Confounding Causality Principles: comment on Rédei and san Pedro s Distinguishing Causality Principles

Similar documents
Open problems and recent results on causal completeness of probabilistic theories

Measurement Independence, Parameter Independence and Non-locality

Causal completeness of probability theories results and open problems

Comparing causality principles

The nature of Reality: Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen Argument in QM

Causal completeness in general probability theories

A proof of Bell s inequality in quantum mechanics using causal interactions

Response to Wiseman, Rieffel, and Cavalcanti on Bell s 1964 Paper

Is spacetime hole-free?

Is Spacetime Hole-Free?

A Crucial Mistake in the Free Will Debate

Counterfactuals in Quantum Mechanics arxiv: v1 [quant-ph] 4 Sep 2007

A Note On Comparative Probability

A No-Go Result on Common Cause Approaches via Hardy s Paradox

Favoring, Likelihoodism, and Bayesianism

Hardy s Paradox. Chapter Introduction

Incompatibility Paradoxes

Counterfactuals in Quantum Mechanics

arxiv: v1 [quant-ph] 15 Mar 2016

Russell s logicism. Jeff Speaks. September 26, 2007

Desire-as-belief revisited

ON THE NOTION OF PRIMITIVE ONTOLOGY. Andrea Oldofredi Université de Lausanne MCMP (LMU) 29 Oct. 2014

Local primitive causality and the common cause principle in quantum field theory

A Theory for Comparing the Expressive Power of Access Control Models

Paradoxes of special relativity

Consequences of special relativity.

What happens to the value of the expression x + y every time we execute this loop? while x>0 do ( y := y+z ; x := x:= x z )

arxiv: v1 [quant-ph] 16 Aug 2007

This is logically equivalent to the conjunction of the positive assertion Minimal Arithmetic and Representability

University of Sheffield. School of Mathematics & and Statistics. Measure and Probability MAS350/451/6352

Tutorial on Mathematical Induction

For True Conditionalizers Weisberg s Paradox is a False Alarm

Measurement: still a problem in standard quantum theory

Quantum Field Theory: Motivating the Axiom of Microcausality

Sequence convergence, the weak T-axioms, and first countability

Axiomatic set theory. Chapter Why axiomatic set theory?

Discrete Structures Proofwriting Checklist

In Defense of Jeffrey Conditionalization

CSC 5170: Theory of Computational Complexity Lecture 9 The Chinese University of Hong Kong 15 March 2010

Gödel s Argument for Cantor s Cardinals Matthew W. Parker Centre for Philosophy of Natural and Social Science

The Adjoint Functor Theorem.

Delayed Choice Paradox

A Generalised Lottery Paradox for Infinite Probability Spaces 1. Martin Smith. University of Glasgow I. INTRODUCTION

Hidden Variables and Commutativity in Quantum Mechanics

Has CHSH-inequality any relation to EPR-argument?

Consequences of special relativity.

Basic System and Subsystem Structures in the Dataflow Algebra. A. J. Cowling

PREAMBLE (Revised) Why Einstein was Mistaken About the Velocity of Light.

Bell s Theorem. Ben Dribus. June 8, Louisiana State University

For True Conditionalizers Weisberg s Paradox is a False Alarm

On the Evolution of the Concept of Time

PHILOSOPHY OF PHYSICS (Spring 2002) 1 Substantivalism vs. relationism. Lecture 17: Substantivalism vs. relationism

Propositional Logic Review

PROOF-THEORETIC REDUCTION AS A PHILOSOPHER S TOOL

DECISIONS UNDER UNCERTAINTY

Ontology on Shaky Grounds

Philosophy of Mathematics Intuitionism

Bell s inequalities and their uses

Propositions and Proofs

EASTERN DIVISION OF THE AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL ASSOCIATION 2009 GROUP MEETING: THE PHILOSOPHY OF TIME SOCIETY

Arguments and Proofs. 1. A set of sentences (the premises) 2. A sentence (the conclusion)

