Extending the Monoidal T-norm Based Logic with an Independent Involutive Negation

Similar documents
Residuated fuzzy logics with an involutive negation

First-order t-norm based fuzzy logics with truth-constants: distinguished semantics and completeness properties

Adding truth-constants to logics of continuous t-norms: axiomatization and completeness results

Fleas and fuzzy logic a survey

Some consequences of compactness in Lukasiewicz Predicate Logic

On Very True Operators and v-filters

A note on fuzzy predicate logic. Petr H jek 1. Academy of Sciences of the Czech Republic

What is mathematical fuzzy logic

Generalized continuous and left-continuous t-norms arising from algebraic semantics for fuzzy logics

EQ-algebras: primary concepts and properties

A Fuzzy Formal Logic for Interval-valued Residuated Lattices

PRESERVATION THEOREMS IN LUKASIEWICZ MODEL THEORY

Towards Formal Theory of Measure on Clans of Fuzzy Sets

The Blok-Ferreirim theorem for normal GBL-algebras and its application

MTL-algebras via rotations of basic hoops

On the filter theory of residuated lattices

A logical and algebraic treatment of conditional probability

The quest for the basic fuzzy logic

First-Order Logic. 1 Syntax. Domain of Discourse. FO Vocabulary. Terms

DE MORGAN TRIPLES REVISITED

BL-Functions and Free BL-Algebra

On varieties generated by Weak Nilpotent Minimum t-norms

Interpreting Lattice-Valued Set Theory in Fuzzy Set Theory

Omitting Types in Fuzzy Predicate Logics

On Urquhart s C Logic

A logic for reasoning about the probability of fuzzy events

arxiv: v1 [math.lo] 20 Oct 2007

Fuzzy Does Not Lie! Can BAŞKENT. 20 January 2006 Akçay, Göttingen, Amsterdam Student No:

A logic for reasoning about the probability of fuzzy events

On the set of intermediate logics between the truth and degree preserving Lukasiewicz logics

Triple Rotation: Gymnastics for T-norms

Algebra and probability in Lukasiewicz logic

Mathematical Logic. Reasoning in First Order Logic. Chiara Ghidini. FBK-IRST, Trento, Italy

Many-Valued Semantics for Vague Counterfactuals

Monadic GMV -algebras

Embedding logics into product logic. Abstract. We construct a faithful interpretation of Lukasiewicz's logic in the product logic (both

Some properties of residuated lattices

Advances in the theory of fixed points in many-valued logics

Embedding theorems for normal divisible residuated lattices

Free Weak Nilpotent Minimum Algebras

WEAK EFFECT ALGEBRAS

arxiv: v1 [math.lo] 16 Mar 2009

185.A09 Advanced Mathematical Logic

Fuzzy Logics and Substructural Logics without Exchange

Reasoning about uncertainty of fuzzy events: an overview

Modal systems based on many-valued logics

Logic and Implication

Forcing in Lukasiewicz logic

Logics preserving degrees of truth and the hierarchies of abstract algebraic logic

THE FORMAL TRIPLE I INFERENCE METHOD FOR LOGIC SYSTEM W UL

Non-classical Logics: Theory, Applications and Tools

Uninorm Based Logic As An Extension of Substructural Logics FL e

Quantifier elimination, amalgamation, deductive interpolation and Craig interpolation in many-valued logic

On some axiomatic extensions of the monoidal t-norm based logic MTL: an analysis in the propositional and in the first-order case

On the Minimum Many-Valued Modal Logic over a Finite Residuated Lattice

THE FORMAL TRIPLE I INFERENCE METHOD FOR LOGIC SYSTEM W UL

AN ALGEBRAIC STRUCTURE FOR INTUITIONISTIC FUZZY LOGIC

Fuzzy Logic in Narrow Sense with Hedges

Introduction to Fuzzy Sets and Fuzzy Logic

Kamila BENDOVÁ INTERPOLATION AND THREE-VALUED LOGICS

When does a semiring become a residuated lattice?

