PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES

Similar documents
CAUSATION. Chapter 14. Causation and the Direction of Time Preliminary Considerations in Support of a Causal Analysis of Temporal Concepts

Published in Analysis, 2004, 64 (1), pp

CAUSATION CAUSATION. Chapter 10. Non-Humean Reductionism

The paradox of knowability, the knower, and the believer

The Conjunction and Disjunction Theses

EASTERN DIVISION OF THE AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL ASSOCIATION 2009 GROUP MEETING: THE PHILOSOPHY OF TIME SOCIETY

Russell s logicism. Jeff Speaks. September 26, 2007

Critical Notice: Bas van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective Oxford University Press, 2008, xiv pages

Gödel vs. Mechanism: An examination of Three Attempts to Show that Gödel s Theorems are Incompatible with Mechanism and Why They Fail

INTENSIONS MARCUS KRACHT

Appendix 2. Leibniz's Predecessors on the Continuum. (a) Aristotle

Realism and Idealism External Realism

Marc Lange -- IRIS. European Journal of Philosophy and Public Debate

Introducing Proof 1. hsn.uk.net. Contents

The Existence of Absolute Space

Introduction to Metalogic

Time Without Change. by Sydney Shoemaker

8. Reductio ad absurdum

Indicative conditionals

T initiatic forms in which, by their very

Tutorial on Mathematical Induction

Part II A Reexamination of Contemporary Utilitarianism

Diachronic Coherence and Radical Probabilism

A New Semantic Characterization of. Second-Order Logical Validity

Philosophy of Mathematics Structuralism

Williamson s Modal Logic as Metaphysics

Accuracy, Language Dependence and Joyce s Argument for Probabilism

The nature of Reality: Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen Argument in QM

Is Consciousness a Nonspatial Phenomenon?

Lewis 2 Definitions of T-terms

Relations. Carl Pollard. October 11, Department of Linguistics Ohio State University

A Height-Potentialist View of Set Theory

Tooley on backward causation

Scientific Explanation- Causation and Unification

CL16, 12th September 2016

35 Chapter CHAPTER 4: Mathematical Proof

Truth, Subderivations and the Liar. Why Should I Care about the Liar Sentence? Uses of the Truth Concept - (i) Disquotation.

Kaplan s Paradox and Epistemically Possible Worlds

*a * * *b * * *c *d *

1 Multiple Choice. PHIL110 Philosophy of Science. Exam May 10, Basic Concepts. 1.2 Inductivism. Name:

Universalism Entails Extensionalism

Draft of February 2019 please do not cite without permission. A new modal liar 1 T. Parent

The claim that composition is identity is an intuition in search of a formulation.

240 Metaphysics. Frege s Puzzle. Chapter 26

Searle on Emergence. Vladimír Havlík. The Academy of Sciences of the Czech Republic, Prague

The Converse of Deducibility: C.I. Lewis and the Origin of Modern AAL/ALC Modal 2011 Logic 1 / 26

Part II On the Equivalence of Scientific Theories

8. Reductio ad absurdum

The Varieties of (Relative) Modality

Significance Testing with Incompletely Randomised Cases Cannot Possibly Work

Chapter 2. Mathematical Reasoning. 2.1 Mathematical Models

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 3: Analysis, Analytically Basic Concepts, Direct Acquaintance, and Theoretical Terms. Part 2: Theoretical Terms

Uni- and Bivariate Power

Vocabulary atom atomos Dalton's atomic theory law of constant composition law of definite proportions law of multiple proportions matter.

So, what are special sciences? ones that are particularly dear to the author? ( Oh dear. I am touched. Psychology is just, so, well, special!

The Inductive Proof Template

Counterfactuals and comparative similarity

Simply Possible. Theodore Sider Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 60 (2000):

How Einstein came to employ the action-reaction principle in justifying general relativity

I. Induction, Probability and Confirmation: Introduction

3. Nomic vs causal vs dispositional essentialism. 1. If quidditism is true, then properties could have swapped their nomic roles.

