Playing with forcing

Similar documents
FORCING PROPERTIES OF IDEALS OF CLOSED SETS

arxiv: v1 [math.lo] 16 Jan 2010

Complexity of Ramsey null sets

WHY Y-C.C. DAVID CHODOUNSKÝ AND JINDŘICH ZAPLETAL

CANONICALIZATION BY ABSOLUTENESS

Adam Kwela. Instytut Matematyczny PAN SELECTIVE PROPERTIES OF IDEALS ON COUNTABLE SETS. Praca semestralna nr 3 (semestr letni 2011/12)

Inner models and ultrafilters in

Distributivity of Quotients of Countable Products of Boolean Algebras

SMALL SUBSETS OF THE REALS AND TREE FORCING NOTIONS

Wojciech Stadnicki. On Laver extension. Uniwersytet Wrocławski. Praca semestralna nr 2 (semestr letni 2010/11) Opiekun pracy: Janusz Pawlikowski

CCC Forcing and Splitting Reals

Maharam Algebras. Equipe de Logique, Université de Paris 7, 2 Place Jussieu, Paris, France

The topology of ultrafilters as subspaces of 2 ω

Increasing δ 1 2 and Namba-style forcing

IDEAL GAMES AND RAMSEY SETS

Classical Theory of Cardinal Characteristics

Uncountable γ-sets under axiom CPA game

MAYA SARAN DISSERTATION

G δ ideals of compact sets

Decomposing Borel functions and structure at finite levels of the Baire hierarchy.

RIGIDITY OF CORONA ALGEBRAS SAEED GHASEMI

Borel cardinals and Ramsey ultrafilters (draft of Sections 1-3)

ISOLATING CARDINAL INVARIANTS

An introduction to OCA

On Borel maps, calibrated σ-ideals and homogeneity

Canonical models for fragments of the Axiom of Choice

The length-ω 1 open game quantifier propagates scales

Non-trivial automorphisms from variants of small d

Classes of Polish spaces under effective Borel isomorphism

Hypergraphs and proper forcing

BPFA and BAAFA. Their equiconsistency and their nonequivalence. Thilo Weinert. February 4, 2009

GAMES ON BOOLEAN ALGEBRAS

JUMP OPERATIONS FOR BOREL GRAPHS

A product of γ-sets which is not Menger.

HECHLER'S THEOREM FOR TALL ANALYTIC P-IDEALS

CAMBRIDGE TRACTS IN MATHEMATICS. 174 Forcing Idealized

Luzin and Sierpiński sets meet trees

The Metamathematics of Randomness

Combinatorial Variants of Lebesgue s Density Theorem

Homogeneous spaces and Wadge theory

ANOTHER PROOF OF HUREWICZ THEOREM. 1. Hurewicz schemes

4 Choice axioms and Baire category theorem

1.A Topological spaces The initial topology is called topology generated by (f i ) i I.

WHY SATURATED PROBABILITY SPACES ARE NECESSARY

Stat 451: Solutions to Assignment #1

FORCING WITH SEQUENCES OF MODELS OF TWO TYPES

A local Ramsey theory for block sequences

PROBABILITY MEASURES AND EFFECTIVE RANDOMNESS

Uniformity, Universality, and Computability Theory

Logic and Games SS 2009

Tutorial: Generic Elementary Embeddings. Lecture 2: Consistency results

1 MONOTONE COMPLETE C*-ALGEBRAS AND GENERIC DYNAMICS

Measure and Category. Marianna Csörnyei. ucahmcs

4 Countability axioms

Chain Conditions of Horn and Tarski

On the open-open game

Projective measure without projective Baire

Compact subsets of the Baire space

Continuous and Borel Dynamics of Countable Borel Equivalence Relations

Von Neumann s Problem

Distributivity of the algebra of regular open subsets of βr \ R

Jónsson Properties for Non-Ordinal Sets Under the Axiom of Determinacy

Math 209B Homework 2

Ramsey theory with and withoutpigeonhole principle

An inner model from Ω-logic. Daisuke Ikegami

THE CANTOR GAME: WINNING STRATEGIES AND DETERMINACY. by arxiv: v1 [math.ca] 29 Jan 2017 MAGNUS D. LADUE

Large Sets in Boolean and Non-Boolean Groups and Topology

A variant of Namba Forcing

October 12, Complexity and Absoluteness in L ω1,ω. John T. Baldwin. Measuring complexity. Complexity of. concepts. to first order.

