Does Frege have too many thoughts? A Cantorian problem revisited

Similar documents
T focus, dealing only with Frege s distinction between Sinn and Bedeutung,

Williamson s Modal Logic as Metaphysics

The paradox of knowability, the knower, and the believer

Chapter 4. Basic Set Theory. 4.1 The Language of Set Theory

Universalism Entails Extensionalism

Popper s Measure of Corroboration and P h b

The Foundations of Mathematics. Frege s Logicism

Seminar 7: The Logic of Principia Mathematica

Critical Notice: Bas van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective Oxford University Press, 2008, xiv pages

Kaplan s Paradox and Epistemically Possible Worlds

The claim that composition is identity is an intuition in search of a formulation.

PROOF-THEORETIC REDUCTION AS A PHILOSOPHER S TOOL

Introduction to Logic and Axiomatic Set Theory

Lecture 12: Arguments for the absolutist and relationist views of space

Truth, Subderivations and the Liar. Why Should I Care about the Liar Sentence? Uses of the Truth Concept - (i) Disquotation.

A Little History Incompleteness The First Theorem The Second Theorem Implications. Gödel s Theorem. Anders O.F. Hendrickson

Paradoxes of special relativity

Incompatibility Paradoxes

Hardy s Paradox. Chapter Introduction

Indicative conditionals

Draft of February 2019 please do not cite without permission. A new modal liar 1 T. Parent

Avoiding the Block Universe: A Reply to Petkov Peter Bokulich Boston University Draft: 3 Feb. 2006

Throwing Darts, Time, and the Infinite

Accuracy, Language Dependence and Joyce s Argument for Probabilism

First-Degree Entailment

Model-theoretic Vagueness vs. Epistemic Vagueness

A Note On Comparative Probability

A Little Deductive Logic

Zeno s Paradox #1. The Achilles

EXISTENTIAL IMPORT REVISITED KAREL LAMBERT

Physicalism decomposed

A Little Deductive Logic

For True Conditionalizers Weisberg s Paradox is a False Alarm

For True Conditionalizers Weisberg s Paradox is a False Alarm

DEEP METAPHYSICAL INDETERMINACY

Kripke on Frege on Sense and Reference. David Chalmers

Russell s logicism. Jeff Speaks. September 26, 2007

The λ-calculus and Curry s Paradox Drew McDermott , revised

Identity in Physics and Elsewhere

CM10196 Topic 2: Sets, Predicates, Boolean algebras

Metaphysics of Modality

Mathematical Descriptions

Why favour simplicity?

In Newcomb s problem, an agent is faced with a choice between acts that

Confirmation Theory. Pittsburgh Summer Program 1. Center for the Philosophy of Science, University of Pittsburgh July 7, 2017

We introduce one more operation on sets, perhaps the most important

240 Metaphysics. Frege s Puzzle. Chapter 26

Russell s Paradox, Our Solution, and the Other Solutions

Epistemic Modals and Informational Consequence

Comments on Markosian s How Fast Does Time Pass?

Relevant Logic. Daniel Bonevac. March 20, 2013

The Conjunction and Disjunction Theses

Favoring, Likelihoodism, and Bayesianism

Philosophy of Mathematics Structuralism

Intermediate Logic. Natural Deduction for TFL

1 Multiple Choice. PHIL110 Philosophy of Science. Exam May 10, Basic Concepts. 1.2 Inductivism. Name:

Elementary constructions on sets

A New Semantic Characterization of. Second-Order Logical Validity

Math 144 Summer 2012 (UCR) Pro-Notes June 24, / 15

Precis of Aristotle s Modal Syllogistic

Comparative Bayesian Confirmation and the Quine Duhem Problem: A Rejoinder to Strevens Branden Fitelson and Andrew Waterman

Deduction by Daniel Bonevac. Chapter 3 Truth Trees

The Really Real: The Consistency of Primary Substance Primacy in Aristotle s Categories

KRIPKE S THEORY OF TRUTH 1. INTRODUCTION

A Re-Evaluation of Schrodinger s Cat Paradox

Deep Metaphysical Indeterminacy

Philosophy of Mathematics Intuitionism

Dr. Truthlove, or How I Learned to Stop Worrying and Love Bayesian Probabilities

GÖDEL S COMPLETENESS AND INCOMPLETENESS THEOREMS. Contents 1. Introduction Gödel s Completeness Theorem

