Available online at J. Math. Comput. Sci. 4 (2014), No. 3, ISSN: ORDERINGS AND PREORDERINGS ON MODULES

Similar documents
NOTES ON LINEAR ALGEBRA OVER INTEGRAL DOMAINS. Contents. 1. Introduction 1 2. Rank and basis 1 3. The set of linear maps 4. 1.

Quasi-primary submodules satisfying the primeful property II

A Note on Finitely Generated Multiplication Semimodules over Commutative Semirings

Lecture 2. (1) Every P L A (M) has a maximal element, (2) Every ascending chain of submodules stabilizes (ACC).

Course 311: Michaelmas Term 2005 Part III: Topics in Commutative Algebra

Pacific Journal of Mathematics

4.4 Noetherian Rings

PRIMARY DECOMPOSITION OF MODULES

INJECTIVE MODULES: PREPARATORY MATERIAL FOR THE SNOWBIRD SUMMER SCHOOL ON COMMUTATIVE ALGEBRA

Ideals Of The Ring Of Higher Dimensional Dual Numbers

Section II.1. Free Abelian Groups

ZARISKI-LIKE TOPOLOGY ON THE CLASSICAL PRIME SPECTRUM OF A MODULE

On Annihilator Small Intersection Graph

Some Properties of D-sets of a Group 1

Subrings of Finite Commutative Rings

ON sfp-injective AND sfp-flat MODULES

Characterization of Weakly Primary Ideals over Non-commutative Rings

r-ideals of Commutative Semigroups

THE ARTIN-SCHREIER THEOREM KEITH CONRAD

COMMUNICATIONS IN ALGEBRA, 15(3), (1987) A NOTE ON PRIME IDEALS WHICH TEST INJECTIVITY. John A. Beachy and William D.

Tensor Product of modules. MA499 Project II

Journal of Algebra 226, (2000) doi: /jabr , available online at on. Artin Level Modules.

OUTER MEASURES ON A COMMUTATIVE RING INDUCED BY MEASURES ON ITS SPECTRUM. Dariusz Dudzik, Marcin Skrzyński. 1. Preliminaries and introduction

Fréchet algebras of finite type

ON THE PRIME SPECTRUM OF MODULES

Math 210B. Artin Rees and completions

ON REGULARITY OF RINGS 1

DOUGLAS J. DAILEY AND THOMAS MARLEY

Integral Extensions. Chapter Integral Elements Definitions and Comments Lemma

INJECTIVE MODULES AND THE INJECTIVE HULL OF A MODULE, November 27, 2009

On Dual Versions of Krull s Intersection Theorem

A New Characterization of Boolean Rings with Identity

Prime Hyperideal in Multiplicative Ternary Hyperrings

A Generalization of VNL-Rings and P P -Rings

Characterisation of Duo-Rings in Which Every Weakly Cohopfian Module is Finitely Cogenerated

Primal, completely irreducible, and primary meet decompositions in modules

SUBCATEGORIES OF EXTENSION MODULES BY SERRE SUBCATEGORIES

RIGHT-LEFT SYMMETRY OF RIGHT NONSINGULAR RIGHT MAX-MIN CS PRIME RINGS

Weakly Semicommutative Rings and Strongly Regular Rings

Order-theoretical Characterizations of Countably Approximating Posets 1

FACTOR GRAPH OF NON-COMMUTATIVE RING

ON ALMOST PSEUDO-VALUATION DOMAINS, II. Gyu Whan Chang

Lecture 6. s S} is a ring.

ZERO-DIMENSIONALITY AND SERRE RINGS. D. Karim

Associated Primes under Noncommutative Localization (Preliminary Version)

11. Finitely-generated modules

RINGS ISOMORPHIC TO THEIR NONTRIVIAL SUBRINGS

Honors Algebra 4, MATH 371 Winter 2010 Assignment 4 Due Wednesday, February 17 at 08:35

P-Ideals and PMP-Ideals in Commutative Rings

Primitive Ideals of Semigroup Graded Rings

Small-Essential Submodules and Morita Duality

Torsion Graph of Modules

A CHARACTERIZATION OF GORENSTEIN DEDEKIND DOMAINS. Tao Xiong

Chapter 1. Sets and Numbers

be any ring homomorphism and let s S be any element of S. Then there is a unique ring homomorphism

NOTES ON SPLITTING FIELDS

Left R-prime (R, S)-submodules

TIGHT CLOSURE IN NON EQUIDIMENSIONAL RINGS ANURAG K. SINGH

Rings With Topologies Induced by Spaces of Functions

arxiv: v1 [math.ac] 25 Jul 2017

arxiv:math/ v1 [math.ac] 19 Sep 2002 Ian M. Aberbach

W P ZI rings and strong regularity

MP-Dimension of a Meta-Projective Duo-Ring

arxiv: v1 [math.ra] 6 Sep 2018

STRONGLY JÓNSSON AND STRONGLY HS MODULES

arxiv:math/ v1 [math.ra] 27 Sep 2004

MINIMAL POLYNOMIALS AND CHARACTERISTIC POLYNOMIALS OVER RINGS

GENERATING IDEALS IN SUBRINGS OF K[[X]] VIA NUMERICAL SEMIGROUPS

ON RIGHT S-NOETHERIAN RINGS AND S-NOETHERIAN MODULES

ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY COURSE NOTES, LECTURE 2: HILBERT S NULLSTELLENSATZ.