Zeno s Paradox #1. The Achilles

Math 4606, Summer 2004: Inductive sets, N, the Peano Axioms, Recursive Sequences Page 1 of 10

Causal Explanation and Ontological Commitment. Mark Colyvan University of Tasmania

2.3 Measuring Degrees of Belief

FACTORIZATION AND THE PRIMES

Material Implication and Entailment

Chapter 2 Empirical Foundations

DR.RUPNATHJI( DR.RUPAK NATH )

Is Lucas s Gödelian argument valid?

Ontology on Shaky Grounds

Kripke on Frege on Sense and Reference. David Chalmers

GÖDEL S COMPLETENESS AND INCOMPLETENESS THEOREMS. Contents 1. Introduction Gödel s Completeness Theorem

Proving Completeness for Nested Sequent Calculi 1

Elementary Linear Algebra, Second Edition, by Spence, Insel, and Friedberg. ISBN Pearson Education, Inc., Upper Saddle River, NJ.

Logic. Quantifiers. (real numbers understood). x [x is rotten in Denmark]. x<x+x 2 +1

Commentary on Guarini

Confirmation Theory. Pittsburgh Summer Program 1. Center for the Philosophy of Science, University of Pittsburgh July 7, 2017

An A statement: The year 1967 is 49 years in the past. A B statement: The year 1967 is 49 years before the year 2016

Formal Logic. Critical Thinking

Euler s Galilean Philosophy of Science

1. Propositions: Contrapositives and Converses

Mind Association. Oxford University Press and Mind Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Mind.

SIMILARITY IS A BAD GUIDE TO COUNTERFACTUAL TRUTH. The Lewis-Stalnaker logic systems [2] account for a wide range of intuitions about

Alternative Technologies

Introduction to Philosophy Philosophy 110W Spring 2011 Russell Marcus

Anselm s God in Isabelle/HOL

Popper s Measure of Corroboration and P h b

Introduction to Basic Proof Techniques Mathew A. Johnson

Tutorial on Axiomatic Set Theory. Javier R. Movellan

A General Overview of Parametric Estimation and Inference Techniques.

Proof: If (a, a, b) is a Pythagorean triple, 2a 2 = b 2 b / a = 2, which is impossible.

Math 414, Fall 2016, Test I

The Ontology of Counter Factual Causality and Conditional

Hardy s Paradox. Chapter Introduction

Direct Proof and Counterexample I:Introduction

Conceivability and Modal Knowledge

PHIL12A Section answers, 14 February 2011

Logicality of Operators

Review of Gordon Belot, Geometric Possibility Oxford: Oxford UP, 2011

Transcription:

i PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES Edited by WILFRID SELLARS and HERBERT FEIGL with the advice and assistance of PAUL MEEHL, JOHN HOSPERS, MAY BRODBECK VOLUME XVII Contents October 1966 NUMBER 5 Do ReIations Individuate? by ]. W. Meiland, UNIVERSITY OF MICHIGAN Scriven on Human Unpredictability by David K. Lewis and lane Shelby Richardson, HARVARD UNIVERSITY Assertion and Belief by Charles Sayward, UNIVERSITY OF NEBRASKA Do Relations Individuate? by J. w. MEILAND UNIVERSITY OF MICHIGAN "VVuaT is it that renders two exactly similar material objects numerically different from one another? One possible answer to this question is that the two objects have different relational properties or stand in different relations. They stand in different spatial relations to some other material objects and, perhaps, to one another. For example, one object X may be to the left of the other, Y (this relation hereafter being called "Relation L"), while Y is to the right of X. E. B. Allaire rejects this answer on the grounds that X and Y first must be numerically different before they can stand in Relation L: "Relations-I'll stick with spatial ones--presuppose numerical difference; they do not account for it. The thisness and the thatness of things is presupposed in saying that the one is to the left of the other. 'u Allaire's own answer to the question stated above is that each of the two numerically different material objects contains a different "bare particular" (a particular of this sort being called "bare" because it itself has no properties) : "Bare particulars are, 65