Theory of Computation CS3102 Spring 2014

Gunk Mountains: A Puzzle

Generality, Extensibility, and Paradox

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 3: Analysis, Analytically Basic Concepts, Direct Acquaintance, and Theoretical Terms. Part 2: Theoretical Terms

In Defense of Jeffrey Conditionalization

The Paradox of Knowability from a Russellian Perspective

Lecture 11: Gödel s Second Incompleteness Theorem, and Tarski s Theorem

Contingent Existence and Iterated Modality

Gödel s Argument for Cantor s Cardinals Matthew W. Parker Centre for Philosophy of Natural and Social Science

Published in Analysis, 2004, 64 (1), pp

Abstract: In this paper, I present a schema for generating counterexamples to the

I. Induction, Probability and Confirmation: Introduction

Gödel vs. Mechanism: An examination of Three Attempts to Show that Gödel s Theorems are Incompatible with Mechanism and Why They Fail

In Defence of a Naïve Conditional Epistemology

(1.3.1) and in English one says a is an element of M. The statement that a is not an element of M is written as a M

The Nuisance Principle in Infinite Settings

Hedging Your Ifs and Vice Versa

Logic and Mathematics:

The nature of Reality: Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen Argument in QM

On the scope of diagonal argument and on contradictory equivalence.

An Intuitively Complete Analysis of Gödel s Incompleteness

Lecture 6: Greedy Algorithms I

Ibn Sina s explanation of reductio ad absurdum. Wilfrid Hodges Herons Brook, Sticklepath, Okehampton November 2011

A new resolution of the Judy Benjamin problem

Abstract. Some authors (Muller and Saunders 2008, Huggett and Norton, 2013) have attempted to defend

Alternative Technologies

Wittgenstein on The Standard Metre

What Does Quantum Mechanics Suggest About Our Perceptions of Reality?

Introduction. Introductory Remarks

Symposium: L.E.J. Brouwer, Fifty Years Later. Free Choice Sequences: A Temporal Interpretation Compatible with Acceptance of Classical Mathematics

Weak and Global Supervenience Are Strong

Transcription:

does frege have too many thoughts? 45 standard probabilistic practice of saying that E provides evidence for H just in case P(H E) > P(H).) Whether one s resulting credence in the theory of quantum mechanics would be so low that one would reject quantum mechanics would depend on details like one s prior probability for Theory X. Even with a probability shift in favour of Theory X, one s credences could still be such that quantum mechanics is judged vastly more probable than Theory X. Just as the observation of the decay can provide evidence for Theory X and against quantum mechanics, the observation that we are in a small civilization can provide evidence for or against various physical theories. For example, consider Theory Y, which predicts that all civilizations are small. The fact that our civilization is small could constitute evidence in favour of Theory Y and against inflationary theory. But depending on such factors as one s prior probability for Theory Y, one s credences could still be such that inflationary theory is judged vastly more probable than Theory Y. Thus, that our civilization is small could lead one to decrease one s credence in inflationary theory, but nevertheless that credence could still be high. The issue we are discussing in the previous paragraph is a general issue about theory comparison in science; if that is the core of Olum s paper then there is nothing surprising here. It would be surprising if there were a conflict between anthropic reasoning and observation, but Olum s argument fails to show that this is the case. University of Kentucky Lexington, KY 40506-0027, USA dienho@uky.edu bmonton@uky.edu Reference Olum, K. 2004. Anthropic reasoning conflicts with observation. Analysis 64: 1 8. Does Frege have too many thoughts? A Cantorian problem revisited Kevin C. Klement In two recent papers in this journal, Adam Rieger (2002) and Nicholas Denyer (2003) discuss a problem with Frege s ontology. According to Analysis 65.1, January 2005, pp. 45 49. Kevin C. Klement Blackwell Publishing Ltd.Oxford, UK and Malden, USAANALAnalysis0003-26382005 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.January 20056514549ArticlesKevin C. Klement Does Frege have too many thoughts?