Quasi-Bigraduations of Modules, Slow Analytic Independence

(1) A frac = b : a, b A, b 0. We can define addition and multiplication of fractions as we normally would. a b + c d

Structure Theorem for Semisimple Rings: Wedderburn-Artin

where c R and the content of f is one. 1

Modules Over Principal Ideal Domains

Formal power series rings, inverse limits, and I-adic completions of rings

Quasigroups and Related Systems 21 (2013), Introduction

Splitting sets and weakly Matlis domains

Math Studies Algebra II

INTRODUCTION TO COMMUTATIVE ALGEBRA MAT6608. References

Communications in Algebra Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information:

NOETHERIAN SPACES OF INTEGRALLY CLOSED RINGS WITH AN APPLICATION TO INTERSECTIONS OF VALUATION RINGS

A Note on the Inverse Limits of Linear Algebraic Groups

A Theorem on Unique Factorization Domains Analogue for Modules

Homological Methods in Commutative Algebra

Direct Product of BF-Algebras

EXCELLENT RINGS WITH SINGLETON FORMAL FIBERS. 1. Introduction. Although this paper focuses on a commutative algebra result, we shall begin by

THE CLASSIFICATION OF INFINITE ABELIAN GROUPS WITH PARTIAL DECOMPOSITION BASES IN L ω

and this makes M into an R-module by (1.2). 2

How to sharpen a tridiagonal pair

Diameter and girth of Torsion Graph

Subring of a SCS-Ring

Honors Algebra 4, MATH 371 Winter 2010 Assignment 3 Due Friday, February 5 at 08:35

Paul E. Bland and Patrick F. Smith (Received April 2002)

The category of linear modular lattices

On J(R) of the Semilocal Rings

COMPRESSIBLE MODULES. Abhay K. Singh Department of Applied Mathematics, Indian School of Mines Dhanbad India. Abstract

Noetherian property of infinite EI categories

RESIDUAL SMALLNESS IN COMMUTATIVE ALGEBRA

38 Irreducibility criteria in rings of polynomials

Transcription:

Available online at http://scik.org J. Math. Comput. Sci. 4 (2014), No. 3, 574-586 ISSN: 1927-5307 ORDERINGS AND PREORDERINGS ON MODULES DONGMING HUANG Department of Applied Mathematics, Hainan University, Haikou 570228, China Copyright c 2014 Dongming Huang. This is an open access article distributed under the Creative Commons Attribution License, which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited. Abstract. The purpose of this paper is to investigate some relevant properties of semireal modules. By introducing the notion of preorderings on modules over commutative rings, we discuss the interplay between semireality, preorderings and orderings on modules. In particular, we obtain that an R module M is semireal if and only if M possesses a preordering. We also give some necessary and sufficient conditions for a preordering to be an ordering on modules. Keywords: semireal module; ordering; preordering. 2010 AMS Subject Classification: 13J30,16W80. 1. Introduction In Artin s solution to the Hilbert s 17th problem, the notion of orderings on fields played an important role. The notion of orderings on fields was first studied by Artin and Schreier [1,2]. Later, the notion of orderings was generalized to the category of commutative rings by Coste and Roy [4]; see also [5]. Recently, it was further generalized to the category of modules by Zeng[9]. It s well known that the notion of preorderings plays an important role in the study of real algebra in the categories of fields and commutative rings. Naturally, such a question Received May 14, 2014 574