The physical construct of quantum mechanics

Review Kuhlmann, Lyre, and Wayne: Ontological Aspects of Quantum Field Theory

Argumentation and rules with exceptions

MATH2206 Prob Stat/20.Jan Weekly Review 1-2

Chapter 2 Empirical Foundations

Metainduction in Operational Set Theory

Predicates, Quantifiers and Nested Quantifiers

Expressive Power, Mood, and Actuality

What are the recursion theoretic properties of a set of axioms? Understanding a paper by William Craig Armando B. Matos

What does it feel like to be in a quantum superposition?

Einselection of Pointer Observables: The New H-Theorem?

A New Semantic Characterization of. Second-Order Logical Validity

arxiv: v1 [math.st] 22 Feb 2013

Some Writing Examples

Throwing Darts, Time, and the Infinite

Statistics 612: L p spaces, metrics on spaces of probabilites, and connections to estimation

Max Planck, Nobel Prize in Physics and inventor of Quantum Mechanics said:

A booklet Mathematical Formulae and Statistical Tables might be needed for some questions.

Truthmaker Maximalism defended again. Eduardo Barrio and Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereyra

Checking Consistency. Chapter Introduction Support of a Consistent Family

UNIVERSITY OF NOTTINGHAM. Discussion Papers in Economics CONSISTENT FIRM CHOICE AND THE THEORY OF SUPPLY

The problem Countable additivity Finite additivity Conglomerability Structure Puzzle. The Measure Problem. Alexander R. Pruss

Dear Dr. Glaser, Printed for "Dr. Rainer Glaser"

The Born Rule. Chapter Classical Random Walk

ECE353: Probability and Random Processes. Lecture 2 - Set Theory

Standard forms for writing numbers

Lecture 22: Quantum computational complexity

What s Observable in Special and General Relativity?

Absolute motion versus relative motion in Special Relativity is not dealt with properly

THE COMMON CAUSE PRINCIPLE AND THE EPR-BELL SCENARIO

Formal Epistemology: Lecture Notes. Horacio Arló-Costa Carnegie Mellon University

Length Contraction on Rotating Disc: an Argument for the Lorentzian Approach to Relativity

The Common Cause Principle

Articles. A Paradox of Two Space Ships in Special Relativity

EXAMPLES OF MORDELL S EQUATION

1 More finite deterministic automata

arxiv: v1 [math.co] 13 Dec 2014

On Likelihoodism and Intelligent Design

Group Theory, Lattice Geometry, and Minkowski s Theorem

Transcription:

Confounding Causality Principles: comment on Rédei and san Pedro s Distinguishing Causality Principles arxiv:1210.1463v1 [quant-ph] 4 Oct 2012 Joe Henson February 10, 2019 Abstract Rédei and san Pedro discuss my Comparing Causality Principles, their main aim being to distinguish reasonable weakened versions of two causality principles presented there, SO1 and SO2. They also argue that the proof that SO1 implies SO2 contains a flaw. Here, a reply is made to a number of points raised in their paper. It is argued that the intuition that SO1 should be stronger than SO2 is implicitly based on a false premise. It is pointed out that a similar weakening of SO2 was already considered in the original paper. The technical definition of the new conditions is shown to be defective. The argument against the stronger versions of SO1 and SO2 given by Rédei and san Pedro is criticised. The flaw in the original proof is shown to be an easily corrected mistake in the wording. Finally, it is argued that some cited results on causal conditions in AQFT have little relevance to these issues, and are, in any case, highly problematic in themselves. In[3] I presented a framework within which some problems surrounding Bell s local causality condition and Reichenbach s Principle of Common Cause (PCC) could be addressed. The main aim was to clarify the relation between variants of the causal condition that is used in the derivation of the Bell inequalities. The central idea behind the more technical side of the work was the following: that various conditions in the literature claimed as alternatives to Bell s are either equivalent, or stronger in the sense that they incorporate inessential extra restrictions, or could be shown to be inadequate in a clear way. In this connection, the main results in the paper strengthen the justification of Bell s causal condition, and defend the significance of Bell s theorem against the possibility of replacing local causality with some weaker alternative. email: j.henson@imperial.ac.uk 1