46 kevin c. klement Rieger, Frege regards thoughts as objects. But this is impossible, because one can generate a distinct thought for every concept, in violation of Cantor s theorem whereby there must be more concepts than objects. Denyer points out that Rieger s argument involves a questionable hidden assumption. I will suggest that Denyer won that battle, but that the war to save Frege was lost a long time ago. Rieger s argument is as follows. For each concept, consider the thought that Ben Lomond falls under that concept. He assumes (problematically, as we shall see) that the thought so generated is distinct for each concept. Call these the Ben Lomond thoughts. Now consider the concept of being an ordinary Ben Lomond thought. Something is an ordinary Ben Lomond thought iff it is a Ben Lomond thought but does not fall under the concept it attributes to Ben Lomond. From this concept we can generate a Ben Lomond thought, viz. the thought that Ben Lomond is an ordinary Ben Lomond thought. The problem is of course whether or not this resulting Ben Lomond thought is ordinary. It s ordinary iff it does not fall under the concept it attributes to Ben. But it attributes ordinariness to Ben, so it s ordinary iff it is not. Denyer retorts that the problem doesn t have to be traced back to treating thoughts as objects, and can instead be traced back to the naive assumption that each Ben Lomond thought is associated with exactly one concept. Denyer gives a more complicated example, but consider the thought that Ben Lomond loves Ben Lomond. This thought can be decomposed as attributing any of three concepts to Ben Lomond: the concept something falls under iff it loves Ben Lomond, the concept something falls under iff Ben Lomond loves it, or the concept something falls under iff it loves itself. Without the assumption that the Ben Lomond thought generated for each concept is distinct, the antinomy does not go through. It is also fairly easy to see that there is no violation of Cantor s theorem, because without this assumption the proof that there are at least as many objects as concepts evaporates. Moreover, as he admits in a footnote, Rieger also speaks loosely by suggesting that for each concept, there is such a thing as the thought that Ben Lomond falls under that concept. As Frege (1979: 118 25) makes clear, the sense/reference distinction applies also to concept expressions. Fregean concepts are functions and have extensional identity conditions. The expressions... is non-self-identical and... is a unicorn refer to the same concept, despite having different senses. So the thoughts expressed by Ben Lomond is non-self-identical, and Ben Lomond is a unicorn, attribute the same concept to Ben, but are surely distinct. This point, however, is not as crucial. If Frege is committed to more than one thought for each concept, that would, if anything, make the Cantorian problems worse, not better.

does frege have too many thoughts? 47 While Rieger s specific attempt at a Cantorian construction does not work, there are surely better ones. Instead of considering Ben Lomond thoughts, we can consider thoughts that universally generalize upon concepts. For each pair consisting of a concept C, and a sense that presents it C*, we can generate a distinct thought by considering the thought that everything is C, with C* being the operant sense presenting C. Call the thoughts so generated universal thoughts. Now define a concept O that something falls under if and only if it is a universal thought that does not fall under the concept it generalizes upon. We must assume that there is at least one sense O *, presenting O. This may seem questionable, but consider that the sense of the expression... is a universal thought that does not fall under the concept it generalizes upon would appear to be one such sense. Hence, there is a universal thought everything is O (as presented through O *). Does it fall under O? Apparently, it does just in case it does not. Does this construction suffer the same defect as Rieger s? I fail to see how. Frege understands quantifiers as second-level concepts. The sense expressed by everything is..., a sense whose referent is a second-level concept, has the sort of incompleteness that is filled by a sense presenting a first-level concept. The thought expressed would seem to differ for each such sense placed in that spot. Everything is such that it loves Lomond is a distinct thought from everything is such that Lomond loves it, and so forth. Here, the worries about multiple possible decompositions do not seem to arise. Frege is in trouble. The charge that Frege s ontology falls prey to this sort of Cantorian problem is not new. A few months after reporting Russell s paradox, Russell despaired in a letter to Frege that from Cantor s proposition that any class contains more subclasses than objects we can elicit constantly new contradictions (see Frege 1980: 147), and reports on his discovery of a Cantorian paradox regarding propositions, suggesting that, mutatis mutandis, this should be a worry for Frege s theory of thoughts. In the ensuing correspondence, Russell formulates the paradox in terms of both generating a distinct proposition for every class, as well as generating a distinct proposition for every propositional function. Frege never quite fully appreciated Russell s point, but nevertheless Russell had put his finger on a genuine issue Frege should have been concerned with, as I have argued elsewhere (Klement 2001, 2002: chs. 5 6). Years later, the same sort of Cantorian problem regarding thoughts or propositions plagued Alonzo Church s initial attempts to devise a Logic of Sense and Denotation. Church (1951) had (plausibly enough) included as an axiom in one of this formulations the principle that distinct universal thoughts are generated by each sense presenting a function onto truthvalues. Accordingly, John Myhill (1958) used, essentially, the Cantorian