ORDERINGS AND PREORDERINGS ON MODULES 575 arises: can we introduce preorderings on modules over commutative rings? This paper is aimed to answer this question. Throughout this paper, ring means commutative ring with identity 1, and all modules are unitary. For two subsets A and B of a set S, denote by A \ B the complement of B in A, i.e. A \ B = {x S x A but x / B}. Let M be an R module. For nonempty subsets S,T of R, set S + T = {s + t s S and t T }. In particular, if S = {s}, we write s + T instead of S + T. For nonempty subsets A,B of M, set (A : B) = {r R rb A for all b B} and A + B = {a + b a A and b B}. In particular, if B = {b}, we write (A : b) instead of (A : B) and A + b(or b + A) instead of A + B. For a nonempty subset S of R and a nonempty subset A of M, set SA = {sa s S,a A}. In particular, if S = {s}, we write sa instead of SA. A proper submodule P of M is called prime if ax P with a R and x M implies either a (P : M) or x P. For properties of modules and prime submodules, we refer the reader to [6,7] and the references therein. Conventionally, we use N, Z, and R for the set of all positive integers, the set of integers and the field of real numbers, respectively. 2. Orderings Let R be a ring. Then we may obtain the two multiplicative subsets of R as follows: T R := { n i=1 a 2 i n N, and a i R for i = 1,,n}; 1 + T R := {1 +t t T R }. Definition 2.1. [9] Let M be an R module. M is said to be semireal, if there exists an element e in M such that (1 + t)e 0 for every t T R. In this case, such an element e is said to be a semireal element. M is said to be real, if ( n i=1 a2 i )x = 0, where x M and a i R for i = 1,,n, implies a i x = 0 for i = 1,,n.

576 DONGMING HUANG Definition 2.2. [9] A subset Q of M is called an ordering of M if the following conditions are satisfied: (1)Q+Q Q; (2)Q Q = M; (3)Q Q is a prime submodule of M; and (4)(Q : Q) is an ordering of ring R. Lemma 2.3. Let M be an R module and Q an ordering of M. If x R, then x / (Q : Q) if and only if Q Q = {q Q xq Q}. Proof. The sufficiency Suppose that Q Q = {q Q xq Q}. If x (Q : Q), then Q {q Q xq Q} = Q Q. Thus, M = Q Q Q Q, and so M = Q Q. This contradicts the fact that Q Q is a proper submodule of M(since Q Q is a prime submodule of M). Hence, x / (Q : Q). The necessity Suppose that x / (Q : Q). Set Q 1 = {q Q xq Q}. Since (Q : Q) is an ordering of R,x (Q : Q). Thus, xq 1 xq Q. On the other hand, by the construction of Q 1,xQ 1 Q. Thus, xq 1 Q Q. Observe that x / ((Q Q) : M)(since x / (Q : Q)). By the primity of Q Q, we have Q 1 Q Q. Conversely, since x(q Q) x( Q) Q, we have Q Q Q 1. Therefore, Q Q = Q 1 = {q Q xq Q}. This completes the proof. Theorem 2.4. Let M be an R module and Q a subset of M. If Q satisfies: Q + Q Q, Q Q = M, and (Q : Q) is an ordering of R, then Q Q is a prime submodule of M if and only if for any x / (Q : Q), Q Q = {q Q xq Q}. Proof. The necessity follows immediately from Lemma 2.3. It s enough to prove the sufficiency. Suppose that Q Q = {q Q xq Q} for any x / (Q : Q). We shall first show that the subset Q Q is a submodule of M. Obviously, Q Q is a subgroup of M. Suppose that there is an x R such that x(q Q) Q Q. Then x(q Q) Q (if otherwise, x(q Q) = x((q Q) (Q Q)) = x(q Q) x(q Q) Q Q, a contradiction). Thus xq Q, and so x / (Q : Q). Since (Q : Q) is an ordering of R, x (Q : Q). Thus, x(q Q) x( Q) Q, a contradiction. It follows that x(q Q) (Q Q) for every x R. Therefore, Q Q is a submodule of M. Next, we shall show the submodule Q Q is a prime submodule. Since (Q : Q) is an ordering of R, 1 / (Q : Q). Thus, Q Q, and so Q Q Q Q = M. Hence, Q Q is a proper submodule of M.

