquette CONUNDRUMS OF CONDITIONALS IN CONTRAPOSITION

Marie Duží

Lecture 11: Gödel s Second Incompleteness Theorem, and Tarski s Theorem

Introduction to Logic in Computer Science: Autumn 2006

Propositional Logic Arguments (5A) Young W. Lim 11/30/16

Section 1.2: Propositional Logic

Gödel s Completeness Theorem

Overview of Logic and Computation: Notes

Chapter 1: The Logic of Compound Statements. January 7, 2008

Gödel s First Incompleteness Theorem (excerpted from Gödel s Great Theorems) Selmer Bringsjord Intro to Logic May RPI Troy NY USA

Completeness for FOL

Overview. I Review of natural deduction. I Soundness and completeness. I Semantics of propositional formulas. I Soundness proof. I Completeness proof.

Today. Next week. Today (cont d) Motivation - Why Modal Logic? Introduction. Ariel Jarovsky and Eyal Altshuler 8/11/07, 15/11/07

Knowledge base (KB) = set of sentences in a formal language Declarative approach to building an agent (or other system):

Modal Sentential Logic I

The Converse of Deducibility: C.I. Lewis and the Origin of Modern AAL/ALC Modal 2011 Logic 1 / 26

Description Logics. Foundations of Propositional Logic. franconi. Enrico Franconi

Paraconsistent Logic, Evidence, and Justification

Logic: Propositional Logic (Part I)

cis32-ai lecture # 18 mon-3-apr-2006

The proposition p is called the hypothesis or antecedent. The proposition q is called the conclusion or consequence.

SOCRATES DID IT BEFORE GÖDEL

Prima Facie Norms, Normative Conflicts, and Dilemmas

Logic. Propositional Logic: Syntax

Dialetheic deontic logic and language-created reality

Notes on Modal Logic

Transcription:

Deontic Logic and Meta-Ethics Deontic Logic as been a field in which quite apart from the questions of antinomies "paradoxes" have played a decisive roles, since the field has been invented. These paradoxes (like Ross' Paradox or the Good Samaritian) are said to show that some intuitively valid logical principles cannot be true in deontic logic, even if the same principles (like deductive closure within a modality) are valid in alethic modal logic. Paraconsistency is not concerned with solutions to these paradoxes. There are, however, lots of problems with ex contradictione qoudlibet in deontic logic, since systems of norms and regulations, even more so if they are historically grown, have a tendency to contain conflicting requirements. To restrict the ensuing problems at least a weak paraconsistent logic is needed. There may be, further on, real antinomies of deontic logic and metaethics (understood comprehensively as including also some basic decision and game theory).

Inconsistent Obligations It often may happen that one is confronted with inconsistent obligations. Consider for example the rule that term papers have to be handed in at the institute's office one week before the session in question combined with the rule that one must not disturb the secretary at the institute's office if she is preparing an institute meeting. What if the date of handing in your paper falls on a day when an institute meeting is prepared? Entering the office is now obligatory (i.e. it is obligatory that it is the case that N.N. enters the office, O(p)), and at the same time it is forbidden (i.e. it is obligatory that it is not the case that N.N. enters the office, O( p)). Now, in standard Deontic Logic we have a conjunction principle (1) O(p q) O(p) O(q) If two states are each obligatory, then it is obligatory to have them both realised. Given principle (1) and our little story about papers we get:

Inconsistent Obligations (II) (2) O() Since standard Deontic Logics are extensions of standard logic, they include ex contradictione qoudlibet (3) () q As normal modal logics standard Deontic Logics contain their equivalent to the rule of necessitation (4) A O(A) and the distribution equivalent to the (K)-Axiom (5) O(p q) (O(p) O(q)) Given the normal character of Deontic Logic we get (6) O((p p) q) (7) O() O(q) and thus with (2) and Modus Ponens (8) O(q) for any sentence "q" whatsoever!

Inconsistent Obligations (III) Thus having an inconsistent normative system as it happens all the day makes it obligatory to do whatever you like (burning the term paper, blowing up the university...). This is unbearable. And that fortunately is not how we reason is these situations. In the example given there may be easy solutions, but in normative systems that have a long history the conflicts and the ways to resolve them are not so obvious (the existence of higher courts to solve such conflicts is witness to this). Given that we have not resolved the conflicts yet the underlying logic has to be a paraconsistent one. The question is, where paraconsistency has to intervene. Should the underlying logic of the non-deontic language (i.e. PC) be changed thus that we no longer have Explosion or similar rules? Or should the behaviour of sentences within the scope of deontic operators be changed, maybe by giving up the additivity of "O( )"?