The Erwin Schrödinger International Boltzmanngasse 9 Institute for Mathematical Physics A-1090 Wien, Austria

Dual-Intuitionistic Logic and Some Other Logics

Model Theory MARIA MANZANO. University of Salamanca, Spain. Translated by RUY J. G. B. DE QUEIROZ

Paraconsistency in Chang s Logic with Positive and Negative Truth Values

EQ-ALGEBRAS WITH PSEUDO PRE-VALUATIONS. Yongwei Yang 1. Xiaolong Xin

States of free product algebras

Chapter I: Introduction to Mathematical Fuzzy Logic

A duality-theoretic approach to MTL-algebras

The prime spectrum of MV-algebras based on a joint work with A. Di Nola and P. Belluce

The logic of perfect MV-algebras

Congruence Boolean Lifting Property

Paraconsistency properties in degree-preserving fuzzy logics

Applied Logic. Lecture 1 - Propositional logic. Marcin Szczuka. Institute of Informatics, The University of Warsaw

Propositional Logics and their Algebraic Equivalents

Basic Algebraic Logic

Propositional Logic Language

The Countable Henkin Principle

03 Review of First-Order Logic

Left-continuous t-norms in Fuzzy Logic: an Overview

Universal Algebra for Logics

Making fuzzy description logic more general

MONADIC FRAGMENTS OF INTUITIONISTIC CONTROL LOGIC

Aggregation and Non-Contradiction

Fuzzy Logics Interpreted as Logics of Resources

First-Order Gödel Logics

CHAPTER 2. FIRST ORDER LOGIC

Logic via Algebra. Sam Chong Tay. A Senior Exercise in Mathematics Kenyon College November 29, 2012

Syntax. Notation Throughout, and when not otherwise said, we assume a vocabulary V = C F P.

Gödel Negation Makes Unwitnessed Consistency Crisp

On Hájek s Fuzzy Quantifiers Probably and Many

The Relation Reflection Scheme

Embedding theorems for classes of GBL-algebras

Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic

Mathematics 114L Spring 2018 D.A. Martin. Mathematical Logic

Combinatorics of Interpolation in Gödel Logic

Gödel Logics a short survey

The variety generated by perfect BL-algebras: an algebraic approach in a fuzzy logic setting

Outline. 1 Background and Aim. 2 Main results (in the paper) 3 More results (not in the paper) 4 Conclusion

On the Independence of the Formal System L *

Transcription:

Extending the Monoidal T-norm Based Logic with an Independent Involutive Negation Tommaso Flaminio Dipartimento di Matematica Università di Siena Pian dei Mantellini 44 53100 Siena (Italy) flaminio@unisi.it Enrico Marchioni Departamento de Lógica, Universidad de Salamanca Campus Unamuno - Edificio FES 37007 Salamanca (Spain) marchioni@usal.es Abstract In this paper we investigate the logic MTL obtained by extending Esteva and Godo s logic MTL with an involutive negation not dependent on the t-norm and with the Baaz s operator. Moreover, we also introduce and study the related predicate calculus MTL. Algebraic and standard completeness results are shown to hold for both MTL and MTL. Keywords: Many-valued logics, Left-continuous t-norms, Involutive negations. 1 Introduction t-norms with an independent involutive negation. Our approach is somehow related to the one carried out in [5]. Indeed we investigate the logic obtained by adding to MTL a unary connective and axioms which capture the behavior of involutive negations. Moreover, we also introduce in MTL the operator [1], which resulted to be fundamental to prove the subdirect representation theorem for MTL -algebras. In the first part of this paper we introduce the logic MTL, the variety of MTL -algebras (its algebraic structures) and we provide algebraic and standard completeness results. Finally, we introduce the predicate calculus MTL and prove both standard and algebraic completeness. The Monoidal T-norm based Logic MTL was introduced by Esteva and Godo in [4], and was shown in [7], by Jenei and Montagna, to be standard complete w.r.t. MTL-algebras over the real unit interval, i.e. algebras defined by leftcontinuous t-norms and their residua. In this logic a negation is definable from the implication and the truth constant 0, so that ϕ stands for ϕ 0. This negation behaves quite differently depending on the chosen left-continuous t- norm and in general is not an involution. Such an operator can be forced to be involutive by adding the axiom ϕ ϕ to MTL. The system so obtained was called in [4] IMTL (Involutive Monoidal T-norm based Logic). However, in such a logic the involution does depend on the t-norm, so that IMTL singles out only those left-continuous t-norms which yield an involutive negation. Clearly, operators like Gödel and Product t-norms are ruled out. This motivated then the interest in studying a logic of left-continuous 860 2 MTL and MTL -algebras Definition 1 The logic MTL is obtained by adding to MTL the operator and the related axioms ( 1) ( 5) (see [1, 6]), and the unary connective and the axioms: ( 1) 0, ( 2) ϕ ϕ, ( 3) (ϕ ψ) ( ψ ϕ), where, for any formula ψ and γ, ψ γ stands for (ψ γ)&(γ ψ). Deduction rules for MTL are modus ponens ( ϕ ϕ ψ ψ ) and generalization ( ϕ ϕ ). Definition 2 An MTL -algebra is a structure L = L,,,,, n, δ, 0, 1 such that L,,,,, 0, 1 is an MTL-algebra; for every