ORDERINGS AND PREORDERINGS ON MODULES 577 Let xq Q Q, where x R and q M. Since M = Q Q, we have either q Q or q Q. Without loss of generality, we may assume q Q. Assume x / (Q Q : M) = (Q Q : Q Q). Then, there are two cases to consider: Case 1. x / (Q : Q). In this case, by supposition, Q Q = {q Q xq Q}. Thus, q {q Q xq Q} = Q Q, Since xq Q Q Q. Case 2. x (Q : Q). In this case, we have x / (Q : Q), since x / (Q Q : M) and (Q Q : M) = (Q Q : Q Q) = (Q : Q) (Q : Q). Thus, x / (Q : Q). Hence, by supposition, Q Q = {q Q xq Q}. Since xq (Q Q) Q, we have q {q Q xq Q} = Q Q. Therefore, Q Q is a prime submodule of M. This completes the proof. By Theorem 2.4, we may obtain an equivalent definition of orderings on modules over commutative rings as follows: Definition 2.5. Let M be an R module. A subset Q of M is called an ordering of M if the following conditions are satisfied: (1)Q + Q Q; (2)Q Q = M; (3)for any x / (Q : Q), Q Q = {q Q xq Q} ; and (4)(Q : Q) is an ordering of ring R. Proposition 2.6. Let A be a submodule of an R module M and Q an ordering of M. If A Q Q, then Q A is an ordering of A. Proof. Obviously, Q A satisfies the conditions (1) and (2) in Definition 2.5. For the check of the condition (4), it suffices to prove (Q : Q) = (Q A : Q A). Clearly, (Q : Q) (Q A : Q A). Conversely, suppose that there is x (Q A : Q A), but x / (Q : Q). Then x(q A) Q A Q. Thus Q A {q Q xq Q}. By Lemma 2.3, Q A Q Q. Notice that Q A = (Q Q) Q Q. Hence, A = M A = (Q Q) A = (Q A) ( Q A) Q Q, this contradicts the assumption A Q Q. Thereby, we have (Q : Q) = (Q A : Q A). Now, we check Q A satisfies condition (3). If x / (Q Q : Q Q) = (Q : Q). Then (Q A) (Q A) = (Q Q) A = {q Q xq Q} A = {q Q A xq Q A}. By definition 2.5, the proof is completed. 3. Preorderings

578 DONGMING HUANG The notion of preorderings play an important role in the study of real rings. In the category of commutative rings, preordering was defined as follows: Let R be a ring. A subset T of R is called a preordering if T + T T, T T T, R 2 T and 1 / T. In this section, we introduce the notion of preorderings in the category of modules and then establish some results about preorderings and orderings on modules. Definition 3.1. Let M be an R module. A subset Q of M is called a preordering of M if the following conditions are satisfied: (1) Q + Q Q; (2) (Q : Q) is a preordering of ring R. Remarks 1. (1) If Q is a preordering of an R module M, so is Q. (2) For a preordering Q of a ring R, Q is obviously a preordering of R as an R module. However, as an R module, a preordering Q of R need not be a preordering of the ring R. Even neither Q nor Q would be. For example, set Q := 2N {0}. We may check that Q is a preordering of Z as a Z-module. Note that 1 2 / Q Q. Therefore, neither Q nor Q will be a preordering of Z. It s easy to check the following Lemma: Lemma 3.2. Let M be an R-module and Q a subset of M. Then, Q is a preordering if and only if Q satisfies the following conditions: (1)Q + Q Q; (2) for all x R, x 2 (Q : Q); and (3) 1 / (Q : Q). Theorem 3.3. An R module M is semireal if and only if M possesses a preordering. Proof. The necessity Suppose M is semireal. Then, for any t T R, there is an e M such that (1 +t)e 0. Set Q = {te t T R }. We claim that Q is a preordering of M. By Lemma 3.2, it is enough to check conditions (1)-(3) in Lemma 3.2. (1)For q 1,q 2 Q, there exist t 1,t 2 T R such that q i = t i e,i = 1,2. Thus, q 1 +q 2 = t 1 e+t 2 e = (t 1 +t 2 )e Q. It follows that Q+Q Q. (2)For x R and q Q where q = te, t T R, we have x 2 q = x 2 (te) = (x 2 t)e Q. Hence, x 2 (Q : Q); (3)If 1 (Q : Q), then e = 1 e 1 Q Q. Thus, e = te for some t T R. Hence, (1 + t)e = 0, a contradiction. It is follows that 1 / (Q : Q). The sufficiency Let Q be a preordering of M. Suppose M is not a semireal module. Then, for any q Q, there exists a t = n i=1 a i 2 T R, where n N,a i R, i = 1,, n, such that (1+t)q = 0. Thus, q = tq = ( n i=1 a i 2 )q = n i=1 a i 2 q Q+ +Q Q, this implies Q Q,