Central to the discussion are two causality principles that can be defined in that framework, SO1 and SO2. Essentially, the two conditions are as follows ([3] contains more exact definitions, and the definitions of other terms used below). Consider two spacelike separated regions A and B in a spacetime S. A screening off type condition states that any pair of probabilistic events A and B occurring in any such regions A and B respectively will be uncorrelated once probabilities are conditioned on any full specification of events in the relativistic past. The past region can be defined in different ways. For SO1 the region is the mutual past P 1 = J (A) J (B), where J (A) is the causal past of A, while SO2 uses the larger joint past region P 2 = J (A) J (B)\(A B), where \ is set difference. In [3], proofs are provided that these conditions are equivalent. Rédei and san Pedro [4] take issue with the equivalence result using two main arguments. Firstly, they state that the equivalence seems counterintuitive in that SO2 should intuitively be weaker than SO1, and cite results on causal principles in AQFT that seem consistent with the intuition. The proposed solution is that SO2 should be replaced by a similar but weaker condition. Secondly they find fault with the proof that SO1 implies SO2. Simpson s paradox repeated. The common intuition that SO2 must be the weaker condition is based, it seems, on the idea that conditioning on more events in the past can only make more pairs of events uncorrelated, not less. If this was true then SO1 would easily imply SO2, but equivalence would be in doubt. This reasoning is incorrect, however. Uncorrelated events can become correlated once probabilities are conditioned on past events, leading to the so-called Simpson paradox [7]. Because of this, if arguments that SO2 implies SO1 seem endangered by causes of future correlations lying outside P 1, then arguments that SO2 implies SO1 should seem equally endangered by a Simpson s paradox brought on by events outside P 1. An argument along these lines is touched on in [3] before the equivalence proof is given. Finite SO2 and SO2w. The weakened conditions proposed by Rédei and san Pedro are called finite SO1 and finite SO2. The weakening consists in restricting the set of regions to which the condition applies, allowing correlations between events in certain spacelike regions that are not subject to the screening off condition. The regions to which finite SO1 and finite SO2 do not apply are causally infinite regions A such that the causal closure of A contains its own causal past (see [4] for details). This is claimed to rule out regions like J (B)\J (A) which would, if correct, prevent the equivalence proofs in [3] from applying to the new finite conditions. A similar variant of SO2, which is not mentioned in [4], was considered in section 2.4 of [3]. There SO2w is defined, in which the regions A and B are restricted to be regions that are of finite extent and do not contain any part of the initial hypersurface. Rédei and san Pedro s finite SO2 condition has the advantage that it isdefined purely with respect to thecausal relation onthe theset of spacetime points, which in my original paper was the only structure explicitly given to the spacetime 2

