Math 225A Model Theory. Speirs, Martin

Similar documents
Math 225A Model Theory. Speirs, Martin

Math 225A Model Theory. Speirs, Martin

Speirs, Martin. Autumn 2013

More Model Theory Notes

Embedding Differential Algebraic Groups in Algebraic Groups

tp(c/a) tp(c/ab) T h(m M ) is assumed in the background.

Categories of imaginaries for additive structures

Imaginaries in Boolean algebras.

Model theory of algebraically closed fields

NOTE ON A THEOREM OF PUTNAM S

Stable embeddedness and N IP

Model theory, algebraic dynamics and local fields

A MODEL-THEORETIC PROOF OF HILBERT S NULLSTELLENSATZ

Introduction to Model Theory

Solutions to Unique Readability Homework Set 30 August 2011

ω-stable Theories: Introduction

Categoricity Without Equality

Embedding Differential Algebraic Groups in Algebraic Groups

Joseph Muscat Universal Algebras. 1 March 2013

Reverse Mathematics of Topology

Commutative Banach algebras 79

Intermediate Model Theory

VAUGHT S THEOREM: THE FINITE SPECTRUM OF COMPLETE THEORIES IN ℵ 0. Contents

Completely regular Bishop spaces

Resolution for Predicate Logic

p-jets and Uniform Unramified Manin-Mumford

Math 250A, Fall 2004 Problems due October 5, 2004 The problems this week were from Lang s Algebra, Chapter I.

Mathematical Logic (IX)

Most Continuous Functions are Nowhere Differentiable

Foundations of Mathematics

MODEL THEORY FOR ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY

Model theory for metric structures

Moreover this binary operation satisfies the following properties

An Even Shorter Model Theory

PRESERVATION THEOREMS IN LUKASIEWICZ MODEL THEORY

c 2010 Hernando Tellez

Countable Borel Equivalence Relations: The Appendix

MASTERS EXAMINATION IN MATHEMATICS SOLUTIONS

Solutions for Assignment 4 Math 402

LING 501, Fall 2004: Quantification

Introduction to Model theory Zoé Chatzidakis CNRS (Paris 7) Notes for Luminy, November 2001

Introduction to Groups

Posets, homomorphisms and homogeneity

MA 320 Introductory Probability, Section 1 Spring 2017 Final Exam Practice May. 1, Exam Scores. Question Score Total. Name:

Lecture 2: Syntax. January 24, 2018

Russell Sets, Topology, and Cardinals

IV. Conformal Maps. 1. Geometric interpretation of differentiability. 2. Automorphisms of the Riemann sphere: Möbius transformations

Model Theory of Real Closed Fields

An introduction to o-minimality

First-Order Logic. 1 Syntax. Domain of Discourse. FO Vocabulary. Terms

CMPS 217 Logic in Computer Science. Lecture #17

Model Theory and Modules, Granada

arxiv:math/ v2 [math.ra] 14 Dec 2005

FINITE MODEL THEORY (MATH 285D, UCLA, WINTER 2017) LECTURE NOTES IN PROGRESS

Easy and hard homogenizable structures

Short notes on Axioms of set theory, Well orderings and Ordinal Numbers

Forking and Dividing in Random Graphs

TROPICAL SCHEME THEORY

Lecture Note of Week 2

Model theory, algebraic dynamics and local fields

EXAMPLES AND EXERCISES IN BASIC CATEGORY THEORY

NOTES ON WELL ORDERING AND ORDINAL NUMBERS. 1. Logic and Notation Any formula in Mathematics can be stated using the symbols

Properties of Almost All Graphs and Generalized Quantifiers

Supplement. Dr. Bob s Modern Algebra Glossary Based on Fraleigh s A First Course on Abstract Algebra, 7th Edition, Sections 0 through IV.

CONTINUOUS MODEL THEORY AND FINITE- REPRESENTABILITY BETWEEN BANACH SPACES

Solutions to Assignment 4

Adjunctions! Everywhere!

