COMPARING PERIODIC ORBITS OF MAPS OF THE INTERVAL

Similar documents
Alexander M. Blokh and Ethan M. Coven

Periodic orbits of continuous mappings of the circle without fixed points

Maximum topological entropy of permutations and cycles. Deborah King. University of Melbourne. Australia

PERIODS IMPLYING ALMOST ALL PERIODS FOR TREE MAPS. A. M. Blokh. Department of Mathematics, Wesleyan University Middletown, CT , USA

The ordering on permutations induced by continuous maps of the real line

THE FIXED POINT PROPERTY FOR CONTINUA APPROXIMATED FROM WITHIN BY PEANO CONTINUA WITH THIS PROPERTY

Rotation set for maps of degree 1 on sun graphs. Sylvie Ruette. January 6, 2019

SHARKOVSKY S THEOREM KEITH BURNS AND BORIS HASSELBLATT

V^O,ff)= fl U 9k(p-e,p + e),

Kneading Sequences for Unimodal Expanding Maps of the Interval

NEW ORDER FOR PERIODIC ORBITS OF INTERVAL MAPS. Alexander Blokh and Micha l Misiurewicz. November 7, 1995

SYNCHRONOUS RECURRENCE. Contents

Extension of continuous functions in digital spaces with the Khalimsky topology

CHAOTIC UNIMODAL AND BIMODAL MAPS

A lower bound for the maximum topological entropy of 4k + 2 cycles of interval maps

CIRCULAR CHROMATIC NUMBER AND GRAPH MINORS. Xuding Zhu 1. INTRODUCTION

PERIODIC POINTS OF THE FAMILY OF TENT MAPS

ELEMENTARY PROOF OF THE CONTINUITY OF THE TOPOLOGICAL ENTROPY AT θ = 1001 IN THE MILNOR THURSTON WORLD

ORIENTATION-REVERSING MORSE-SMALE DIFFEOMORPHISMS ON THE TORUS

A complement to the theory of equivariant finiteness obstructions

Decomposition of Riesz frames and wavelets into a finite union of linearly independent sets

Limits at Infinity. Horizontal Asymptotes. Definition (Limits at Infinity) Horizontal Asymptotes

Newton, Fermat, and Exactly Realizable Sequences

arxiv: v1 [math.co] 3 Nov 2014

On the Frobenius Numbers of Symmetric Groups

On zero-sum partitions and anti-magic trees

Formal power series rings, inverse limits, and I-adic completions of rings

Irredundant Families of Subcubes

AN EXTENSION OF A THEOREM OF NAGANO ON TRANSITIVE LIE ALGEBRAS

ON EXPONENTIAL GROWTH RATES FOR FREE GROUPS

FOLIATIONS WITH NONORIENTABLE LEAVES

Primary Decompositions of Powers of Ideals. Irena Swanson

School of Mathematics and Statistics. MT5836 Galois Theory. Handout 0: Course Information

ZEROS OF SPARSE POLYNOMIALS OVER LOCAL FIELDS OF CHARACTERISTIC p

GENERALIZATIONS OF SOME ZERO-SUM THEOREMS. Sukumar Das Adhikari Harish-Chandra Research Institute, Chhatnag Road, Jhusi, Allahabad , INDIA

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved.

COMBINATORIAL DIMENSION OF FRACTIONAL CARTESIAN PRODUCTS

II. Products of Groups

Definitions, Theorems and Exercises. Abstract Algebra Math 332. Ethan D. Bloch

CHAOTIC BEHAVIOR IN A FORECAST MODEL

MINIMAL.4-SETS, INFINITE ORBITS, AND FIXED ELEMENTS

5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting

Week 15-16: Combinatorial Design

MULTI PING-PONG AND AN ENTROPY ESTIMATE IN GROUPS. Katarzyna Tarchała, Paweł Walczak. 1. Introduction

When is the Ring of 2x2 Matrices over a Ring Galois?