66 PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES therefore, the entities in things accounting for the numerical difference of things. ''2 1 wish to show that the theory of bare particulars is highly implausible and that relations do individuate material objects. I What is Allaire's argument for the claim that "relations presuppose numerical difference?" He says that if this were not so, "then in at least some cases we would be forced to say what we all know to. be false; namely, that the same thing is to the left of itself. ''3 But perhaps saying that the same thing is to the left of itself is false just because Relation L does individuate-- that is, just because if X and Y stand in Relation L to one another, then it is logically impossible for X and Y to be numerically identical. Perhaps that X and Y stand in Relation L is a logically sufficient condition of the numerical difference of X and Y. If so, then standing in that relation would by itself guarantee that the terms of the relation are numerically different; and thus bare particulars would not be required to account for this difference. Allaire denies that standing in Relation L is a logically sufficient condition of numerical difference. He admits that Relation L "cannot be exemplified by one thing." But he says: "That L is asymmetrical is factual, not logical. TM Since asymmetry implies irreflexivity, Allaire is claiming that it is a factual matter, not a logical truth, that Relation L is irreflexive. He does not give any argument for this claim. But this claim is crucial to the plausibility of this theory of bare particulars, as I now wish to show. If it is merely a factual matter that Relation L cannot be exemplified by one thing, then it is logically possible that it be exemplified by one thing. Let us suppose that we are observing a case of what we would describe as "one material object X being to the left of another, Y." Since on the theory of bare particulars, objects contain bare particulars, Allaire would say that if this is in fact a case involving two different objects, then there is one bare particular in the location occupied by X and a different bare particular in the location occupied by Y. But, if Allaire is correct about Relation L, it is logically possible that this case is not a case involving two different objects, X and Y, even though in every observable respect this case is just like a case involving two different objects. That is, it is logically possible that the numericaliy same bare particular occupies two different locations (those which, as we say, are occupied by X and Y). So in claiming that the irreflexivity of Relation L is factual, not logical, Allaire is claiming that the numerically same bare particular can occupy two different locations. But there is no way to determine, in a case of the sort described above, whether the two locations are occupied by different bare particulars or by the same bare particular, for what is observed is the same in either case. Hence, if Allaire is correct, there

DO RELATIONS INDIVIDUATE? 67 is no way to determine whether such a case is a case of numerical difference or of numerical identity. That X and Y occupy different locations does not settle the matter, if Allaire is correct, since those different locations may be occupied by the same bare particular. But then what basis could anyone have for asserting that in a case of the sort described above, X and Y are numerically different or that they are numerically the same? One could not even have an inductive basis for such assertions. For to have an inductive basis for this, one would have to have found that in some previous cases of objects that occupy different locations, those objects were numerically different (or identical). But in order to acquire such inductive evidence, we would first have to possess a way of determining whether a given case is a case of numerical identity or of numerical difference. Since there could be no basis for saying, with certainty or with probability, that two exactly similar material objects are numerically identical or numerically different, one could never know, in a given case, how many bare particulars are present. So the theory of bare particulars provides an account of the numerical differences of things at the price of making it impossible for us to determine whether or not a given case is a case of numerical difference. Thus, if the theory of bare particulars is correct, it can never be employed in a particular case. The only reason that Allaire gives for supposing that there are bare particulars is that they are required to "account for the numerical difference of things." But if the theory of bare particulars is correct, then no cases could be known to exist for which it was needed to account. For although bare particulars are supposed to explain numerical difference rather than provide a criterion for detecting numerical difference, the existence of bare particulars would seem to eliminate the possibility of having any criterion for detecting numerical difference in cases of two bodies that have exactly the same properties (other than spatial properties). It is true that one could still say: "If this particular case is a case of numerical difference, then it is a case involving two different bare particulars." But is to say that two different bare particulars are present in such a case to say anything more than that it is a case of numerical difference? And if it is not to say anything more than this, then in what sense does saying that different bare particulars are present account for numerical difference? Gould Allaire say that the irreflexivity of Relation L is logical rather than factual? To do so would meet the objections above. But to do so would also allow relations to individuate. For then standing in Relation L would by itsejf, regardless of the existence or nonexistence of bare particulars, guarantee numerical difference. Objects would be numerically different solely in virtue of standing in Relation L. And then there would be no need to postulate the