Measures and Measure Spaces

Unsolvable problems, the Continuum Hypothesis, and the nature of infinity

INFINITE ASYMPTOTIC GAMES

Banach-Mazur game played in partially ordered sets

THE SMOOTH IDEAL JOHN D. CLEMENS, CLINTON T. CONLEY, AND BENJAMIN D. MILLER

Ramsey determinacy of adversarial Gowers games

7 About Egorov s and Lusin s theorems

TOPOLOGICAL RAMSEY SPACES DENSE IN FORCINGS

MASSACHUSETTS INSTITUTE OF TECHNOLOGY 6.436J/15.085J Fall 2008 Lecture 3 9/10/2008 CONDITIONING AND INDEPENDENCE

Combinatorial dichotomies and cardinal invariants

Reasonable ultrafilters

ADVANCED CALCULUS - MTH433 LECTURE 4 - FINITE AND INFINITE SETS

arxiv:math.gn/ v1 6 Dec 2003

ON THE LACZKOVICH-KOMJÁTH PROPERTY OF SIGMA-IDEALS. 1. Introduction

Eventually Different Functions and Inaccessible Cardinals

The axiom of choice and two-point sets in the plane

G δ -sets in topological spaces and games

EMBEDDING DISTRIBUTIVE LATTICES IN THE Σ 0 2 ENUMERATION DEGREES

INSTITUTE OF MATHEMATICS THE CZECH ACADEMY OF SCIENCES. Tsirelson-like spaces and complexity of classes of Banach spaces.

COUNTABLE COMPACTNESS, HEREDITARY π CHARACTER, AND THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS

Ordering functions. Raphaël Carroy. Hejnice, Czech Republic January 27th, Universität Münster 1/21

CONSISTENCY RESULTS IN THE THEORY OF CONTINUOUS FUNCTIONS AND SELECTIVE SEPARABILITY

CLASSES OF STRICTLY SINGULAR OPERATORS AND THEIR PRODUCTS

Ramsey theorems for product of finite sets with submeasures

CHODOUNSKY, DAVID, M.A. Relative Topological Properties. (2006) Directed by Dr. Jerry Vaughan. 48pp.

Infinite Combinatorics, Definability, and Forcing

COPYABLE STRUCTURES ANTONIO MONTALBÁN

ON A QUESTION OF SIERPIŃSKI

Silver trees and Cohen reals

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved.

Transcription:

Winterschool, 2 February 2009

Idealized forcings Many forcing notions arise as quotient Boolean algebras of the form P I = Bor(X )/I, where X is a Polish space and I is an ideal of Borel sets.

Idealized forcings Many forcing notions arise as quotient Boolean algebras of the form P I = Bor(X )/I, where X is a Polish space and I is an ideal of Borel sets. s Classical examples are: Cohen forcing with the ideal of meager sets, random forcing with null sets, Miller with K σ and Sacks with countable sets.

The generic real A forcing notion of the form Bor(ω ω )/I adds the generic real, denoted ġ and defined in the following way: ġ(n) = m = [(n, m)] I where [(n, m)] is the basic clopen in ω ω ).

The generic real A forcing notion of the form Bor(ω ω )/I adds the generic real, denoted ġ and defined in the following way: ġ(n) = m = [(n, m)] I where [(n, m)] is the basic clopen in ω ω ). Genericity Of course, the generic ultrafilter can be recovered from the generic real.

Properness As observed by Jindřich Zapletal, properness of a forcing of the form P I can be stated in the following way:

Properness As observed by Jindřich Zapletal, properness of a forcing of the form P I can be stated in the following way: of idealized forcing If I is an ideal then the forcing notion P I is proper if and only if for any M H κ and any condition B M P I {x B : x is generic over M} / I.

Properness As observed by Jindřich Zapletal, properness of a forcing of the form P I can be stated in the following way: of idealized forcing If I is an ideal then the forcing notion P I is proper if and only if for any M H κ and any condition B M P I {x B : x is generic over M} / I. Note that the set of generic reals over a countable model is always a Borel set.

Borel reading of names If a forcing notion of the form P I is proper then we have a nice reprezentation of names.

Borel reading of names If a forcing notion of the form P I is proper then we have a nice reprezentation of names. Theorem (Zapletal) If the forcing P I is proper and ẋ is a name for a real then for each B P I there is C B and a Borel function f : C ω ω such that C ẋ = f (ġ).

s Are there any natural examples of proper forcings P I?

s Are there any natural examples of proper forcings P I? Definition An ideal I is said to be generated by closed sets if each set A I can be covered by an F σ set in I.

s Are there any natural examples of proper forcings P I? Definition An ideal I is said to be generated by closed sets if each set A I can be covered by an F σ set in I. Theorem (Zapletal) If I is generated by closed sets then P I is proper.

Ideals generated by closed sets are quite common in descriptive set theory. Recall the following theorem.