The following techniques for methods of proofs are discussed in our text: - Vacuous proof - Trivial proof

Day 5. Friday May 25, 2012

2.1 Sets. Definition 1 A set is an unordered collection of objects. Important sets: N, Z, Z +, Q, R.

MATH 101: ALGEBRA I WORKSHEET, DAY #1. We review the prerequisites for the course in set theory and beginning a first pass on group. 1.

MODEL THEORY OF DIFFERENCE FIELDS

EQ-ALGEBRAS WITH PSEUDO PRE-VALUATIONS. Yongwei Yang 1. Xiaolong Xin

X G X by the rule x x g

Assignment #1 Sample Solutions

THE CLASSIFICATION PROBLEM FOR MODELS OF ZFC

Between proof theory and model theory Three traditions in logic: Syntactic (formal deduction)

Final Exam Review. 2. Let A = {, { }}. What is the cardinality of A? Is

Compact complex manifolds with the DOP and other properties.

Characterizing First Order Logic

REU 2007 Discrete Math Lecture 2

LADDER INDEX OF GROUPS. Kazuhiro ISHIKAWA, Hiroshi TANAKA and Katsumi TANAKA

Boolean Algebras, Boolean Rings and Stone s Representation Theorem

Propositional Logic, Predicates, and Equivalence

φ(a + b) = φ(a) + φ(b) φ(a b) = φ(a) φ(b),

D-MATH Algebra I HS18 Prof. Rahul Pandharipande. Solution 1. Arithmetic, Zorn s Lemma.

MATH 101B: ALGEBRA II PART A: HOMOLOGICAL ALGEBRA

Qualifying Exam Logic August 2005

Löwenheim-Skolem Theorems, Countable Approximations, and L ω. David W. Kueker (Lecture Notes, Fall 2007)

Non-archimedean tame topology and stably dominated types. Ehud Hrushovski François Loeser

Clearly C B, for every C Q. Suppose that we may find v 1, v 2,..., v n

Representations and Linear Actions

Notes on the Banach-Tarski Paradox

Stable embeddedness and N IP

The Vaught Conjecture Do uncountable models count?

Axioms for Set Theory

Lecture 13: Soundness, Completeness and Compactness

Stone-Čech compactification of Tychonoff spaces

Equivalence Relations

Relativizing Tarskian Variables

Transcription:

Math 225A Model Theory Speirs, Martin Autumn 2013

General Information These notes are based on a course in Metamathematics taught by Professor Thomas Scanlon at UC Berkeley in the Autumn of 2013. The course will focus on Model Theory and the course book is Hodges a shorter model theory. As with any such notes, these may contain errors and typos. I take full responsibility for such occurences. If you find any errors or typos (no matter how trivial!) please let me know at mps@berkeley.edu. Lecture 15 Elimination of Imaginaries Definition. An imaginary element of a τ-structure A is a class [a] E where a A n and E is a definable equivalence relation on A n. So an imaginary element can be thought of as an element of a quotient of a definable set by a definable equivalence relation. Thus thinking in terms of the category of definable sets 1, passing to the imaginaries means allowing this category to have quotients. Example (Trivial equivalence relation). If a A n then we may identify a with the class [a] =A n under the (definable) equivalence relation given simply by equality. Definition. A τ-structure A eliminates imaginaries if, for every definable equivalence relation E on A n there exists definable function f : A n A m such that for x, y A n we have xey f(x) = f(y) Remark. The definition given above is what Hodges calls uniform elimination of imaginaries. Remark. If A eliminates imaginaries, then for any definable set X and definable equivalence relation E on X, there is a definable set Y and a definable bijection f : X/E Y. Of course this is not literally true, we should rather say that there is a definable map f : X Y such that f is invariant on the equivalence classes defined by E. So elimination of imaginaries is saying that quotients exists in the category of definable sets. 1 This is the category whose objects are definable sets and morphism are definable functions. 1