S, whereas mention of finite extent implicitly uses more structure. Finite SO1 is also new. Beyond that, the conditions are clearly very similar, at least in intent. Causal finiteness is defective. However, the definition of the term causally finite does not do the intended job, even in the intuitive case referred to in [4], that is, 2D Minkowski space. The problem is illustrated in figure 1. Let us use light-cone co-ordinates u = t + x and v = t x in this space. Consider a region defined by u 0, v 0 and u u where u is positive. This region corresponds to the region B Y in Figure 1 of [4], and for brevity it will be called O here. It extends infinitely into the past in an obvious sense. Rédei and san Pedro claim that such regions are also causally infinite in the sense of their definition. However, the causal complement O is the set of all points such that u < 0 and v > 0, and so the causal closure (O ) is the quadrant defined by u 0, v 0. This causal closure region (O ) does not contain its own past, and so O is causally finite by their definition. Thus, in 2D Minkowski space at least, the proof of the equivalence of SO1 and SO2 actually does carry over to the finite conditions! This undermines the motivation for the definition of Causal finiteness. Figure 1: A spacetime diagram showing the problem with the definition of causal finiteness. The region O corresponds to the region B Y in Figure 1 of [4], which the authors claim to be causally finite. The diagram shows the causal complement of this region O, and the causal closure (O ). It is easy to see that the causal closure (O ), which is the quadrant to the right in the diagram, does not contain its own past. It is certainly worthwhile to consider the consequences of modifying SO1 and SO2. But before analysing finite SO1 and SO2, we first need to improve on the definitions. When this task is completed, the more substantial questions can be dealt with. Motivation for finite SO1 and SO2 is problematic. However, even given that this technical problem can be resolved, the motivation given for preferring the alternative conditions is questionable. Briefly, Rédei and san Pedro state that a causally 3

infinite region might very well be empirically inaccessible in its entirety... hence one might not be in the position to decide empirically whether [an event in that region] has happened or not. Hence events in such regions should not be subject to screening-off conditions, they argue. This argument depends on a strong epistemic interpretation of the idea of domains of decidability from [3], that is, that they should be understood as the regions to which we would have to have access in order to know whether the event had occurred or not. Butterfield ([2], footnote 3, p.6) makes a compelling criticism of the use of epistemic language in [3]. It is, he states, a gloss that would be unnecessary, were it not an attempt to avoid the need to bring in the difficult notion of events being intrinsic to regions (an attempt which in any case fails). If we agree, and accept that domains of decidability should not be thought of epistemically, the argument given above cannot be carried through. There is a further problem with the argument: Rédei and san Pedro s finite SO1 and SO2 conditions still allow events whose least domain of decidability is causally infinite to be conditioned on, but they have argued against causally infinite least domains of decidability in general. SO1 does imply SO2. In section 5 of their paper Rédei and san Pedro challenge the proof that SO1 implies SO2. Rather than a being substantial error, however, this boils down to an erroneous restatement, in the explanation of the proof, of a result proved earlier in the paper. Correcting the restatement completes the proof. The first part of the proof in [3] shows that, if we assume SO1, any pair of events A and B in any spacelike regions A and B will be uncorrelated when probabilities are conditioned on any full specifications of three particular disjoint regions, the union of which is the joint past P 2. The last part of the proof offered is the following: [f]rom corollary 1, if C Φ(P 1 ), X Φ(X) and Y Φ(Y) then C X Y Φ(P 2 ) where Φ(A) refers to the set of full specifications of A. That is, if we condition on any full specification of the three regions, that is equivalent to conditioning on some full specification of their union, and this is claimed to complete the proof. Rédei and san Pedro rightly point out that this is not the same as saying that any full specification of P 2 is equal to the union of some such triple of full specifications C, X and Y for the corresponding disjoint regions, which is what we need to show that SO2 holds. However, when we return to corollary 1 to see what is actually says, we discover that it does indeed complete the proof. Corollary 1 is as follows: if R = i A i for some finite set of regions A i, then a full specification F of R can be written F = i A i where A i is a full specification of A i. Here signifies a disjoint union. The meaning is that any full specification F of R can be written in this way. This corollary is saying exactly what Rédei and san Pedro point out is missing from the proof. The error, such as it is, consists in explaining the content of corollary 1 incorrectly. So while the objection helps to clarify the proof, the problem is not substantial. Thus the equivalence between the original forms of SO1 and SO2 is not actually in danger. However, the conjecture that finite SO1 implies finite SO2 is also referred to as likely true and intuitively plausible in section 5 of [4], while the opposite implication is considered less likely to hold. An intuition refined in the face of Simpson s 4