x, y L, δ satisfies the properties of Baaz s projection [1]; moreover the following properties hold: (n1) n(0) = 1, (n2) n(n(x)) = x, (n3) δ(x y) (n(y) n(x)). The notions of theory, proof and model are as usual. The notion of evaluation e from formulas into an MTL -algebra L is extended by requiring: e( ϕ) = n(e(ϕ)). Similarly to BL ([6]), for MTL a deduction theorem in its usual form fails (ϕ ϕ, but for each n N, ϕ n ϕ). Anyway we get the following (weaker) formulation: Theorem 1 Let T be a theory over MTL and let ϕ, ψ be two formulas. Then T {ϕ} ψ iff T ϕ ψ. Since all the axioms of MTL -algebras are expressed in an equational way, it is clear that the class of all MTL -algebras constitutes a variety. Moreover, since the axioms for MTL -algebras are just the algebraic translation of the axioms of MTL, it is clear that the Lindenbaum sentence algebra of MTL is (termwise equivalent to) the free MTL -algebra on countably many generators. Therefore MTL is sound and strongly complete w.r.t. the class of all MTL -algebras. Now we are going to prove that MTL is complete w.r.t. the class of all linearly ordered MTL -algebras. In the sequel we will use the following notation: MTL stands for the logic obtained by adding to MTL the connective and the axioms ( 1 5). Similarly MTL - algebras are the algebraic counterpart of MTL. We follow the line of [6] for the completeness of BL w.r.t. the class of all linearly ordered BL - algebras, and introduce the notion of filter over an MTL -algebra L by requiring F to be a filter over the MTL-reduct of L, plus the further condition x F implies δ(x) F. (1) It is now easy to show that the following holds: Theorem 2 The following are equivalent: (i) MTL ϕ, (ii) ϕ is an L-tautology for each MTL -algebra, (iii) ϕ is an L-tautology for each linearly ordered MTL -agebra. The next step is to use Theorem 2 in order to show that each MTL -algebra can be decomposed as subdirect product of a class of linearly ordered MTL -algebras. We use the following: Lemma 1 Let L be any MTL -algebra and let L be its underlying MTL -algebra. Then L and L have the same congruences. Proof: As usual it is possible to define an isomorphism between the lattice of filters of an MTL - algebra (ordered by inclusion) and the congruence lattice of any MTL -algebra. In particular, for every congruence θ, we define the filter F θ = {x : (x, 1) θ} and the inverse, if F is a filter over an MTL -algebra, then we consider θ F = {(x, y) : x y F and y x F }. Hence in order to prove the claim is sufficient to prove that for every filter over L, θ F is a congruence of L. We already know that θ F is a congruence of L, thus we only need to prove that if (x, y) θ F, then (n(x), n(y)) θ F. Now if (x, y) θ F, then x y F and by (1) δ(x y) F. Since δ(x y) (n(y) n(x)), we obtain (n(y) n(x)) F. Similarily we can prove that y x F implies (n(x) n(y)) F, therefore (n(x), n(y)) θ F and thus the Lemma is proved. Theorem 3 Every MTL -algebra is isomorphic to a subdirect product of a family of linearly ordered MTL -algebras. Proof: By the Birkhoff s subdirect representation theorem (see [8]), every MTL -algebra is isomorphic to a subdirect product of a family of subdirectly irreducible MTL -algebras. Being subdirectly irreducible only depends on the congruence lattice, therefore by the previous Lemma, an MTL -algebra is subdirectly irreducible iff its underlying MTL -algebra is subdirectly irreducible. Since any subdirectly irreducible MTL -algebra is linearly ordered, the claim follows. 861