Changing coordinates to adapt to a map of constant rank

STABILIZATION BY A DIAGONAL MATRIX

TOPOLOGICAL ENTROPY FOR DIFFERENTIABLE MAPS OF INTERVALS

ON EQUIVALENCE OF ANALYTIC FUNCTIONS TO RATIONAL REGULAR FUNCTIONS

Homological Decision Problems for Finitely Generated Groups with Solvable Word Problem

Square 2-designs/1. 1 Definition

Patterns and minimal dynamics for graph maps

ADDING MACHINES, ENDPOINTS, AND INVERSE LIMIT SPACES. 1. Introduction

THE REGULAR ELEMENT PROPERTY

THE GROUP OF UNITS OF SOME FINITE LOCAL RINGS I

A. M. Blokh. Department of Mathematics, University of Alabama at Birmingham, Birmingham, AL , USA. March 31, 1993

L Enseignement Mathématique, t. 40 (1994), p AN ERGODIC ADDING MACHINE ON THE CANTOR SET. by Peter COLLAS and David KLEIN

Exact Devaney Chaos and Entropy

Discrete dynamics on the real line

Real Analysis Math 131AH Rudin, Chapter #1. Dominique Abdi

ON CLUSTERING IN CENTRAL CONFIGURATIONS GREGORY BUCK. (Communicated by Kenneth R. Meyer)

Combinatorial Interpretations of a Generalization of the Genocchi Numbers

Boolean Inner-Product Spaces and Boolean Matrices

MEAN DIMENSION AND AN EMBEDDING PROBLEM: AN EXAMPLE

Patterns and Cycles in Dynamical Systems. Kate Moore Dartmouth College June 30, 2017

DIMENSIONS OF JULIA SETS OF HYPERBOLIC ENTIRE FUNCTIONS

REVERSALS ON SFT S. 1. Introduction and preliminaries

HW2 Solutions Problem 1: 2.22 Find the sign and inverse of the permutation shown in the book (and below).

THE SHARKOVSKY THEOREM: A NATURAL DIRECT PROOF

MATH 326: RINGS AND MODULES STEFAN GILLE

OTTO H. KEGEL. A remark on maximal subrings. Sonderdrucke aus der Albert-Ludwigs-Universität Freiburg

ROTATION SETS OF TORAL FLOWS

Transitive sensitive subsystems for interval maps

A CHARACTERIZATION OF STRICT LOCAL MINIMIZERS OF ORDER ONE FOR STATIC MINMAX PROBLEMS IN THE PARAMETRIC CONSTRAINT CASE

NAME: Mathematics 205A, Fall 2008, Final Examination. Answer Key

Prime Properties of the Smallest Ideal of β N

MATH 8253 ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY WEEK 12

Dimension of the mesh algebra of a finite Auslander-Reiten quiver. Ragnar-Olaf Buchweitz and Shiping Liu

290 J.M. Carnicer, J.M. Pe~na basis (u 1 ; : : : ; u n ) consisting of minimally supported elements, yet also has a basis (v 1 ; : : : ; v n ) which f

The Sine Map. Jory Griffin. May 1, 2013

A.M.Blokh. VGNC, Moscow, USSR (current address: MPI für Marthematik, Gottfried-Claren-Strasse 26, Bonn, Germany)

Lecture 16 Symbolic dynamics.

The Skorokhod reflection problem for functions with discontinuities (contractive case)

ON MULTI-AVOIDANCE OF RIGHT ANGLED NUMBERED POLYOMINO PATTERNS

Perron-Frobenius theorem

Stanford Mathematics Department Math 205A Lecture Supplement #4 Borel Regular & Radon Measures

TOPOLOGICAL ENTROPY AND TOPOLOGICAL STRUCTURES OF CONTINUA


MATH 117 LECTURE NOTES

arxiv: v1 [math.co] 20 Dec 2016

ON DOUBLE COVERINGS OF A POINTED NON-SINGULAR CURVE WITH ANY WEIERSTRASS SEMIGROUP

CHAPTER I. Rings. Definition A ring R is a set with two binary operations, addition + and

ON MIXING AND PARTIAL MIXING

Section II.1. Free Abelian Groups

On Weird and Pseudoperfect

TOPOLOGICAL CONJUGACY AND TRANSITIVITY

Discrete Applied Mathematics

LEVEL MATRICES G. SEELINGER, P. SISSOKHO, L. SPENCE, AND C. VANDEN EYNDEN

TOEPLITZ KNEADING SEQUENCES AND ADDING MACHINES

Counting Peaks and Valleys in a Partition of a Set

Transcription:

TRANSACTIONS OF THE AMERICAN MATHEMATICAL SOCIETY Volume 333, Number 2, October 1992 COMPARING PERIODIC ORBITS OF MAPS OF THE INTERVAL C. BERNHARDT, E. COVEN, M. MISIUREWICZ, AND I. MULVEY Abstract. Let n and 6 be cyclic permutations of finite ordered sets. We say that n forces 6 if every continuous map of the interval which has a representative of n also has one of 6. We give a geometric version of Jungreis' combinatorial algorithm for deciding in certain cases whether n forces 9. Introduction This paper is concerned with the forcing relation between finite cyclic permutations. Let it be a cyclic permutation of {\,..., k} and let /:/ / be a continuous map of a compact interval. A representative of it in / is a subset {x\ < < Xk} of / such that f{x\) = xk^) (i I,..., k). We say that it forces 6 if every continuous map of a compact interval which has a representative of it also has a representative of 6. The study of the forcing relation is a natural outgrowth of the proof in [BGMY] of Sarkovskii's Theorem. The formal study of the forcing relation was begun by S. Baldwin [Ba], who showed that forcing is a partial order and gave an algorithm for deciding whether it forces 6. Baldwin's algorithm checks, in terms of closed walks through directed graphs with oriented edges (oriented Markov graphs), whether 6 has a representative in the canonical it-linear map Ln, defined on [1, k] by Ln = it on {1,..., k] and Ln is linear on [1, 2],..., [k - 1, k]. I. Jungreis [J, Theorem 5.1] gave a faster algorithm, in terms of itineraries, for deciding whether it forces 0 in certain cases. In this paper, we present an effective algorithm for deciding whether it forces 6 in the cases considered by Jungreis. Our algorithm is in some sense the same as Jungreis'. However, our implementation is in terms of rational numbers instead of itineraries, and our proof is geometric instead of combinatorial, avoiding the "intricate combinatorial theorem" of [J, 6]. The main idea of our proof is to compare canonical representatives of it and 8 in maps we call horseshoe maps. Throughout this paper, the lower case Greek letters it, 6, n will denote cyclic permutations, and it = {a\a2 a ) means that n{a\) = ai,..., n(a -i) = an, it(an) = a\. The upper case Latin letters P, Q, R will denote representatives of cyclic permutations, i.e., periodic orbits. The upper case Latin letter H will denote a horseshoe map (defined in the next section). Received by the editors July 13, 1990. 1980 Mathematics Subject Classification (1985 Revision). Primary 58F20, 58F08, 58H20. 701 1992 American Mathematical Society 0002-9947/92 $1.00+ $.25 per page

702 C. BERNHARDT ET AL. 1. Background Let n>2. The horseshoe map H : [0, 1] [0, 1] of type n+ is defined as follows: for x e [i/n, (i + 1)/«] (i = 0,..., n 1), H is continuous, maps each of the n laps f n(x - i/n) if / is even, \ 1 - n(x - i/n) if i is odd. 7, = [0, \/n],i2 = [l/n,2/n],...,in = [(n-l)/n, 1] linearly onto [0, 1], and is increasing on the first lap. The horseshoe map of type n~ is defined analogously. It is decreasing on the first lap. In either case, we write 1(H) = n. Let n > 0. We say that it has type n+ (resp. n~) if the canonical it -linear map Ln has n laps, and is increasing (resp. decreasing) on the first lap. In either case, we write /(ft) = n. Note that the trivial permutation (1) has type 0+ and type 0~. For any it and any H, the set of representatives of it in H is finite. It is nonempty if and only if it and H have the same type or l(it) < 1(H) [MN]. An important tool in the early study of forcing was the observation by Baldwin [Ba, Lemma 3.1 and Theorem 3.3] (see also [Bel, Lemmas 1.7 and 1.8]) that if 8 has a representative in the canonical it -linear map Ln, then it forces 8. We shall use a variant of this result involving horseshoe maps. Suppose P is a periodic orbit of H. For i = 0,..., n (n = 1(H)), define d min{\p - i/n\ : p e P} and let p be the unique point in P such that \pi - i/n\ = di. We say that P fits H if n = 2 or if n > 3 and dj + d +i < \/n (i = 1,..., n - 2). In either case, the P-truncation Hp of H, defined by f H(Pi) if \x - i/n\ <dt, p \ H(x) otherwise, (i = 0, 1.n) is well defined. The figure below shows the graph of Hp, where H is the horseshoe map of type 3+ and P = {46/365, 76/365, 138/365, 218/365, 228/365, 316/365} is a representative of (136425) in H.