48 kevin c. klement construction I describe above to show that Church s system was inconsistent. Hence, C. A. Anderson (1980) has dubbed this paradox the Russell- Myhill antinomy. In some of my recent work, I have attempted to highlight all the possible ways someone with broadly Fregean commitments could escape from such paradoxes (Klement 2002, 2003). With regard to the particular Cantorian construction sketched above, the most initially promising responses would be (1) denying there is any such concept as O, (2) denying that there is any sense O * presenting the concept O (since, if there is no such sense, there can be no thoughts about O ), (3) denying that the concept O is the only concept that the thought that everything is O generalizes over, and (4) denying that the thought that everything is O is of the appropriate logical type for the question as to whether it falls under O to be meaningful. We can form complex function expressions that, at least apparently, are satisfied by all and only things that are O. Hence, solution (1) would entail giving up the standard comprehension principle used in higher-order function logic; this could be done, but I doubt the historical Frege would have gone along happily. Solution (2) is similarly difficult to swallow, since the complex function expressions satisfied by all and only things that are O would seem to have O as referent, and therefore must express senses that present O. Denyer s solution to Rieger s version would point us towards attempting solution (3), but I have already cast suspicion on such an attempt. That only leaves solution (4). Perhaps it is the solution Rieger would advocate, since he suggests that the problem is that thoughts are objects. If O is a concept that takes objects as argument, but the thought that everything is O is not an object, then the question doesn t arise as to whether it falls under O. But the issue is really more complicated than that. Presumably if thoughts are of a different logical type, then we must merely distinguish concepts that apply (or not) to objects from concepts that apply (or not) to thoughts. Which one is O? Recall that O is the function mapping all universal thoughts not falling under the concept they generalize upon to the True, and everything else (in the appropriate logical category) to the False. So O can be considered in the latter category, and so denying that thoughts are objects provides no help (modulo an interpretation of everything is... to limit itself to the appropriate logical category). Indeed, Church s type-theory made such distinctions as between type o 0 (truth-values), type o 1 (senses whose referents are truth-values, i.e., thoughts), type o 2 (senses whose referents are thoughts), and so on, as well as between types i 0 (individuals), i 1 (senses whose referents are individuals), i 2 (senses whose referents are senses of type i 1 ), etc. These type distinctions provided him with no help in replying to Myhill. Solution (4) will only work either if thoughts are not placed in any logical category

knowledge in borderline cases 49 at all (e.g. if we simply eschew them altogether), or if thoughts are split into different ramified orders so that no thought can involve quantification over a range of thoughts in which it is included. Russell accepted the harsh and highly artificial (Russell 1903: 528) solution given by ramification only after years of searching for others; there s no indication Frege would have been happy with it at all. University of Massachusetts Amherst, MA 01003-9269, USA klement@philos.umass.edu References Anderson, C. A. 1980. Some new axioms for the Logic of Sense and Denotation: alternative (0). Noûs 14: 217 34. Church, A. 1951. A formulation of the Logic of Sense and Denotation. In Structure, Method and Meaning: Essays in Honor of Henry M. Sheffer, ed. P. Henle, H. Kallen and S. Langer, 3 24. New York: Liberal Arts Press. Denyer, N. 2003. Rieger s problem with Frege s ontology. Analysis 63: 166 70. Frege, G. 1979. Posthumous Writings, ed. H. Hermes et al. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Frege, G. 1980. Philosophical and Mathematical Correspondence, ed. G. Gabriel et al. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Klement, K. 2001. Russell s paradox in Appendix B of the Principles of Mathematics: Was Frege s reply adequate? History and Philosophy of Logic 22: 13 28. Klement, K. 2002. Frege and the Logic of Sense and Reference. New York: Routledge. Klement, K. 2003. The number of senses. Erkenntnis 58: 303 23. Myhill, J. 1958. Problems arising in the formalization of intensional logic. Logique et Analyse 1: 78 82. Rieger, A. 2002. Paradox without Basic Law V: A problem with Frege s ontology. Analysis 62: 327 30. Russell, B. 1903. The Principles of Mathematics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Blackwell Publishing Ltd.Oxford, UK and Malden, USAANALAnalysis0003-26382005 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.January 20056514955ArticlesSven Rosenkranz Knowledge in borderline cases Knowledge in borderline cases Sven Rosenkranz 1. Vagueness gives rise to borderline cases. If F is vague, then there will typically be cases to which F clearly applies, cases to which it clearly doesn t apply and intermediate cases which we don t know how to classify. Analysis 65.1, January 2005, pp. 49 55. Sven Rosenkranz