Probabilistic Aspects of Voting

Similar documents
Survey of Voting Procedures and Paradoxes

Algorithmic Game Theory Introduction to Mechanism Design

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 24: Decisions in Groups

CMU Social choice 2: Manipulation. Teacher: Ariel Procaccia

Voting. José M Vidal. September 29, Abstract. The problems with voting.

Strategy-Proofness on the Condorcet Domain

GROUP DECISION MAKING

MATH 19-02: HW 5 TUFTS UNIVERSITY DEPARTMENT OF MATHEMATICS SPRING 2018

Dependence and Independence in Social Choice Theory

Probability Models of Information Exchange on Networks Lecture 1

3.1 Arrow s Theorem. We study now the general case in which the society has to choose among a number of alternatives

APPLIED MECHANISM DESIGN FOR SOCIAL GOOD

Recap Social Choice Fun Game Voting Paradoxes Properties. Social Choice. Lecture 11. Social Choice Lecture 11, Slide 1

arxiv: v2 [math.co] 14 Apr 2011

Coalitional Structure of the Muller-Satterthwaite Theorem

On the Strategy-proof Social Choice of Fixed-sized Subsets

13 Social choice B = 2 X X. is the collection of all binary relations on X. R = { X X : is complete and transitive}

Social Choice. Jan-Michael van Linthoudt

Dr. Y. İlker TOPCU. Dr. Özgür KABAK web.itu.edu.tr/kabak/

Efficient Algorithms for Hard Problems on Structured Electorates

Social choice theory, Arrow s impossibility theorem and majority judgment

Nontransitive Dice and Arrow s Theorem

Finite Dictatorships and Infinite Democracies

Choosing Collectively Optimal Sets of Alternatives Based on the Condorcet Criterion

CMU Social choice: Advanced manipulation. Teachers: Avrim Blum Ariel Procaccia (this time)

Arrow s Paradox. Prerna Nadathur. January 1, 2010

Follow links for Class Use and other Permissions. For more information send to:

"Arrow s Theorem and the Gibbard-Satterthwaite Theorem: A Unified Approach", by Phillip Reny. Economic Letters (70) (2001),

Resource Allocation via the Median Rule: Theory and Simulations in the Discrete Case

Political Economy of Institutions and Development. Lectures 2 and 3: Static Voting Models

SYSU Lectures on the Theory of Aggregation Lecture 2: Binary Aggregation with Integrity Constraints

APPLIED MECHANISM DESIGN FOR SOCIAL GOOD

Lecture 20 Random Samples 0/ 13

Social Dichotomy Functions (extended abstract)

14.770: Introduction to Political Economy Lectures 1 and 2: Collective Choice and Voting

Antonio Quesada Universidad de Murcia. Abstract

Volume 31, Issue 1. Manipulation of the Borda rule by introduction of a similar candidate. Jérôme Serais CREM UMR 6211 University of Caen

Social Choice and Social Networks. Aggregation of General Biased Signals (DRAFT)

Approval Voting for Committees: Threshold Approaches

Approximation algorithms and mechanism design for minimax approval voting

Wreath Products in Algebraic Voting Theory

THE PROFILE STRUCTURE FOR LUCE S CHOICE AXIOM

Coalitionally strategyproof functions depend only on the most-preferred alternatives.

Social Choice and Social Network. Aggregation of Biased Binary Signals. (Draft)

Antipodality in committee selection. Abstract

Approximation Algorithms and Mechanism Design for Minimax Approval Voting

Partial lecture notes THE PROBABILITY OF VIOLATING ARROW S CONDITIONS

Points-based rules respecting a pairwise-change-symmetric ordering

Social Choice and Mechanism Design - Part I.2. Part I.2: Social Choice Theory Summer Term 2011