PERIODIC orbits of maps of the interval 703 Remark. If P does not fit H, then Hp may not be well defined. For example, consider the periodic orbit {4/63, 16/63,62/63} of the horseshoe map of type 4+. Lemma 1. Let P be a representative of it in H such that Hp is well defined. If 8 has a representative in Hp, then it forces 8. Proof. For x e [0, 1], let x' (resp. x") be the right (resp. left) endpoint of the largest closed interval containing x on which Hp is constant. If P = {xi < < XiJ, set Xq = 0 and x^.+1 = 1. Then every periodic orbit of Hp lies in Uí=o[*í» x"+\\ Therefore by [MN, Theorem 1.21], it forces 8. D We say that it fits H if the set of representatives of it in H is nonempty and every representative of it in H fits H. We leave the proof of the following lemma to the reader. Lemma 2. it fits H if and only if one of the following conditions holds: (1) it and H have the same type. (2) l(it) = 1(H) - 1. (3) H has type n± and it has type (n - 2)=f Suppose that P and Q are periodic orbits of H such that Hq is well defined. We say that P is tighter than Q if HQ\P = H\P, i.e., H and HQ agree on P. Lemma 3. Suppose that P and Q are periodic orbits of H suchthat Hq is well defined. Then the following statements are equivalent: (1) P is tighter than Q. (2) di(p)>di(q)(i = 0,...,l(H)). If, in addition, P has at least three members, then the following statement is equivalent to the others: (3) di(p)>di(q)(i=l,...,l(h)-l). Proof. The equivalence of (1) and (2) follows from the definitions. We show that (3) implies (1) if P has at least three members. Let n = 1(H) and let Hq be the map defined analogously to Hq, except that we do not truncate at_0 or 1, i.e., we ignore do and d. Then P is a periodic orbit of Hq. Since Hq = Hq on [\/n-d\, (n-l)/n+d -i] and this interval is mapped to itself by Hq, it suffices to show that PC [\/n-d\, (n-l)/n+d -i]. The complement of [l/n - d\, (n - \)/n + d _i] consists of two intervals, K\ and K2. H is linear on these two intervals, either H(K\) ílíi = 0 or H(Ki)nK2 = 0, and either H(K2)C\KX = 0 or H(K2)nK2 = 0. Therefore any periodic orbit of H which lies in K\ UK2 can have only one or two members. D In order to use Lemmas 1 and 3 effectively, we need a method of constructing representatives of a cyclic permutation in a horseshoe map. The tool we shall use is itineraries. An H-itinerary (itinerary for short when H is clear) of a point x [0, 1] is a sequence x = (r(j))ji0 such that Hj(x) e /t(j) (;' = 0, 1,...). The correspondence between points and itineraries is one-to-one, except for those points whose orbit meets the set of turning points of H. Such points have two itineraries. Since H maps the turning points to 0 or 1, this cannot happen for