Remark. If A eliminates imaginaries then for any imaginary element [a] E = ã there is some tuple â A m such that ã and â are interdefinable i.e. there is a formula ϕ(x, y) such that A = ϕ(a, â), If a Ea then A = ϕ(a, â), If ϕ(b, â) then bea, If ϕ(a, c) then c = â. To get the formula ϕ we use the function f given by the definition of elimination of imaginaries, and let ϕ(x, y) be f(x) = y, (note: then â = f(a)). Almost conversely, if for every A A every imaginary in A is interdefinable with a real (i.e. non-imaginary) tuple then A eliminates imaginaries. We will prove this after proving the compactness theorem. Example. For any structure A, every imaginary in A A is interdefinable with a sequence of real elements. Example. Let A = (N, <, (mod 2)). Then A eliminates imaginaries. For example, to eliminate the odd/even equivalence relation, E, we can define f : N N by mapping x to the least z such that xez. I.e. f is define by the formula f(x) = y xey z[xez y < z y = z]. In the above example we claim furthermore A eliminates all other equivalence relations. This is because A has definable choice functions. Definition. A has definable choice functions if for any formula θ( x, ȳ) there is a definable function f(ȳ) such that ȳ x[θ( x, ȳ) θ(f(ȳ), ȳ)] (i.e. f is a skolem function for θ) and such that ȳ z[ x(θ( x, ȳ) θ( x, z)) f(ȳ) = f( z)] Proposition. If A has definable choice functions then A eliminates imaginaries. Proof. Given a definable equivalence relation E on A n let f be a definable choice function for E(x, y). Since E is an equivalence relation we have ye(f(y), y) and thus f(y) = f(z) yez. y, z ([y] E = [z] E f(y) = f(z)) 2

Example (continued). We now see that A = (N, <, (mod 2)) eliminates imaginaries. Basically since A is well ordered, we can find a least element to witness membership of definable sets, hence we have definable choice functions. Question. Suppose A has Skolem functions. Must A eliminate imaginaries? Example. A = (N, (mod 2)) does not eliminate imaginaries. First note that the only definable subsets of N are, N, 2N and (2n+1)N. This is because A has an automorphisms which switches (2n + 1)N and 2N. Now suppose f : N N M eliminates the equivalence relation (mod 2), i.e. f(x) = f(y) y x (mod 2). Then range(f) is definable and has cardinality 2. Since there are no definable subsets of N of cardinality 2, we must have M > 1. Now let π : N M N be a projection. Then π(range(f)) is a finite nonempty definable subset of N. But no such set exists. Note that if we allow parameters in defining subsets, then A does eliminate imaginaries. Example. Consider a vector space V over a field K. We will put these together into a two-sorted structure (V, K, + V, 0 V, + K, K, K,V, 0 K, 1 K ) here the functions and constant are suitably defined. Now define, for v, w V, Then V/ is the projective space P(V ). v w λ K \ 0 λv = w Question. Can we eliminate imaginaries in this case? Proposition. If the τ-structure A eliminates imaginaries, then A A eliminates imaginaries. Proof. The idea is that an equivalence relation with parameters can be obtained as a fiber of an equivalence relation in more variables. More precisely, let E A n be an equivalence relation definable in A A. Let ϕ(x, y; z) L (τ) and a A l be such that xey A = ϕ(x, y; a). Now define u = v ϕ defines an equivalence relation ψ(x, u, y, v) = u v ϕ(x, y, v) does not define an equivalence relation or or Where ϕ defines an equivalence relation is clearly first-order expressible. Now ψ defines an equivalence relation on A n+l. Letting f : A n+l A M eliminate ψ, then f(, a) eliminates E. 3

Multi-Sorted Structures, A eq We saw that atomisation was a way to force elimination of quantifiers. Similarly one can force elimination of imaginaries, provided one is willing to work in a multi-sorted logic. Given a τ-structure A we will construct A eq as follows. For each definable equivalence relation E on A n we have a sort S E and a function symbol π E interpreted as π Aeq E : A n S Aeq E := A n /E mapping a to [a] E. This shows A eq is interpreted 2 in A. Conversely, A can be interpreted in A eq. Let () =(x) be x S =A. Given an unnested τ-formula ϕ(x 0,..., x l 1 ) consider E ϕ defined by then we have xe ϕ ȳ (ϕ( x) ϕ(ȳ)) π Eϕ : A l S Eϕ This almost works. Question. How can we define, in A eq, the class [ā] Eϕ where A = ϕ(ā)? 2 Here we mean interpreted in the sense of multi sorted structures. 4