ORDERINGS AND PREORDERINGS ON MODULES 579 and so 1 (Q : Q). This contradicts condition (3) in Lemma 3.2. Therefore, M is a semireal module. This completes the proof. Remark 2. Q = {te t T R } is called the induced preordering by the semireal element e. Clearly, it s the minimal preordering (minimal with respect to set inclusion) containing e. According to [9], there are modules which are semireal but not necessarily possess orderings. This also means, by Theorem 3.3, that there are modules which possess preorderings but not possess orderings. But when the considered module is finitely generated, we have Proposition 3.4. Let M be a finitely generated R module. Then the following conditions are equivalent: (1)M is semireal; (2)M possesses a preordering; (3)M possesses an ordering. Proof. This follows immediately from Theorem 3.3 and Proposition 3.5 in [9]. Proposition 3.5. Let ϕ : M M be an R module homomorphism, and let Q be a preordering of M with Q ϕ(m), and denote Q = ϕ 1 (Q ). Then Q is a preordering of M. Proof. For q 1, q 2 Q, we have q 1 +q 2 ϕ 1 (ϕ(q 1 +q 2 )) = ϕ 1 (ϕ(q 1 )+ϕ(q 2 )) ϕ 1 (Q ) = Q. Thus, Q + Q Q. For any x R and q Q. Since ϕ(x 2 q) = ϕ(x) 2 ϕ(q) Q, x 2 q ϕ 1 (Q ) = Q, i.e. x 2 (Q : Q). Since 1 / (Q : Q ), there is a q Q, but q / Q. Then, there is a q Q such that ϕ(q) = q. Observe that ϕ( q) = q / Q. Hence, q / ϕ 1 (Q ) = Q. Thus, 1 / (Q : Q). By Lemma 3.2, the proof is completed. φ 1 Proposition 3.6. Let M 1 M φ 2 M 2 be an exact sequence of R-module homomorphisms. If Q is a preordering of M, then either φ 1 1 (Q) is a preordering of M 1 or φ 2 (Q) is a preordering of M 2. Proof. Assume that φ1 1 (Q) is not a preordering of M 1. Notice that φ1 1 1 1 (Q)+φ1 (Q) φ1 (Q) and x 2 φ 1 1 1 1 1 (Q) φ (Q) for any x R. Thus, by Lemma 3.2, 1 (φ (Q) : φ (Q)). Now, 1 we may assert that φ 2 (Q) is a preordering of M 2. Clearly, we have φ 2 (Q) + φ 2 (Q) φ 2 (Q) and x 2 φ 2 (Q) φ 2 (Q) for any x R. Suppose 1 (φ 2 (Q) : φ 2 (Q)). Then, for any q Q, φ 2 (q) 1 1

580 DONGMING HUANG φ 2 (Q). Thus, there exists a q 1 Q, such that φ 2 (q) = φ 2 (q 1 ), and so φ 2 (q + q 1 ) = 0. Hence, q + q 1 Kerφ 2. By the exactness of the sequence, we have q + q 1 Imφ 1. Thereby, there exists m 1 M 1, such that φ 1 (m 1 ) = q + q 1. Thus, m 1 φ1 1 (q + q 1) φ1 1 1 (Q) φ1 (Q), since 1 (φ1 1 1 (Q) : φ1 (Q)) we got above. Thus, φ 1( m 1 ) Q, i.e. (q + q 1 ) Q. Hence, q q 1 Q Q. This implies 1 (Q : Q), a contradiction. It follows that φ 2 (Q) is a preordering of M 2. This completes the proof. Clearly, by definitions, an ordering is always being a preordering. However, the converse is not necessary true. Then such a question naturally arises: Under what conditions that might be true. In the sequel, we seek some sufficient and necessary conditions for a preordering to be an ordering. Lemma 3.7. [5] Let T be a preordering of ring R. Then, T is an ordering if and only if, for x,y R, xy T implies either x T or y T. Lemma 3.8. Let M be an R module and Q a subset of M. Then, (1) implies (2) (1) For x R and m M, xm Q implies either x (Q : Q) or m Q; (2) For x,y R, xy (Q : Q) implies either x (Q : Q) or y (Q : Q). Proof. Suppose that (1) holds. If xy (Q : Q) and x / (Q : Q), then x(yq) = (xy)q Q. By supposition, we have yq Q, and so y (Q : Q). This completes the proof. Theorem 3.9. Let M be an R module and Q a preordering of M. Then, Q is an ordering if and only if the following conditions are satisfied: (1) For x R and m M, xm Q implies either x (Q : Q) or m Q ; (2) For p,q M, p + q Q Q implies either p Q or q Q. Proof. The necessity (1)Suppose that xm Q where x R and m M, but x / (Q : Q) and m / Q. Then, m Q and x( m) Q. By Lemma 2.3, m Q Q. Thus, m Q, a contradiction. (2)Assume p + q Q Q. If p / Q, then p Q. Thus, q p + Q Q Q + Q Q. This implies p Q or q Q. The sufficiency Since assumption (1) holds, by Lemma 3.8 and by Lemma 3.7, (Q : Q) is an ordering of R. If Q Q M, let m M \ (Q Q). Since m + ( m) = 0 Q Q and assumption(2) holds, m Q or m Q, a contradiction. Thus, Q Q = M. For proving that Q