704 C. BERNHARDT ET AL. periodic points. Thus there is a one-to-one correspondence between periodic points and periodic itineraries. This correspondence preserves (least) periods. Itineraries are ordered in the following way. Define e = +1 (resp. -1) if H is increasing (resp. decreasing) on Ik, (0) = +1, and Ç(k) et(0) et(fc-i) (k > 1). If T t a are itineraries, let k be the least integer such that x(k) ^ a(k). Then x < a if Ç(k) = +1 and x(k) < a(k), or if Ç(k) = -1 and t(/c) > a(k). In the other two cases, x > a. Lemma 4 (cf. [MT, Lemma 3.1]). Let x and y be points in [0, 1] having unique itineraries x and a. Then x < y if and only if x < a. Theorem 5. Let 1(H) = n and let x be a sequence with x(i) e {I,..., n} (i 0, 1,...). Then the unique point in [0,1] whose itinerary is x is Ylf=oajlnJ+x where aj = x(j) - 1 if CO') = +1, a = n- x(j) if (;') = -1. Proof. Using induction on m, it is straightforward to show that for m > 0, the left endpoint of Im nh-l(it{i))n- f]h-m(it{m)), which has length l/«m+1, is,"w";'+1- We say that it is a doubling of r\ if for some even k, it is defined on {I,..., k}, n is defined on {1,..., k/2}, and n{2i - 1, 2/} = {2n(i) - 1, 2n(i)} (i = I,..., k/2). In this case, we write tj = it 2. Lemma 6 [Be2, Theorem 1.12]. (1) it forces it/2. (2) If it forces 8 ^ it, then it/2 forces 8. 2. The algorithm In the propositions below, it is defined on {I,..., k}, it fits H, and n = 1(H). Label the laps of Ln from left to right as follows: (1) J\,..., J if H and n have the same type, (2) J\,..., J -i if H has type n± and it has type (n - 1)±, (3) J2,..., Jn if H has type n± and it has type (n - l)=p, (4) J2,..., Jn-\ if H has type n± and it has type (n - 2)=f. In cases (2), (3), and (4), we allow Ln to have "phantom" laps J\ and/or J. In this way, Ln is increasing or decreasing on Jm according as H is increasing or decreasing on Im (m = 1,..., n). We define below an itinerary x which is the largest L^-itinerary of 1, even allowing "phantom" itineraries, where the laps of Ln are labelled as above. If n = (1), then H has type 2±. In this case, let x = 111 if H has type 2-, and x = 222 if H has type 2+. If it ^ (1), we define x inductively as follows. Let t(0) = 1 if (1) or (2) hold, t(0) = 2 if (3) or (4) hold. Assume that t(0),..., x(j - 1) have been defined. If L{(\) e J only, let x(j) = i. If L{(\) e J n JM, let x(j) = i if Ç(j) = -l, x{j) = i + 1 if CO') = +1 (Here 1 e Jx n /2 in cases (3) and (4), and /c e Jn-\ n / in cases (2) and (4).) Let r be the unique point in [0,1] whose //-itinerary is x, and let R(it) be the orbit of r. Since x is an./^-itinerary of 1, r min R(it). In the sequel, C corresponds to the itinerary x defined above. Proposition 7 below is straightforward.