CONNECTING PAIRWISE AND POSITIONAL ELECTION OUTCOMES

Economics Bulletin, 2012, Vol. 32 No. 1 pp Introduction. 2. The preliminaries

Participation Incentives in Randomized Social Choice

Quantifying the Classical Impossibility Theorems from Social Choice

Social Choice and Networks

Approximation Algorithms and Mechanism Design for Minimax Approval Voting 1

Chapter 1. The Mathematics of Voting

Logic and Social Choice Theory

Empowering the Voter: A Mathematical Analysis of Borda Count Elections with Non-Linear Preferences

Strategic Manipulability without Resoluteness or Shared Beliefs: Gibbard-Satterthwaite Generalized

The Best Way to Choose a Winner

Best reply dynamics for scoring rules

Introduction to Formal Epistemology Lecture 5

arxiv: v1 [cs.gt] 1 May 2017

Stackelberg Voting Games: Computational Aspects and Paradoxes

Lecture: Aggregation of General Biased Signals

Using a hierarchical properties ranking with AHP for the ranking of electoral systems

Condorcet Efficiency: A Preference for Indifference

Algebraic Voting Theory

The Axiomatic Method in Social Choice Theory:

Repeated Downsian Electoral Competition

The Condorcet Jur(ies) Theorem

Winning probabilities in a pairwise lottery system with three alternatives

Introduction to Game Theory Lecture Note 2: Strategic-Form Games and Nash Equilibrium (2)

arxiv: v2 [cs.gt] 6 Jan 2015

On the probabilistic modeling of consistency for iterated positional election procedures

Inequality of Representation

Single-peaked consistency and its complexity

2. AXIOMATIC PROBABILITY

AN ABSTRACT OF THE THESIS OF

Who wins the election? Polarizing outranking relations with large performance differences. Condorcet s Approach. Condorcet s method

THREE BRIEF PROOFS OF ARROW S IMPOSSIBILITY THEOREM JOHN GEANAKOPLOS COWLES FOUNDATION PAPER NO. 1116

Voting Handout. Election from the text, p. 47 (for use during class)

On Social Choice Theory

Consistent Approval-Based Multi-Winner Rules

Lose Big, Win Big, Sum Big: An Exploration of Ranked Voting Systems

Thema Working Paper n Université de Cergy Pontoise, France

Non-Manipulable Domains for the Borda Count

Chapter 12: Social Choice Theory

Chapter 2 Class Notes

Arrow s Impossibility Theorem and Experimental Tests of Preference Aggregation

Voting and Mechanism Design

Algebraic Voting Theory

A BORDA COUNT FOR PARTIALLY ORDERED BALLOTS JOHN CULLINAN, SAMUEL K. HSIAO, AND DAVID POLETT

Discrete Random Variables

A Characterization of Single-Peaked Preferences via Random Social Choice Functions

Discrete Mathematics and Probability Theory Spring 2016 Rao and Walrand Note 14

Basic Probabilistic Reasoning SEG

Strategic Manipulation and Regular Decomposition of Fuzzy Preference Relations

The Gibbard random dictatorship theorem: a generalization and a new proof

NOISE SENSITIVITY and CHAOS in SOCIAL CHOICE THEORY

Transcription:

Probabilistic Aspects of Voting UUGANBAATAR NINJBAT DEPARTMENT OF MATHEMATICS THE NATIONAL UNIVERSITY OF MONGOLIA SAAM 2015

Outline 1. Introduction to voting theory 2. Probability and voting 2.1. Aggregating noisy signals: The Condorcet Jury Theorem 2.2. Let s calculate probability: Bertrand s Ballot Theorem 2 2.3. Probability is a richer language: Gibbard s random dictator theorem 3. Final remarks

1.What is voting theory? 3 In the end democracy pins down to voting! Then, how should we organize voting properly? i.e. What is a good voting procedure? and Which voting system is the best? etc. As a byproduct of developments in the age of enlightenment a formal approach to this question is emerged with contributions of Marquis de Condorcet (1743 1794) Jean Charles de Borda (1733 1799) Joseph Bertrand (1822 1900) Charles Dodgson (1832 1898), etc. The formal approach is based on the following analysis: Which voting scheme has which property?