Finally, Theorem 3 implies the following: Theorem 4 Let Γ be any set of MTL - sentences and let ϕ be any MTL -sentence. If MTL Γ ϕ, then there are a linearly ordered MTL -algebra and an evaluation v of MTL into L such that v(γ) = 1 for each γ Γ and v(ϕ) 1 3 Rational and standard completeness We begin by recalling some definitions and results. Definition 3 ([3]) Let C be any extension of MTL, and let V(C) be the variety generated by the Lindenbaum sentence algebra over C. (1) C has the rational (real) embedding property if any linearly ordered finite or countable structure of V(C) can be embedded into a structure in V(C) whose lattice reduct is Q [0, 1] (the real interval [0, 1]). (2) C is rational (standard) complete iff it is sound and complete w.r.t. interpretations in a class K of MTL-algebras whose lattice reduct is the rational interval [0, 1] (the real interval [0, 1]). (3) C is (finite) strong complete w.r.t. a class K iff for every (finite) set of formulas T and every formula A, one has: T C A iff e(a) = 1 for every evaluation e into any A K. (4) C is (finite) strong rational (standard) complete iff C is (finite) strong complete w.r.t. a class K of MTL-algebras whose lattice reduct is the rational interval [0, 1] (the real interval [0, 1]). Lemma 2 ([3]) Let C be any axiomatic extension of MTL. Then: (i) If C has the real embedding property, then it has the rational embedding property. (ii) If C is finite strong standard complete, then C is finite strong rational complete. (iii) C has the rational (real respectively) embedding property, then C is finite strong rational (standard respectively) complete. 862 Our first step, now, will consist in showing that any countable MTL -chain can be embedded into a countable linearly ordered dense monoid X which will be order-isomorphic to Q [0, 1]. Theorem 5 For every countable linearly ordered MTL -algebra S = S,,, n, δ, S, 0 S, 1 S, there are a countably ordered set X,, a binary operation, two monadic operations and, and a mapping Φ : S X such that the following conditions hold: (1) X is densely ordered, and has a maximum M and a minimum m. (2) X,,, M is a commutative linearly ordered integral monoid. (3) is left-continuous w.r.t. the order topology on X,. (4) is an order reversing involutive mapping. { M if x = M (5) For any x X, x = m otherwise. (6) Φ is an embedding of the structure S,, n, δ, S, 0 S, 1 S into X,,,,, m, M, and for all s, t S, Φ(s t) is the residuum of Φ(s) and Φ(t) in X,,,,, m, M. Proof: Notice that (1), (2) and (3) have been proved in [7]. Then we just have to show (4) and (5), and extend the proof of (6) given in [7] so as to cope with the operations and. For any s S, let ς(s) be the successor of s if it exists, and take ς(s) = s otherwise. Let X = {(s, 1) s S} {(s, r) s, s = ς(s ) > S s, r Q (0, 1)}. For any (s, q), (t, r) X, let (s, q) (t, r) iff either s < S t, or s = t and q r. Clearly, is a linear lexicographic order with a maximum (1 S, 1) and a minimum (0 S, 1). To prove (4), define for any (s, q) X: { (n(s), 1) if q = 1; (s, q) = (ς(n(s)), 1 q) otherwise.