PERIODIC ORBITS OF MAPS OF THE INTERVAL 705 Proposition 7. If Ln has a turning point at L{(\) which is a relative maximum (resp. minimum), then CO + 1) = -1 (resp. +1). (Here 1 is a turning point of Ln in cases (3) and (4), and k is a turning point in cases (2) and (4).) Proposition 8. R(n) is a representative of it or it/2. Proof. The result is true for it = (1). If it = (12), the result is true since x = 111 if H has type 2- and x = 222 if H has type 2+ and 3+. So assume that it ^ (1) or (12), and hence that k > 3. We show that the period of R(x) divides k. To do this, it suffices to show that Ç(k) = +1, for then x and hence r have periods which divide k. Since L (l) 1, either Ln has a turning point at L -1(l) which is a relative minimum, or L ~ ' ( 1 ) = k / and Ln is decreasing on Jn. In the first case, Ç(k) = +1 by Proposition 7. In the second case, et(^_i) = -1 and Ln has a turning point at L ~2(l) which is a relative maximum. Therefore by Proposition 7, l(k- l) = -I and so Ç(k) = +1. Since k > 3, R(it) cannot lie on a single lap of H, and therefore the period of R(it) is greater than one. This period is k/s, where 1 < s < k. Now Ln permutes the blocks {I,..., s}, {s+l,..., 2s},..., {k-s+l,..., k}, and is monotone on each block. Therefore s = 1 or 2. The map <p: {1,..., k} -» R(it), defined by p(i) = HJ(r), where i = L (l), preserves the order relation <. Thus R(it) is a representative of it or it/2 according as 5 = 1 or 2. D Proposition 9. R(it) is a representative of it/2 or it according as it is a doubling or not. Proof. If it is not a doubling, then it 2 is not defined, and so by Proposition 8, R(it) is a representative of it. Suppose then that it is a doubling. Let L (1) 6 7, n JM, where 0<j<k/2. If Li+k/2(l) < LJn(l), then CO') = -1 and CO + k/2) = +1, while if L{+k/2(l) > L{(\), then CO) = +1 and CO + k/2) = -1. In either case, x(j + k/2) x(j). Therefore x and hence r have period k/2. Thus R(it) is not a representative of it, and so by Proposition 8 it must be a representative of it/2. D Proposition 10. If it is a doubling, then Ç(k/2) = -1. Proof. Setting j k/2 in the proof of Proposition 9, we get L*(l) < Lj (1), and hence C(fc/2) = -1. D Proposition 11. R(n) fits H. Proof. We need only consider the case that it is a doubling. We may assume that n > 3, for if n = 2 there is nothing to prove. By Proposition 10, Ç(k/2) = -1. Then by [MN, Proposition 9.8(1)], the orbit P of the largest fixed point of Hk less than r (such exists) is a representative of a cycle r\ which is a doubling of it/2 and such that each point of R(it) is surrounded by two points of P, in the sense that its nearest neighbors in R(it) UP both are in P. Furthermore, if R(it) {r\ < < rk/2}, then n is the unique doubling of it/2 such that n(2i) - r\(2i - 1) has the same sign as the slope of H at r, (/=!,..., k/2). Since et(y) = +1 or -1

706 C. BERNHARDT ET AL. according as L{+k/2(\) - L (1) and L{+k/2+](l) - L{+x(\) have the same sign or opposite signs (j = 0,..., k/2-1), it has this last property, and so P is a representative of it. If P {p\ < < pk), call the points p2m-\ and p2m (m 1,..., k/2) partners. If d (P) is attained at p e P, let p be the partner of p, and let di = \pi - i/n\. Since P fits H, d + di+x < \/n (i = 1,..., n - 2). Using the fact that H maps partners to partners, it is straightforward to show that di + dj+i < \/n (i = 1,...,«- 2) as well. Since the point of R(it) at which dj(r(it)) is attained lies between pi and p (i = 0,...,«), we have di(r(it)) + di+i(r(it))<l/n (i = 1,...,«- 2). o Remark. If it is a doubling which fits //, then although /?(7r) fits //, some other representative of it/2 may not fit //. For example, it = (136245), of type 3+, fits the horseshoe map H of type 4+, but it/2 = (123) has a representative which does not fit H. See the remark before Lemma 1. Proposition 12. R(it) is tighter than every representative of it in H. Proof. The result is trivial if it = ( 1 ), so we may assume that k > 2. By looking at the points (i, Ln(i)) (i 1,..., k) in the graph of Ln and the points (p, H(p)) (p P) in the graph of H, it is easy to see that for every representative P of it in H, and for P = R(it) as well if it is a doubling, di(p) is attained at HJ(p), where p = minp and j is the unique integer, 0 < j < k - 1, such that L (1) e /, n 7;+i (/ = 1,..., n - I). Therefore to show that di(r(n)) > di(p), it suffices to show that HJ+l(p) > W+1(r) (resp. Hj+i(p) < Hj+i(r)) if Ln has a relative maximum (resp. minimum) at LJn(l). The itinerary a ofp is also an L^-itinerary of 1. From the construction of x and the definition of ordering of itineraries it follows that at each step of the construction of x we make the choice that makes x maximal. Hence a < x and so p < r. By Proposition 7, if Ln has a relative maximum at L]n(\), then Hj+i(p) > HJ+l(r), and if L has a relative minimum at L{(\), then W+l(p) < HJ+l(r). Therefore d (P) < d (R(n)) (i = 1,...,«- 1), and R(it) is tighter than P by Lemma 3. Remark. It can be shown that if it is a doubling and I (it) > 3, then it has no tightest representative in the horseshoe map of the same type as it. The simplest example is it = (136245). Theorem 13 (cf. [J, Theorem 5.1]). Let it and 8 fit H. Then it forces 8 if and only if R(8) is tighter than R(it). Proof. By Proposition 11, R(n) fits //,andso HRW is well defined. Assume that it forces 8. Suppose first that it is not a doubling. Then R(n) is a representative of it in H, and therefore 8 has a representative Q in HR(n). Then Q is a representative of 8 in H and Q is tighter than R(it). But R(8) is tighter than Q by Proposition 12, so R(8) is tighter than R(it). Suppose now that it is a doubling. We may assume that 8 ^ it. By Lemma 6, it/2 forces 8. By Proposition 9, R(it) is a representative of it/2 in //, and the argument above shows that R(8) is tighter than R(it). Conversely, assume that R(8) is tighter than R(it). If 8 is not a doubling, then R(it) and R(8) are representatives of it (it 2 if it is a doubling) and 8