ORDERINGS AND PREORDERINGS ON MODULES 581 is an ordering of M, by Definition 2.5, it s now sufficient to show that Q Q = {q Q xq Q} for any x / (Q : Q). Assume x / (Q : Q). Then x (Q : Q), since (Q : Q) is an ordering of R. Thus, x(q Q) x( Q) Q. Hence, we have Q Q {q Q xq Q}. On the other hand, for q {q Q xq Q},x( q) Q. Thus, by assumption (1), either x (Q : Q) or q Q. Since x / (Q : Q), we have q Q. It follows that q Q Q. Therefore, we have Q Q = {q Q xq Q}. This completes the proof. Remarks 3. (1) According to the proof above, condition (2) can be replaced by (2) Q Q = M. (2) Theorem 3.9 can be considered as a generalization of Lemma 3.7. In Lemma 3.7, the condition R = T T (in the proof of sufficiency, cf.[5]) can be deduced from other conditions. However, in Theorem 3.9, condition (2) is indispensable. For example, let x be an indeterminant element on R. Then, R[x] can naturally be an R module. It s easy to check that R + is a preordering of R module R[x] and satisfies the condition (1), but R + is not an ordering of R[x]. This implies condition (2) is indispensable. Corollary 3.10. Let M be an R module and Q a preordering of M. Then, Q is an ordering if and only if, for any m / Q, ( Q : m) = (Q : Q). Proof. The necessity Let m / Q. If r ( Q : m), then rm Q. Thus, by Theorem 3.9, r (Q : Q). Hence, ( Q : m) (Q : Q). On the other hand, observe that m Q, we have (Q : Q)m (Q : Q)( Q) Q. Thus, (Q : Q) ( Q : m). It follows that ( Q : m) = (Q : Q). The sufficiency (1)Suppose that for any m / Q, ( Q : m) = (Q : Q). Let rm Q and m / Q. Then, r ( Q : m) and so r (Q : Q) by supposition. (2)For any m R, if m / Q, then ( Q : m) = (Q : Q). Observe that 1 (Q : Q). Thus m = 1 m (Q : Q)m Q. Hence M = Q Q. By Theorem 3.9 and Remarks 3(1), the proof is completed. φ 1 Proposition 3.11. Let M 1 M φ 2 M 2 0 be an exact sequence of R-module homomorphisms. If Q is an ordering of M, then either φ 1 1 (Q) is an ordering of M 1 or φ 2 (Q) is an ordering of M 2. Proof. Assume that φ 1 1 (Q) is not an ordering of M 1. Then, by Lemma 3 in [9], we have φ 1 (M 1 ) Q. Further, φ 1 (M 1 ) Q Q. i.e. Imφ 1 Q Q. In this case, since φ 1 1 (Q) = M 1,φ 1 1 (Q) is not a preordering of M 1. Hence, by Proposition 3.6, φ 2 (Q) is a preordering

582 DONGMING HUANG of M 2. Since φ 2 is surjective, we have φ 2 (Q) φ 2 (Q) = M 2. Let xm 2 φ 2 (Q), where x R,m 2 M 2. There exist an m M and a q Q, such that φ 2 (m) = m 2 and xφ 2 (m) = φ 2 (q), i.e. φ 2 (xm + q) = 0. Thus, xm + q Kerφ 2 = Imφ 1 Q Q, since the sequence is exact and Imφ 1 Q Q we got above. Hence, xm q + Q Q Q. Thereby, we have either x (Q : Q) or m Q by Theorem 3.9. Thus, either x (φ 2 (Q) : φ 2 (Q)) or m 2 = φ 2 (m) φ 2 (Q), since (Q : Q) (φ 2 (Q) : φ 2 (Q)). Applying Theorem 3.9 again, we obtain that φ 2 (Q) is an ordering of M 2. This completes the proof. Proposition 3.12. Let M be an R module, Q an ordering of M, and S a multiplicative subset of R. Set S 1 Q = { q s q Q and s S}. If S (Q : Q) \ (Q : Q), then S 1 Q is an ordering of S 1 R module S 1 M. Proof. It s easy to check that S 1 Q + S 1 Q S 1 Q and ( r s )2 (S 1 Q : S 1 Q) for r s S 1 R where r R, s S, since S (Q : Q). Suppose 1 1 (S 1 Q : S 1 Q). Pick out a q Q\ Q and an s S. Then, q s = 1 1 q s S 1 Q. Thus, there exist q Q, s S, such that q s = q s. Further, we have t(s q + sq ) = 0 for some t S. Hence, ts q = tsq Q Q. Note that q Q \ Q. Then ts (Q Q : M) (Q : Q), since Q Q is a prime module of M. On the other hand, ts S (Q : Q) \ (Q : Q), a contradiction. It follows that 1 1 / (S 1 Q : S 1 Q). Therefore, S 1 Q is a preordering of S 1 R module S 1 M. Since Q Q = M, we have S 1 Q S 1 Q = S 1 M. Assume x m S 1 Q for x = x s 1, m = m s 2 where x R,m M and s 1, s 2 S. Then,there exist a q Q and an s 3 S such that x s 1 m s2 = q s 3. Thus, we have t(s 3 xm + s 1 s 2 q) = 0 for some t S. In this case, we may assert that xm Q. Indeed, if not, then xm Q\ Q. Thus, (ts 3 )(xm) = ts 1 s 2 q Q Q. Thereby, we have xm Q Q, since Q Q is a prime submodule of M and ts 3 S (Q : Q) \ (Q : Q). Thus, xm Q, a contradiction. It follows that xm Q. By Theorem 3.9, we have either x (Q : Q) or m Q. Further, either x = x s 1 S 1 (Q : Q) or m S 1 Q. Observe that S 1 (Q : Q) (S 1 Q : S 1 Q). Thus, we have x (S 1 Q : S 1 Q) or m S 1 Q. Therefore, by Theorem 3.9, S 1 Q is an ordering of S 1 R module S 1 M. The proof is completed. We can find many multiplicative subsets Ses of R, such that S satisfies S (Q : Q)\ (Q : Q). For example, for an ordering Q of M, set S = 1 + supp((q : Q)), where supp((q : Q)) is the