It is easy to see that is indeed an order-reversing and involutive mapping. To prove (5), let, for any (s, q) X: { (δ(s), 1) if q = 1; (s, q) = (0 S, 1) otherwise. Obviously (s, q) = (1 S, 1) iff s = 1 and q = 1, otherwise we have the minimum (0 S, 1). To prove (6), let for every s S, Φ(s) = (s, 1). Clearly Φ(0 S ) = (0 S, 1) and Φ(1 S ) = (1 S, 1). Moreover, Φ(s) Φ(t) = (s, 1) (t, 1) = (s t, 1) = Φ(s t). Finally, let Φ(n(s)) = (n(s), 1) and Φ(δ(s)) = (δ(s), 1). Clearly, Φ(n(s)) = (s, 1), and Φ(δ(s)) = (s, 1). Thus, Φ is an embedding of partially ordered monoids equipped with an order-reversing involutive mapping. To conclude, notice that the fact that for all s, t S, Φ(s t) is the residuum of Φ(s) and Φ(t), is shown in [7]. We now prove that X is order-isomorphic to Q [0, 1], and define a structure Q [0, 1],,,,, 0, 1 which satisfies (1-6). Such a structure can be embedded over the real unit interval. The resulting structure [0, 1], ˆ, ˆ, ˆ,, 0, 1 will be a linearly ordered MTL algebra where the initial MTL -chain can be embedded. This clearly means that MTL has the real embedding property. Theorem 6 Every countable MTL -chain can be embedded into a standard algebra. Proof: As shown in the above theorem X, is a countable, dense, linearly-ordered set with maximum and minimum. Then X, is orderisomorphic to the rationals in [0, 1] with the natural order Q [0, 1],. Let Ψ be such an isomorphism. Suppose that (1-6) hold, and let for α, β [0, 1], - α β = Ψ(Ψ 1 (α) Ψ 1 (β)), - α = Ψ((Ψ 1 (α)) ), - α = Ψ((Ψ 1 (α)) ), and let for all s S, Φ (s) = Ψ(Φ(s)). Hence, we have a structure Q [0, 1],,,,, 0, 1, that, along with Φ, satisfies (1-6). Now, we can assume, without loss of generality, that X = Q [0, 1] and that is. It is shown in [7, 9] that such a structure is embeddable into an analogous structure [0, 1], ˆ, over the real unit interval, where, for any α, β [0, 1]: αˆ β = sup x X:x α sup x y. y X:y β The operation ˆ is shown to be a left-continuous t-norm which extends. Now, define for any α [0, 1] αˆ = inf x X:x α x. We show that such ˆ is an order-reversing involutive mapping which extends. First let αˆ = sup y. y X:α y We prove that αˆ = αˆ, which means the negation defined is continuous. In general we have that αˆ αˆ. Suppose the inequality is strict: i.e. αˆ < αˆ. This means that there is some z Q such that αˆ < z < αˆ. Therefore, for any x α, z < x and, for any y α, y < z. Hence we have that, for any x α, x < z and, for any y α, z < y. Then z must equal α, but α [0, 1]\Q [0, 1], so we obtain a contradiction. Notice that if α Q, then the above equivalence clearly holds. Thus we have proved αˆ = αˆ. It is easy to see that 0ˆ = 1, 1ˆ = 0 and that ˆ is order-reversing. It remains to prove that (αˆ )ˆ = α. Notice that (αˆ )ˆ = (inf x α x )ˆ = sup x α ((x ) ) = sup x α x = α. Now, define for any α [0, 1] { 1 if α = 1; αˆ = 0 otherwise. Then Q [0, 1],,,, 0, 1 embeds into [0, 1], ˆ, ˆ, ˆ,, 0, 1. Given left-continuity of ˆ over [0, 1], [0, 1], ˆ, ˆ, ˆ, ˆ,, 0, 1 is a linearly ordered MTL -algebra, where the residuum ˆ always exists. Hence the initial MTL -chain S can be embedded into the standard algebra [0, 1], ˆ, ˆ, ˆ, ˆ,, 0, 1. 863

Hence, given Definition 3 and Lemma 2, we easily obtain the following result. Theorem 7 MTL has the real (rational) embedding property, is strong standard (rational) complete, and consequently standard (rational) complete. 4 Predicate calculus: MTL We begin by enlarging the propositional language with a set of predicates P red, a set of object variables V ar and a set of object constants Const together with the two classical quantifiers and. The notion of formula is trivially generalized by saying that if ϕ is a formula and x V ar, then both ( x)ϕ and ( x)ϕ are formulas. Definition 4 Let L be an MTL -algebra. An L-interpretation for a predicate language L is a structure M = M, (r P ) P P red, (m c ) c Const, where: M is a non-empty set, r P : M ar(p ) A for any P P red, where ar(p ) stands for the ariety of the predicate P, m c M for each c Const. For every evaluation of variables v : V ar M, the truth value of a formula ϕ ( ϕ L M,v ) is inductively defined as follows: P (x,..., c,...) L M,v = r P (v(x),..., m c,...), where v(x) M for each variable x, The truth value commutes with connectives of MTL, ( x)ϕ L M,v = inf{ ϕ L M,v : v(y) = v (y) for all variables, except x} and ( x)ϕ L M,v = sup{ ϕ L M,v : v(y) = v (y) for all variables, except x}. The infimum and the supremum might not exist in L. In that case the truth value remains undefined. A structure M is called L-safe if all infima and suprema needed for definition of the truth value of any formula exist in L. In such a case the truth 864 value of a formula ϕ in an L-safe structure M corresponds to ϕ L M = inf{ ϕ L M,v : v : V ar M}. Definition 5 The axioms for MTL are those of MTL plus the following axioms with quantifiers (with x not free in v for ( 2), ( 3) and ( 2); and with t substitutable for x in ϕ(x) for ( 1) and ( 1)): ( 1) ( x)ϕ(x) ϕ(t), ( 2) ( x)(v ϕ) (v ( x)ϕ), ( 3) ( x)(ϕ v) (( x)ϕ v), ( 1) ϕ(t) ( x)ϕ(x), ( 2) ( x)(ϕ v) (( x)ϕ v). Rules for MTL are those of MTL plus generalization for the quantifier: ϕ ( x)ϕ By using the connective it is easy to see that a quantifier is definable by the other one, for instance ( x)ϕ(x) is ( x)( ϕ(x)). Therefore the above set of axioms can surely be simplified. Theorem 8 Let T be a theory over MTL and ϕ a formula. T proves ϕ over MTL iff ϕ L M,v = 1 L for each MTL -algebra L, each L- safe L-model M of T and each v. Proof: (Sketch). Just inspect the corresponding proof given in [6] and see that the proof for MTL is similar (using the Deduction Theorem 1 given here). 5 Standard completeness for MTL First, we need the following Lemma. Lemma 3 ([9]) Let S be a countably linearly ordered MTL algebra, and let X be the dense linearly ordered commutative monoid above defined. Let Φ be the embedding of S into X, as above. Then, Φ is a complete lattice embedding, i.e., if a = sup{a i : i I} S, then sup{φ(a i ) : i I} = Φ(a); if c = inf{a i : i I} S, then inf{φ(a i ) : i I} = Φ(c).