1.Voting Schemes 4 A general rule: When we have two alternatives the simple majority rule does the job! What if we have more than two alternatives? Firstly, the simple majority does not work! Condorcet paradox: Suppose there are 3 voters and 3 alternatives, A, B, C and the rankings are ABC, BCA, (CAB), respectively. Then majority prefers A to B, B to C and C to A. Yet Condorcet proposed the following method: Collect the ballots (i.e. the rankings and ties are allowed), and apply majority rule on all pairwise comparisons of alternatives. If there is a winner, it must be chosen. (If not, then use the Kemeny-Young extension!)

1.The Condorcet vs. Borda 5 Suppose after collecting ballots outcome is as follows: # of voters 2 2 3 2 Ballots (B C A) (B A C) (A B C) (C A B) The Condorcet winner is A. But one can argue that B is not inferior to A. Indeed that is what Borda rule says: In case of m N alternatives assign the score of m i to the i th ranked alternative in every ballot and rank alternatives according to their total scores. The Borda winner is B. Both methods are known to have some drawbacks!

2.1. The Condorcet s jury theorem 6 Motivation: When is a group decision better than individual decision? What is the optimal size of a committee? Problem: Consider a jury with three members each of which has the probability p of making the right decision, and 1 p of getting the wrong. Assume also that the probabilities are independent. If the committee outcome is based on the majority rule, what is the probability of jury getting the right decision? Answer: P 3 = p 3 + 3p 2 (1 p) and P 3 > p iff p > 1 2

2.1. The Condorcet s jury theorem 7 Theorem (Condorcet, 1785): Suppose there are n N (assume n is odd) jurors and their votes are i. i. d draws from the Bernoulli distribution with success probability p. Let P n be the probability that the majority of the jury members vote for success. Then, If 0.5 < p < 1 and n 3, then P n > p, P n increases with n and P n 1 as n ; If 0.5 > p > 0 and n 3, then P n < p, P n dicreases with n and P n 0 as n ; and If 0.5 = p, or p = 1, then P n = p for all n N. Proof: Notice that P n = n x n x= n+1 2 f(x) px (1 p) n x and recall the LLN. where f x =

2.1. The Condorcet s jury theorem 8 CJT is nice in the sense that it gives a formal basis for group action (i.e. democracy). From voting theory perspective, it is a theorem about majority rule. Indeed one can further show that majority rule is the best estimator in this context (Proof by the Neyman-Pearson lemma!). It allows for many extensions. For example, Owen et al., (1989) shows that when jurors have different levels of competence each greater than 0.5, or any case, its average is greater than 0.5, group deciding via majority rule is better than average member, and its competence increases with group size and approaches to 1. REF: Owen G., Grofman B. and S.L.Feld (1989) Proving distribution free generalization of the CJT, Math. Soc. Sciences, 17: 1 16

2.2. Bertand s Ballot Theorem 9 Theorem (Bertrand, 1887): Suppose there are n + m voters and two candidates A, B receiving n, m votes respectively with n > m (so A is the winner). If voters cast their ballots in a random order the probability that A has more votes than B at all times during the election is n m n+m. Proof: Let X i be the random variable that takes value 1 if i th voter votes for A and 1, if otherwise. Consider the sum S k = X 1 + + X k and clearly S n+m = n m. On a two dimensional grid consider points 0, S 0, 1 S 1,, n m, S n+m and we call the line connecting these points as a path.

2.2. Bertand s Ballot Theorem 10 Then our problem reduces to counting the number of paths that lie strictly above X-axis (except the origin), and that of all paths, and finding their ratio. Counting the latter is easy: n+m n. Count the former as follows: First count the number of paths that intersect with X-axis and then subtract it from n+m n.