ORDERINGS AND PREORDERINGS ON MODULES 583 support of ordering (Q : Q) of R. Then such an S satisfies the condition. More generally, we have Corollary 3.13. Let M be an R module, Q an ordering of M, and S a multiplicative subset of R. Set T = {1 + n i=1 p is 2 i n N, p i (Q : Q),s i S,i = 1,,n}. Then T 1 Q is an ordering of T 1 R module T 1 M. Proof. Obviously, T is a multiplicative subset of R. Since (T 1)Q = ( n i=1 p 2 is ) i Q Q, we have T 1+(Q : Q). Observe that 1+(Q : Q) (Q : Q)\ (Q : Q). Therefore, by Proposition 3.12, the proof is completed. 4. N (M) Definition 4.1. Let M be an R module. Define N (M) be the set of elements which aren t semireal in M, i.e. N (M) = {v M there is a t T R such that (1 +t)v = 0}. Lemma 4.2. Let M be an R module. Then (1)N (M) is a submodule of M; (2)If Q is a preordering of M, so is Q = Q + N (M); (3)If Q is a preordering of M, then (Q Q) N (M) Q Q. In particular, when Q is an ordering of M, N (M) Q Q. Proof. (1)For v 1,v 2 N (M), there exist t 1,t 2 T R such that (1 + t i )v i = 0,i = 1,2. Thus, (1 + t 1 + t 2 + t 1 t 2 )(v 1 v 2 ) = (1 + t 1 )(1 + t 2 )(v 1 v 2 ) = 0. Since t + t 1 + tt 1 T R, v 1 v 2 N (M). For any x R,v N (M), there is a t T R such that (1 +t)v = 0. Thus, (1 +t)(xv) = x(1 + t)v = 0. Hence, xv N (M). Therefore, N (M) is a submodule of M. (2)It s easy to check that Q + Q Q and x 2 (Q : Q ). Since Q is a preordering, there exists a q Q, but q / Q. We claim that q Q, but q / Q. Indeed, if not, then there exist a q Q and a v N (M) such that q = q + v. Further, there is a t T R, such that (1 + t)(q + q ) = (1 + t)( v) = 0. Thus, q = (1 + t)q + tq Q, a contradiction. Thereby, 1 / (Q : Q ). By Lemma 3.2, Q is a preordering of M.

584 DONGMING HUANG (3)Assume m (Q Q) N (M). Then, there exists a t T R, such that (1+t)m = 0. Thus, m = tm Q Q, whether m Q or m Q. Therefore, (Q Q) N (M) Q Q. This completes the proof. Proposition 4.3. Set Y N (M) = {Q Q is a preordering of M with N (M) Q}. If Y N (M) is not empty, then N (M) = Q Y N (M) Q. Proof. Obviously, N (M) Q Y N (M) Q. Suppose that there is an e Q Y N (M) Q \ N (M). By definition of N (M), e is a semireal element. By Remark 2, e induces a preordering Q = {te t T R }. Set Q = Q + N (M). Then, by Lemma 4.2(2), Q is a preordering of M. Thus, Q Y N (M), since N (M) Q. Note that N (M) Q and Q is a preordering of M by the Remarks 1(1). Thus Q Y N (M). Hence e Q Y N (M) Q Q. On the other hand, from the proof of Lemma 4.2(2), we have e / Q, a contradiction. It follows that Q Y N (M) Q N (M). Therefore, N (M) = Q Y N (M) Q. This completes the proof. Corollary 4.4. Set Y (M) = {Q Q is a preordering of M}. If Y (M) is not empty, then N (M) = Q Y (M)(Q + N (M)). Proof. Let Y N (M) be the same as above. It s easy to check that Y N (M) = {Q + N (M) Q Y (M)}. By Proposition 4.3, the proof is completed. Lemma 4.5. Let Q be a subset of R module M. Set Q = Q/N (M) = { q = q+n (M) q Q}. Then we have (1)If Q is a preordering of R module M, then Q is a preordering of R-module M/N (M). (2)If Q is an ordering of R module M, then Q is an ordering of R module M/N (M). Proof. (1)Consider the exact sequence N (M) i M φ M/N (M), where i is the identity homomorphism and φ is the canonical homomorphism. Since N (M) is not semireal, i 1 (Q) is not a preordering of N (M). By Proposition 3.6, Q = φ(q) is a preordering of M/N (M). (2)Consider the exact sequence N (M) i M φ M/N (M) 0, where i is the identity homomorphism and φ is the canonical homomorphism. Since N (M) is not semireal, i 1 (Q) is not an ordering of N (M). By Proposition 3.11, Q = φ(q) is an ordering of M/N (M). This completes the proof.