Ideals generated by closed sets are quite common in descriptive set theory. Recall the following theorem. Theorem (Solecki) If I is generated by closed sets then any analytic set A either can be covered by an F σ set from I or contains a G δ I -positive set.

Ideals generated by closed sets are quite common in descriptive set theory. Recall the following theorem. Theorem (Solecki) If I is generated by closed sets then any analytic set A either can be covered by an F σ set from I or contains a G δ I -positive set. Using this theorem Zapletal improved Borel reading of names for ideals generated by closed sets.

Ideals generated by closed sets are quite common in descriptive set theory. Recall the following theorem. Theorem (Solecki) If I is generated by closed sets then any analytic set A either can be covered by an F σ set from I or contains a G δ I -positive set. Using this theorem Zapletal improved Borel reading of names for ideals generated by closed sets. Theorem (Zapletal) If I is generated by closed sets then P I has continuous reading of names.

Games Ideals of Borel sets are often described in terms of infinite games.

Games Ideals of Borel sets are often described in terms of infinite games. Banach-Mazur games Suppose for each Borel set A ω ω G(A) is a two player game in which Adam and Eve play natural numbers x(i). Eve wins the game if x P(A), where P(A) is the payoff set for the game G(A).

Games Ideals of Borel sets are often described in terms of infinite games. Banach-Mazur games Suppose for each Borel set A ω ω G(A) is a two player game in which Adam and Eve play natural numbers x(i). Eve wins the game if x P(A), where P(A) is the payoff set for the game G(A). Characterization of the ideals We say that a game scheme as above describes ideal I if for each Borel A ω ω A I if and only if Eve has a winning strategy in G(A).

Let E denote the ideal generated by closed measure zero sets in 2 ω.

Let E denote the ideal generated by closed measure zero sets in 2 ω. A game Consider the following game. The game is denoted by G E. It is played by Adam and Eve. In his n-th turn Adam picks x n 2 n so that x n x n 1. In her n-th turn Eve picks a basic clopen C n [x n ] such that its relative measure in [x n ] is less than 1/n. By the end of the game a sequence x = n x n 2 ω is formed. Eve wins if either x A or n x C n. Otherwise Adam wins.

Proposition (MS) For each A 2 ω Eve has a winning strategy in G E (A) if and only if A E

Proposition (MS) For each A 2 ω Eve has a winning strategy in G E (A) if and only if A E Proof Suppose first that Eve has a winning strategy σ in the game G E (A). For each s 2 <ω consider a partial play in which Adam picks s k for k s and let C s be the Eve s answer according to σ after this partial play. Put E n = s 2 n C s. Clearly E n is a clopen set and µ(e n ) 1/n. Let D n = m n E n. Now each D n is a closed set of measure zero and since σ is a winning strategy we get that A n D n.

Proof cntd Conversely, assume that A E. So there is a sequence D n of closed sets of measure zero such that A n D n. Without loss of generality assume D n D n+1. Let T n ω <ω be a tree such that D n = lim T n. We define the strategy σ for Eve in the following way. After Adam picks s 2 n in his n-th move consider the tree (T n ) s. Since lim(t n ) s is of measure zero there is k < ω such that (T n ) s 2 k 2 k < 1 n. Let Eve s answer be the set t (T n) s 2k [t]. It is easy to check that this strategy is winning for Eve.

Axiom A Recall that a forcing notion P satisfies Axiom A if there is a sequence of orderings n on P such that 0 =, n+1 n and if P p n, n < ω are such that p n+1 n p n there is a q P such that q n p n for all n, for every p P, for every n and for every ordinal name ẋ there exist P q n p and a countable set B such that q ẋ B.

Axiom A Recall that a forcing notion P satisfies Axiom A if there is a sequence of orderings n on P such that 0 =, n+1 n and if P p n, n < ω are such that p n+1 n p n there is a q P such that q n p n for all n, for every p P, for every n and for every ordinal name ẋ there exist P q n p and a countable set B such that q ẋ B. Trees Usually, Axiom A is present when the forcing has some tree reprezentation.

Proposition (MS) The forcing P E satisfies Axiom A.

Proposition (MS) The forcing P E satisfies Axiom A. Proof For each E-positive Borel set B there is a strategy σ for Adam in the game G E (B). Such a strategy can be viewed as a tree T of partial plays in G E (B) according to σ. Let f T : lim T B be the function which assignes to a run t of the game G E (B) the real x constructed by Adam in t. f T is continuous and hence A = rng(f T ) B is an analytic set. It is also E-positive since the same strategy of Adam works for A.