paradox should find no obvious reason to consider one of the implications more likely to be true than the other (even ignoring the problems with the definition of casual finiteness). Results from AQFT have limited relevance. Rédei and san Pedro go on to review some results on causal conditions in algebraic quantum field theory (AQFT), claiming that they provide some evidence for relations between the screening off conditions, for example that finite SO2 is strictly weaker than the original SO2. It is misguided to compare results based on AQFT to results in the framework presented in [3] in this way, for a number of reasons. Not only the comparison, but also the general significance of the cited results, is questionable. Citing [5] in section 5 of their paper, Rédei and san Pedro state that if AQFT satisfies a certain condition, the finite SO2 holds in AQFT in a specific sense which they then specify. The causal principle referred to is a statement in the AQFT framework, analogous in form to Reichenbach s original statement of the Principle of Common Cause (definition 2 in [5]), with the relativistic joint past as the definition of the past region. It is surprising to see this referred to as a version of SO2, in any sense, in a paper based on a detailed reading of [3]. The first half of [3], leading up to the definitions of SO1 and SO2, deals explicitly and at length with this condition. The original PCC condition is contrasted in detail with screening off conditions. The conclusion is reiterated here to avoid any ambiguity: Reichenbach s original PCC suffers from numerous inadequacies when applied in this manner. Doing so leads to absurdities: this principle rules out many manifestly causal situations and is vulnerable to Simpson s paradox. What Rédei and Summers have shown is that something formally analogous to this inadequate condition holds in AQFT. This should only cause us to question whether the formal analogy, or anything like it, captures anything physically interesting. It does not tell us anything about SO2, finite or infinite. Beyond this particular work, there are broader reasons for caution in comparing results in the AQFT framework to that in[3]. The frameworks are far from equivalent. Furthermore, definitions of causal principles analogous to SO1 and SO2 are not settled in the AQFT framework, and different choices can lead to different results as to whether AQFT obeys various causal principles (see for example [2]). The underlying problem is that, in the SO1 and SO2 conditions, and other such conditions such as Stochastic Einstein locality [2] and Bell s own formulations, the events being conditioned on can be said to describe something like Bell s beables [1]. AQFT is, on the other hand, an axiomatisation of an operational theory. In an important sense, any decision on what a full specification of past events should be in AQFT implicitly presupposes something about what the beables should be. AQFT does not tell us what the beables should be. It does not even tell us whether they should correspond to structures already in the AQFT framework or whether extra structures should be added. For instance, in one case in which beables are added to a lattice QFT, the results are manifestly non-local [6]. Thus any conclusions we can reach here about locality, meaning lack of superluminal influence, are inextricably 5

tied to another problematic aspect of the story, namely what there is to influence or be influenced. This should not be taken as an argument that defining conditions that are formally analogous to SO1 and SO2 in other frameworks is always useless (some speculation along these lines was made in [3] using the idea of the decoherence functional rather than the AQFT framework). However, it is wrong to overinterpret such results as saying anything about the probabilistic framework of [3], or for that matter, anything decisive about locality in the above sense. To do the latter, it is at least necessary to make sure that the causal condition used is physically sensible. This means taking on the arguments surrounding Bell s theorem more directly. References [1] J.S. Bell. Speakable and unspeakable in quantum mechanics. CUP, Cambridge, 1987. [2] J. Butterfield. Stochastic Einstein Locality Revisited. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 58(4):805 867, 2007. [3] J. Henson. Comparing causality principles. Stud. Hist. Philos. Mod. Phys., 36:519 543, 2005. [4] M. Rédei and I. San Pedro. Distinguishing causality principles. Stud. Hist. Philos. Mod. Phys., 43(2):84 89, February 2012. [5] M. Rédei and S. J. Summers. Local primitive causality and the common cause principle in quantum field theory. Found.Phys., 32:335 355, 2002. [6] T.M. Samols. A Stochastic model of a quantum field theory. J. Statist. Phys., 1995. [7] J. Uffink. The principle of the common cause faces the Bernstein paradox. Philosophy of Science, 66(3):525, 1999. 6