68 PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES existence of bare particulars. Numerical difference could be accounted for by citing the relations in which the objects in question stand. II There are two sorts of situations which involve numerical identity or difference. The first concerns objects existing at a given moment; the second concerns objects existing at different moments. As a situation of the first sort, let us suppose that two exactly similar objects X and Y coexist but occupy different locations. If it is only factually the case, rather than logically necessary, that X and Y are numerically different, then it is logically possible that exactly similar objects which occupy different locations are numerically identical. But then what would it mean to say of such objects that they are numerically identical? If we do not employ a theory of substance as substratum or a theory of bare particulars, there seems to be nothing that could be meant by saying that they are numerically identical; if it is only factually the case that X and Y are numerically identical, then a situation that is exactly the same as the described situation in every observable respect could be a situation involving numerical differenceof objects. So unless we say that ascriptions of numerical identity and difference in situations of this first sort are about something unobservable (a substratum or bare particulars), we must say either (i) that ascription of numerical identity or difference in situations of this first sort has no meaning, or else (ii) that what it means to say that two exactly similar objects are numerically different is that they occupy different locations. That is, in order to provide a meaning for such ascriptions without referring to something unobservable, we must deny that it is a merely factual matter that objects occupying different locations are numerically different. We must say that "occupying different locations" is what the expression 'numerically different' means in such a situation. Only in this way will it not be a merely factual matter that objects occupying different locations are numerically different. And hence only in this way will the expression 'numerically different' have a meaning in the first type of situation without invoking something unobservable. In every situation of the first sort--that is, situations involving coexisting material bodies--two such bodies are numerically different if and only if (or when and only when) they occupy different locations. The meaning of the expression 'numerically different' is "occupying different locations." But the following objection might be raised to this position: This position on the meaning of 'numerically different' is satisfactory only if we consider only the first sort of ease. Let us now consider situations in which the two entities in question do not coexist. We often say that what I am now observing (call this "X") is numerically different from what I

SCRIVEN ON HUMAN UNPREDICTABILITY 69 previously observed (call this "Y"). Yet what I now observe can be both exactly similar to and in the same location as what I previously observed, even though the two things are numerically different. Therefore the expression 'X is numerically different from Y' cannot mean "X and Y occupy different locations," unless the expression 'numerically different' is equivocal, that is, unless it has one meaning in the first sort of situation and a different meaning in the second sort of situation. What this objection shows is that we must add to the expression which renders the meaning of 'numerically different': "Two objects are numerically different (a) if they coexist, then when and only when they occupy different locations, or (b) in case they in fact never coexist, if and only if they would have occupied different locations had they coexisted." But to make the addition represented by part (b) is only to add further specification concerning the locations of bodies. It is not to mention something unobservable which is said to be contained within material objects. It seems, then, that a substratum or bare particulars need not be postulated if the expression 'numerical difference' has the meaning suggested above. But if it has the suggested meaning, then relations do individuate. For then X and Y are numerically different when and only when they have or would have had different locations, that is, when and only when they have or would have had different spatial relations to other bodies, Received April 19, 1965 NOTES 1E. B. Allaire, "Another Look at Bare Particulars," Philosophical Studies, 16:19 (1965). Ibid., p. 18. Ibid., p. 19. "Ibid. Scriven on Human Unpredictability by DAVID K. LEWIS and JANE SHELBY RICHARDSON HARVARD UNIVERSITY IN ms paper "An Essential Unpredictability in Human Behavior, ''1 Michael Scriven offers an argument intended to show that it is impossible in principle to predict what a person (or indeed a suitable robot) will do in a certain