Standard Deontic Logic We ask ask ourselves if we want to drop any of the principles of standard Deontic Logic. These are: (DF) F(A) := O( A) (DP) P(A) := O( A) (A1) (O(p) O( p)) [Consistency of Obligation] (A2) O(p) O(q) O(p q) [Additivity of Obligation] (A3) O(T) [Inconsistency is forbidden] Rules: Uniform Substitution and Modus Ponens. Consistency assumption are built into standard Deontic Logic. By (A3) and (DF) we have that inconsistency is forbidden, and it is axiomatically demanded that we have no inconsistent obligations by (A1). Presumably both (A1) and (A3) have to be modified. In standard Deontic Logic we have a derived (K)-rule and its contrapositive: (A B) (O(A) O(B)) F(B), (A B) F(A)

Standard PL Application to Obligations The former strategy of changing the underlying logic may be considered the standard application of a PL to questions of obligation. If the underlying logic of the normative language is changed to, say, SKP, then Explosion is no longer valid, and the argument given above does no longer go through. The principles we find in standard Deontic Logic don't have to be changed then. Syntactically this approach works by adding formation rules, axioms and rules for deontic operators to a paraconsistent logic. ["O(A)" with unneeded brackets dropped becomes "OA".] Semantically the typical truth condition of standard Deontic Logic for "O( )" can be taken over, even more so if the paraconsistent system has a modal semantic already. Note that this approach can deal with the occurence of O(A) and O(A) as both true at the propositional level, since Explosion does not ensue by O(A) O(A).

Standard Semantics of Obligations The paraconsistent treatment of deontic conflicts takes over the standard semantics of standard Deontic Logic. (This is the easier when the underlying paraconsistent logic has already a modal semantics.) One needs a (further) deontic accessibility relation between worlds thus that S(w,w') holds if w' is relative to w a normatively optimal world. "O(A)" is true at w if and only if in all worlds w' such that S(w,w') "A" is true in w' (... false iff in some world w' with S(w,w') "A" is false). If permission is not defined in the usual way [P(A) := O( A)] one can give the basic truth condition as: "P(A) is true at w if and only if in some world w' such that S(w,w') "A" is true in w'. (... false iff in all worlds w' with S(w,w') "A" is false). Optimal worlds are intuitively those worlds where everything that should be the case is the case, and everything that is the case isn't bad. Note that in case of inconsistent obligation we have at least one inconsistent deontic optimal world w' with A and A true at w' for some A.

Standard Semantics of Obligations (II) The deontic accessibility relation cannot be reflexive, since otherwise we had: OA A which unfortunately is not the case. Iterations of deontic operators are also controversial. Thus it is questionable whether S should be transitive, since this leads to: OA OOA The two basic conditions on S are that (i) S is serial: ( w)( w')s(w,w'). Seriality means that no world is a deontic dead end. It makes OA PA true. [Remember again the parallel to alethic accessibility conditions.] (ii) S is almost reflexive: ( w,w')(s(w,w') S(w',w')). Almost Reflexivity means that no new obligations are violated by doing what is obligatory. It makes true: O(OA A) Something that should hold.

Inconsistent Obligations in a Consistent World Casey McGinnis takes the later option of keeping the underlying standard logic: The basic idea is to have a logic that can deal with normative conflicts, but makes no further changes in logic, especially not at the non-modal level of ordinary sentences. So the world is considered to be consistent, therefore PC can be applied in its full strength. Obligations may be inconsistent, so the logic within the scope of deontic operators has to be a paraconsistent logic. This approach assumes: - the world is consistent - obligations may be inconsistent - additivity of obligations and other intuitive principles should hold - there may be gaps with respect to obligation (i.e. states such that O(A) is neither true or false, or at least that neither of O(A) and O( A) is true).