2.2. Bertand s Ballot Theorem 11 Reflection principle: The number paths that intersect with X- axis is twice the number of paths starting at ( 1, 1) and ends (n m, n + m). Thus, p = n+m n 2 n+m 1 n n+m n = n m n+m.

2.2. Bertand s Ballot Theorem 12 This problem quite delicate and relevant for both combinatorics and probability theory. Thus, elections can lead to interesting problems! It also allows for various generalizations including continuous versions (see REF below). From the point of voting the reverse problem sounds also interesting: Given the past history, what is it chance of a candidate (a party) winning in the next? REF: Addario-Berry L. and B.A.Reed (2008) Ballot theorems, old and new. In Horizons of Combinatorics, Bolyai Soc. Math. Stud. Vol. 17: 9 35.

2.3. Gibbard s Random Dictatorship Theorem 13 Setting: N is the set of voters, and A is the set of alternatives with n and m > 2 elements, respectively. Voter i = 1,, n has a strict preferences ordering over A. Let L(A) is the set of all possible strict orderings on A and P(A) be the set all probability distributions over A. A decision scheme is a mapping f: L(A) n P(A). Payoff (or utility): Given f, at any profile l L(A) n voter i N receives m U i f l, l = j=1 u i (x j, l) p(x j, l) where u i.,. : A L(A) n R is a nonrandom utility representation. Axioms: Strategy Proof: Take any pair l, l L(A) n which are identical except voter i s ranking. If for some u i (.,. ) representing i s ranking we have U i f l, l > U i f l, l then f is manipulable for her at l L(A) n. f is STP if it is never manipulable. (Ex post) Pareto: For any x, y A and any l L(A) n if every voter prefers x to y at l, then p y, l = 0.

2.3. Gibbard s Random Dictatorship Theorem 14 Randomly dictatorial decision scheme: A dictatorial decision scheme is the one that picks one voter and always chooses her best alternative as an outcome. f: L(A) n P(A) is r.d. if it is a convex combination of some dictatorial decision schemes. Theorem (Gibbard, 1977): Let m > 2. Then f: L(A) n P(A) satisfies STP and Pareto iff it is randomly dictatorial. Proof: See Gibbard A. (1977) Manipulation of schemes that mix voting with chance, Econometrica 45: 665 681 Tanaka Y. ( 2003 ) An alternative proof of Gibbard s random dictatorship theorem, Rev. Econ. Design 8: 319 328.

2.3. Gibbard s Random Dictatorship Theorem 15 It is an extension of the so called Gibbard- Satterhwaite impossibility theorem (see the REF below). Thus, it is a theorem about the notion of STP. A continuous analog of this theorem is yet to be formulated! REF: Ninjbat U. ( 2012 ) Another direct proof for the Gibbard- Satterthwaite theorem, Econ. Letters 116(3): 418 421. Ninjbat U. ( 2015 ) Impossibility theorems are modified and unified, to appear in Soc. Choice Welf.

3. Final comments 16 Diversity and unity are equally important in doing research! Accordingly, we presented three results in voting theory with elements probability in it which suggest that voting and probability are mutually relevant: Probability is relevant for voting (see CJT) Voting is relevant for probability (see Ballot theorem) Its likely that the most of classical results admit a probabilistic version (see Gibbard s RDT) There is not much stochastic analysis (explicit) in here! But there certainly is a room for it! It makes sense to think ballots as realizations of some random variables Idea of conditioning also makes lots of sense in this context, etc.

General introduction: Some more references 17 Wallis W.D. (2014) The Mathematics of Elections and Voting, Springer. Nitzan S. (2010) Collective Preferences and Choice, CUP. Statistical approach: Balinksi M., R.Laraki ( 2011 ) Measuring, Ranking and Electing, MIT Press. Pivato M. (2013) Voting rules as statistical estimators, Soc. Choice Welf. 40(2): 581 630. Häggström O., Kalai G., Mossel E. (2006) A law of large numbers for weighted majority, Advances in applied mathematics 37(1): 112 123.