ORDERINGS AND PREORDERINGS ON MODULES 585 Note that every nonzero element of M/N (M) is semireal. For proving this, suppose that m is not semireal in M/N (M). Then there is a t T R such that (1 +t) m = 0, and so (1 +t)m N (M). Hence, for some t 1 T R,(1 + t 1 )(1 + t)m = 0, i.e. (1 + t + t 1 + tt 1 )m = 0. Thus, m N (M). It follows that m = 0. Theorem 4.6. Let M be an R module. Then M possesses an ordering if and only if M/N (M) possesses an ordering. Furthermore, there is an one-to-one correspondence between the set of all orderings on R module M and the set of all orderings of R module M/N (M). Proof. It suffices to prove the later conclusion. For this end, let X (M) (resp. X (M/N (M))) be the set of all orderings on M (resp. M/N (M))), and let ϕ : X (M) X (M/N (M)) be defined as follows: ϕ(q) = Q = { q = q + N (M) q Q}, Q X (M). By Lemma 4.5(2), Q is an ordering of R module M/N (M), and so ϕ is a map from X (M) to X (M/N (M)). Now, we shall first show that the mapping is injective. For this purpose, let ϕ(q 1 ) = ϕ(q 2 ), where Q 1,Q 2 X (M). Then Q 1 = Q 2. We claim that Q 1 = Q 2. If otherwise, without loss of generality, we may assume that Q 1 Q 2. Let q Q 1 \ Q 2. Then, q Q 1 = Q 2. Thus, there exists a q 2 Q 2, such that q q 2 N (M). By Lemma 4.2(3), N (M) Q 2 Q 2. Hence, q q 2 + N (M) Q 2 + Q 2 Q 2 Q 2, a contradiction. Now, it remains to show the map is surjective. For this, let Q be an ordering of M/N (M). Denote by φ the canonical module homomorphism from M to M/N (M). Observe that φ(m) = M/N (M) Q. Then, by Lemma 3 in [9], φ 1 (Q) is an ordering of M. On the other hand, notice that ϕ(φ 1 (Q)) = Q. It follows that the map ϕ is surjective. This completes the proof. Conflict of Interests The author declares that there is no conflict of interests. Acknowledgements This work was supported by the youth foundation of Hainan University (qnjj1246) and the National Natural Science Foundation of China (10971044).

586 DONGMING HUANG REFERENCES [1] E. Artin, O. Schreier, Algebraische Konstruktion reeller Korper, Abh. Math. Sem. Univ. Hamburg 5 (1927),85-99. [2] E. Artin, O. Schreier, Eine Kennzeichnung der reell algebraischlossen Korper, Abh. Math. Sem. Univ. Hamburg 5 (1927), 225-231. [3] M.F. Atiyah, I.G. Macdonald, Introduction to commutative algebra, Addison-Wesley (1969). [4] M. Coste, M. F.Coste-Roy, La topologie du spectre reel. In: Ordered fields and real algebraic geometry(d. Dubois and T. Reico,ed.), Contemporary Math., Amer. Math. Soc., Providence,R. I. 8 (1982), 27-59. [5] T.Y. Lam, An introduction to real algebra, Rocky Mountain J. Math. 14 (1984), 767-814. [6] C. P. Lu, Spectra of modules, Comm. Algebra 23 (1995), 3741-3752. [7] R. L. McCasland, M. E. Moore, Prime submodules, Comm. Algebra 20 (1992), 1803-1817. [8] A. Prestel, Lectures on formally real fields, Lect. Notes Math 1093, Springer-Verlag (1984). [9] G. Zeng, On formally real modules, Comm. Algebra 27 (1999), 5847-5856.