Inconsistent Obligations in a Consistent World (II) The idea of keeping the logic within the deontic operators apart from the underlying logic is modelled by keeping PC at the non-modal level and having BN4 [see Chap.9] at the deontic level. The system is called SPDL (for "Semi-Paraconsistent Deontic Logic"). SDPL like SKP singles out a "home world" w 0 as the starting point of accessibility. w 0 is required to be consistent and complete, i.e. atomic sentences receive either {0} or {1} as truth value. { } or {1,0} occur only at worlds different from w 0. Semantic consequence is truth preservation at w 0. "P" is not defined in terms of "O". The semantic rules have to ensure that inconsistency does not travel back from an accessible world via the rules of "O" into the home world: If a w 0 -accessible world is inconsistent for A, then according to the standard semantic rule for "O" given above OA is true at w 0 and false at w 0, and O( A) is true at w 0. So there would be sentences with non-standard values at w 0. This problem can be solved by invoking a double standard in revising the falsity conditions of the standard semantics of "O" and "P".

Inconsistent Obligations in a Consistent World (III) The revised rules are: (SO) 0 v("oa",w) iff (w = w 0 and 1 v("oa",w)) or (w w 0 and ( w')s(w,w') and 0 v("a",w')) (SP) 0 v("pa",w) iff (w = w 0 and 1 v("pa",w)) or (w w 0 and ( w')(s(w,w') 0 v("a",w'))) [The parts for 1 v("oa",w) and 1 v("pa",w) remain the same.] Now one can prove that at w 0 all sentences are bivalent. (Look at the BN4 truth tables for binary values and (S0) and (SP) above.) The Deduction Theorem holds for SPDL. Provable equivalents cannot be substituted for each other in SPDL, since in PC all contradictions are provably equivalent, but O() need not say the same as O(q q), and the presence of deontic conjunction elimination would lead to deontic explosion. SPDL is not a normal modal logic, i.e. neither do "oughtification" for any tautology nor the (K)-rule hold: SPDL T and / SPDL OT.

SPDL Theorems SPDL has as theorems: (T1) P(p q) Pp Pq (T2) Op Pp (T3) O(p q) (Op Oq) (T4) O(p Pp) (T5) OOp Op (T6) O(p q) Op Oq (T7) P(p q) Pp Pq SPDL invalidates: (*1) Op OOp (*2) Pp OPp (*3) Op O(q p) (*4) O(p p) (*5) F() (*6) O() (*7) Pp P p

SPDL Explosion Note: Explosion holds in SPDL (since it has PC as underlying logic). Normative conflicts of the sort OA O( A) can be solved by SPDL and lead neither to deontic explosion nor to general explosion. If, however, we had OA OA this would be a case of an ordinary contradiction (at the home world) and would by the validity of Explosion allow to infer any B whatsoever! The occurence of this problem is softened by not having PA O A, such that the observation of a permission to A does not in conjunction with the norm to have A realized lead to everything. Thus the question is, whether we could ordinarily come into situations where we can ascertain that OA and can ascertain and OA. It seems to me that we can: Imagine a situation where there are two sources of laws/rules, one demanding A the other being quiet on A. The absence of PA O A also deviates from our ordinary notion of permission, as does the absence of PA P( A). These may be reasons to have a paraconsistent logic also as the underlying logic in deontic reasoning.

Questions (Q1) The case of inconsistent obligations, is that a case of weak paraconsistency or of strong paraconsistency, and what does the answer to this question depend upon? (Q2) What does Almost Reflexivity correspond to in alethic modal logic (respectively the logic of provability)?

Exercises (Ex1) That some thing is forbidden means that its negation is obligatory. Consider the deontic necessitation rule A O(A) Why does it say that is forbidden to realise something inconsistent (given the background of standard logic)? (Ex2) If in SPDL one did not revise the falsity condition of "O", but required 0 v("oa",w) 1 v("oa",w) why does this make O(OA A) invalid? [Draw an accessibility diagram.] (Ex3) Show for some of the SPDL theorems/non-theorems why they are valid/invalid.

Further Reading An introduction to Deontic Logic in general is: Aqvist, Lennart. Introduction to Deontic Logic and the Theory of Normative Systems. Neapels, 1987. The deontic "paradoxes" are also dealt with there, as well as Diadic Deontic Logic, which takes conditional obligation to be formalized by "O(A/B)" instead of "B OA". A little overview on the basic systems and there semantics you find at: http://manuel.bremer.bei.t-online.de/sdl.pdf http://manuel.bremer.bei.t-online.de/dydl.pdf (in German). Casey McGinnis' ideas are taken from his forthcoming PhD thesis Paraconsistency and Deontic Logic, (2004). McGinnis also gives a tableau style proof system for BN4 and its deontic application.