Theorem 9 For every MTL formula ϕ, the following are equivalent: (i) MTL ϕ. (ii) For every left-continuous t-norm on [0, 1] and for every evaluation v in the linearly ordered MTL -algebra [0, 1],,, n, δ,, 0, 1, where is the residuum of, v(ϕ) = 1. Proof: (i) (ii) is immediate. The converse is an easy adaptation of the proof given in [9], Theorem 5.4 (iii). Indeed, suppose that MTL ϕ, then there is a countable MTL -chain S where v(ϕ) 1. As done in the proof of standard completeness for the MTL -logic we can define an embedding Ψ of S into a standard MTL -algebra over the real unit interval. Such an embedding is complete by the above Lemma. Then we define an evaluation v over the standard algebra by letting for every atomic formula ψ, v (ψ) = Ψ(v(ψ)). Hence for any closed formula χ we have that v (χ) = Ψ(v(χ)). This clearly implies that v (ϕ) 1. 6 Final remarks In this paper we investigated an extension of the Monoidal T-norm based Logic MTL with an involutive negation that does not depend on the t- norm operation. We introduced the propositional logic MTL and the predicate calculus MTL, and proved standard and algebraic completeness for both systems. The logic obtained is interesting, since by defining a new connective ϕ ψ ( ϕ& ψ), it allows to represent by means of left-continuos t-norms and involutions all dual t-conorms. This is not possible in any other residuated fuzzy logic. Moreover, notice that we can also define S-implications as follows: ϕ ψ ϕ ψ. This suggests that the work carried out in [2] might be recovered under our framework. Future work will focus on proving Kripke-style completeness for the systems obtained and on introducing an involutive negation in other extensions of MTL and especially in BL. Acknowledgments Marchioni recognizes support of the grant No. AP2002-1571 of the Ministerio de Educación y Ciencia of Spain. The authors would also like to thank Francesc Esteva, Lluís Godo and Franco Montagna for their remarkable advices. References [1] Baaz M. Infinite-valued Gödel logics with 0-1- projections and relativizations. In GÖDEL 96, LNL 6, Hájek P. (Ed.), Springer-Verlag, pp. 23 33, 1996. [2] Butnariu E., Klement E. P. and Zafrany S. On triangular norm-based propositional fuzzy logics Fuzzy Sets and Systems, 69, 241 255, 1995. [3] Esteva F., Gispert J., Godo L. and Montagna F. On the standard and rational completeness of some axiomatic extensions of the monoidal t-norm logic. Studia Logica, 71, 199 226, 2002. [4] Esteva F. and Godo L. Monoidal t-norm based logic: towards a logic for left-continuous t-norms. Fuzzy Sets and Systems, 124, 271 288, 2001. [5] Esteva F., Godo L., Hájek P. and Navara M. Residuated fuzzy logics with an involutive negation. Archive for Mathematical Logic, 39, 103 124, 2000. [6] Hájek P. Metamathematics of Fuzzy Logic. Kluwer 1998. [7] Jenei S. and Montagna F. A proof of standard completeness for Esteva and Godo s logic MTL. Studia Logica, 70, 183 192, 2002. [8] McKenzie R., McNulty G. and Taylor W. Algebras, Lattices, Varieties, Vol. I, Wadsworth and Brooks/Cole, Monterey CA, 1987. [9] Montagna F. and Ono H. Kripke semantics, undecidability and standard completeness for Esteva and Godo s logic MTL. Studia Logica, 71, 227 245, 2002. 865