Proof cntd Let T be a tree of a strategy for Adam in the game scheme G E. We will say that T is winning for Adam if for each t lim T we have n x C n, where x and C n are, respectively, the real constructed by Adam and the sequence of clopens picked by Eve in t. Obviously, such a T is a winning strategy for Adam in the game G E (rng(f T )). Hence the set rng(f T ) is E-positive. Now, let T E be the forcing of trees winning for Adam in the game scheme G E. The ordering on T E is as follows: T 0 T 1 if rng(f T0 ) rng(f T1 ).

Proof cntd By Solecki (Petruska) theorem any analytic set A ω ω either contains an E-positive G δ set or can be covered by an F σ set in E. Thus the forcing P E is dense in the forcing Q E of analytic E-positive sets. It follows then that T E T rng(f T ) Q E is a dense embedding. So what we get is that the three forcing notions P E, Q E and T E are equivalent. We will establish Axiom A for T E.

Proof cntd If T T E then each t lim T is a run of a game in which Adam wins. Pick t lim T and let x be the real constructed by Adam in t and C n be the sequence of clopens constructed by Eve. We have that n x C n. In particular there is the least such n 0 and since C n0 is a clopen, there is the least m 0 n 0 such that [x m 0 ] C n0 =. Moreover, any t lim T which contains t m 0 also has this property. If we pick for each t lim T such an m 0 (t) ω then the family {t m 0 (t) : t lim T } is an antichain and each t lim T extends one of its elements. We will call it the first front of the tree T and denote it by F 1 (T ). Analogously we can define the n-th front of the tree T, F n (T ). Note that F n+1 (T ) = τ F n(t ) F 1 (T τ ).

Proof cntd Now we define fusion for T E. Let T T E and n ω, for each τ F n (T ) the set rng(f Tτ ) is still E-positive. If we substitute for T τ a tree of a winning strategy for Adam in the relativized game scheme (G E ) τ we will still obtain a tree in T E. The same is true after substitution for all T τ for τ F n (T ). We define n for n < ω as follows: S n T if S F n (T ). Then if T n is a fusion sequence, i.e. T n+1 n T n we have that T = n T n is a tree of a strategy for Adam and the strategy is winning because T contains infinitely many fronts. This ends the proof.

Yes, but... OK, but what was so special in the ideal E so that we could establish Axiom A?

Yes, but... OK, but what was so special in the ideal E so that we could establish Axiom A? Answer: Not much.

Yes, but... OK, but what was so special in the ideal E so that we could establish Axiom A? Answer: Not much. Definition. Say that an ideal I is generated by an analytic family of closed sets if there is a Σ 1 1 subset A K(2ω ) which generates I.

Theorem (MS) If I is generated by an analytic family of closed sets then the forcing P I satisfies Axiom A.

Theorem (MS) If I is generated by an analytic family of closed sets then the forcing P I satisfies Axiom A. Proof We begin with defining a game scheme G I which is an unfolded version of a Banach-Mazur scheme, i.e. it detects whether π[d] I for a closed D. Pick a bijection ρ : ω ω ω. By the theorem of Kechris, Louveau and Woodin I K(2 ω ) G δ, so let U n be a sequence of open sets such that I K(2 ω ) = n U n. Let G I be a game scheme in which Adam constructs an x (2 ω) ω and Eve constructs a sequence E n of closed sets in 2 ω.

Marcin Sabok Otherwise (Wrocław University) Eve wins Playing the withgame. forcing Proof cntd In his n-th turn Adam can either define some next bits of x or decide to wait. In her n-th turn Eve picks a basic open set O n in 2 ω such that if n = ρ(k, l) then 2 ω \ i l O ρ(i,k) D l. By the end of the game they have a sequence of closed set defined by E n = 2 ω \ O ρ(i,n). i<ω Note that each E n I. Adam wins the game G I (D) if x D and π(x) n E n.

Lemma If D is closed then Eve has a winning strategy in the game G(D) if and only if π[d] I.

Lemma If D is closed then Eve has a winning strategy in the game G(D) if and only if π[d] I. Proof cntd Let T I be the forcing of trees of a strategy for Adam that are winning. For T 0, T 1 T I we define that T 0 T 1 if π[lim T 0 ] π[lim T 1 ]. Now T π[lim T ] is a dense embedding from T I to Q I and the latter contains P I as a dense subset by the Solecki theorem. Hence the forcings T I, Q I and P I are equivalent. We will establish Axiom A for T I.

Proof cntd For T T I the winning condition says that in each game t lim T π(x) n E n. Using a compactness argument we get that for each n there is some k such that the partial play t k already determines that x E n. This observation allows us to define the fronts F n (T ) for each n and the rest of the proof follows the same lines as for P E.

The end Thank You.