PERIODIC ORBITS OF MAPS OF THE INTERVAL 707 in HR(n), and it follows from Lemma 1 that it (it/2 if it is a doubling) forces 8. In the parenthetical case too, it forces 8, because it forces it/2. Suppose then that 8 is a doubling. By Proposition 10, Ç'(k'/2) = -1 (here the primes refer to 8), so as in the proof of Proposition 11, there is a representative of 8 in HR(n). As above, it forces 8. D If x is periodic, then the terms of the series in Theorem 5 can be grouped to give a geometric series. Thus R(it) consists of rational numbers which are computable in finitely many steps, as does the set of numbers {d (R(n))}. Therefore If H is the horseshoe map of the same type as it, then Theorem 5 and 13 together give an effective algorithm for deciding whether it forces 8 in each of the following cases: ( 1 ) it and 8 have the same type, (2) 1(8) = l(n) - 1, (3) it has type n± and 8 has type (n - 2)=f. Remark. If it is a doubling, we can sometimes decide whether it forces 8 even if 8 does not fit the horseshoe map of the same type as it. Formally, define itq it, and if it i is a doubling, define n +\ = it /2 : if not, it is not defined. Let m be the smallest integer such that itm is not a doubling. To decide whether it forces 8, first check whether 8 = it, for some i < m. If so, then it forces 8 by Lemma 6; if not, then again by Lemma 6, it forces 8 if and only if nm forces 8. The algorithm may apply to itm and 8. For example, (1 7 11 4 5 10 2 8 12 3 6 9), of type 8+, forces (13425) but not (1234), both of type 2+. References [Ba] S. Baldwin, Generalizations of a theorem of Sarkovskii on orbits of continuous real-valued functions, Discrete Math. 67 (1987), 111-127. [Bel] C. Bernhardt, Simple permutations with order a power of two, Ergodic Theory Dynamical Systems 4 (1984), 179-186. [Be2] _, The ordering on permutations induced by continuous maps of the real line, Ergodic Theory Dynamical Systems 7 (1987), 155-160. [BGMY] L. Block, J. Guckenheimer, M. Misiurewicz, and L.-S. Young, Periodic points and topological entropy of one-dimensional maps, Lecture Notes in Math., vol. 819, Springer, 1980, pp. 18-34. [J] I. Jungreis, Some results on the Sarkovskii partial ordering of permutations, Trans. Amer. Math. Soc. (to appear). [MT] J. Milnor and W. Thurston, On iterated maps of the interval, Lecture Notes in Math., vol. 1342, Springer, 1988, pp. 465-563. [MN] M. Misiurewicz and Z. Nitecki, Combinatorial patterns for maps of the interval, Universität Göttingen, preprint, 1989. (C. Bernhardt and I. Mulvey) Department of Mathematics and Computer Science, Fairfield University, Fairfield, Connecticut 06430 E-mail address: cbernhard@fairl.bitnet E-mail address: itmulvey@fairl.bitnet (E. Coven) Department of Mathematics, Weslevan University, Middletown, Connecticut 06457 E-mail address : coven@jordan.math.wesleyan.edu (M. Misiurewicz) Instytut Matematyki, Uniwersytet Warszawski, 00-901 Warsaw, Poland