Particle creation as the quantum condition for probabilistic events to occur Physics Letters A 187 Abstract A 1. Introduction

Similar documents
Does probabilism solve the great quantum mystery?

The British Society for the Philosophy of Science

The Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics (Handout Eight) between the microphysical and the macrophysical. The macrophysical world could be understood

The nature of Reality: Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen Argument in QM

HSSP Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics 08/07/11 Lecture Notes

GRW Theory (Ghirardi, Rimini, Weber Model of Quantum Mechanics)

Master Projects (EPFL) Philosophical perspectives on the exact sciences and their history

Determinate Values for Quantum Observables

09a. Collapse. Recall: There are two ways a quantum state can change: 1. In absence of measurement, states change via Schrödinger dynamics:

Where is quantum theory headed?

Hugh Everett III s Many Worlds

Quantum Mechanics: Postulates

A possible quantum basis of panpsychism

The Measurement Problem

The Foundations of Quantum Mechanics and The Limitations of Human Being

Hardy s Paradox. Chapter Introduction

The Measurement Problem of Quantum Mechanics Click to edit Master title style. Wells Wulsin SASS 24 September 2008

Theoretical Biophysics. Quantum Theory and Molecular Dynamics. Pawel Romanczuk WS 2017/18

arxiv:gr-qc/ v1 15 Apr 1997

CLASSICAL AND NON-RELATIVISTIC LIMITS OF A LORENTZ-INVARIANT BOHMIAN MODEL FOR A SYSTEM OF SPINLESS PARTICLES.

Is quantum linear superposition exact on all energy scales? A unique case study with flavour oscillating systems

The Postulates of Quantum Mechanics Common operators in QM: Potential Energy. Often depends on position operator: Kinetic Energy 1-D case: 3-D case

Does the ψ-epistemic view really solve the measurement problem?

Coins and Counterfactuals

Evidence and Theory in Physics. Tim Maudlin, NYU Evidence in the Natural Sciences, May 30, 2014

COPENHAGEN INTERPRETATION:

H. PIERRE NOYES. Stanford Linear Accelerator Center Stanford University, Stanford, California, 94305

Measurement: still a problem in standard quantum theory

Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen paradox and Bell s inequalities

Tails of Schroedinger's Cat. In his famous thought experiment Schroedinger (1935) imagined a cat that measures the

Deep Metaphysical Indeterminacy

On the role of Decoherence in Bohmian Mechanics

Section 11: Review. µ1 x < 0

Counterfactuals in Quantum Mechanics

Delayed Choice Paradox

Interference Between Distinguishable States. Thomas Alexander Meyer

Quasi-gedanken experiment challenging the nosignaling

Decoherence and the Classical Limit

arxiv:quant-ph/ v4 17 Jan 2005

ON THE NOTION OF PRIMITIVE ONTOLOGY. Andrea Oldofredi Université de Lausanne MCMP (LMU) 29 Oct. 2014

MAQRO Testing Quantum Physics in Space

Against the field ontology of quantum mechanics

General Physics (PHY 2140)

84 My God, He Plays Dice! Chapter 12. Irreversibility. This chapter on the web informationphilosopher.com/problems/reversibility

Quantum Theory: What is it about?

David Bohm s Hidden Variables

Confounding Causality Principles: comment on Rédei and san Pedro s Distinguishing Causality Principles

Incompatibility Paradoxes

Proton and Electron Mass Determination. S. Reucroft * and E. G. H. Williams ThinkIncubate, Inc., Wellesley, Mass., USA.

DEEP METAPHYSICAL INDETERMINACY

Introduction to Bell s theorem: the theory that solidified quantum mechanics

The Other Meaning of Special Relativity

arxiv:quant-ph/ v2 6 Sep 1995

A New Conception of Science

Relativistically invariant extension of the de Broglie-Bohm theory of quantum mechanics

Lecture 6-4 momentum transfer and the kinematics of two body scattering

Einselection of Pointer Observables: The New H-Theorem?

Solving the Einstein Podolsky Rosen puzzle: The origin of non-locality in Aspect-type experiments

QUASI-CLASSICAL MODEL FOR ONE-DIMENSIONAL POTENTIAL WELL

Ian Jarvie, Karl Milford and David Miller (eds.): Karl Popper - A Centenary Assessment. Volume III: Science. Ashgate Pub., Aldershot 2006,

Closing the Debates on Quantum Locality and Reality: EPR Theorem, Bell's Theorem, and Quantum Information from the Brown-Twiss Vantage

GRW Theory. Roman Frigg, LSE

Counterfactuals in Quantum Mechanics arxiv: v1 [quant-ph] 4 Sep 2007

Quantum Mechanics: Interpretation and Philosophy

What does Quantum Mechanics Tell us about Time?

A review on quantum teleportation based on: Teleporting an unknown quantum state via dual classical and Einstein- Podolsky-Rosen channels

An axiomatic approach to Einstein's boxes

Conditional Wave Function

Wave function collapse

Quantum Physics in the Nanoworld

When Worlds Collide: Quantum Probability From Observer Selection?

From Bohmian Mechanics to Bohmian Quantum Gravity. Antonio Vassallo Instytut Filozofii UW Section de Philosophie UNIL

Quantum molecular dynamics study of the pressure dependence of the ammonia inversion transition

Electron in a Box. A wave packet in a square well (an electron in a box) changing with time.

04. Five Principles of Quantum Mechanics

Meaning of the wave function

A Brief Introduction to the Quantum Harmonic Oscillator

QFT. Unit 1: Relativistic Quantum Mechanics

Bohmian Trajectories as the Foundation of Quantum Mechanics and Quantum Field Theory

Time in Bohmian Mechanics

On Spontaneous Wave Function Collapse and Quantum Field Theory

Spatial Locality: A hidden variable unexplored in entanglement experiments

Decoherence and The Collapse of Quantum Mechanics. A Modern View

The quantum way to diagonalize hermitean matrices

arxiv: v1 [quant-ph] 15 Mar 2016

A derivation of the time-energy uncertainty relation

Topic 10: Bohm s Theory

chmy361 Lec42 Tue 29nov16

EPR Paradox and Bell Inequalities

2 Quantum Mechanics. 2.1 The Strange Lives of Electrons

Probabilistic exact cloning and probabilistic no-signalling. Abstract

What is it like to be a quantum observer? And what does it imply about the nature of consciousness?

Instant Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics

arxiv: v4 [quant-ph] 26 Oct 2017

Time-Symmetrized Counterfactuals in Quantum Theory 1

E = hν light = hc λ = ( J s)( m/s) m = ev J = ev

Are All Particles Real?


Time Symmetry and the Many-Worlds Interpretation

The physical construct of quantum mechanics

Transcription:

Particle creation as the quantum condition for probabilistic events to occur Nicholas Maxwell Department of History and Philosophy of Science, University College London, Gower Street, London WC IE 6BT, UK ELSEVIER 2 May 1994 Physics Letters A 187 (1994) pp. 351-355. Received 15 October 1993; revised manuscript received 7 March 1994; accepted for publication 7 March 1994. Communicated by J.P. Vigier Abstract A new version of non-relativistic quantum theory is proposed, according to which probabilistic events occur whenever new stationary or bound states are created as a result of inelastic collisions. The new theory recovers the experimental success of orthodox quantum theory, but differs from the orthodox theory for as yet unperformed experiments. 1. Introduction Orthodox quantum theory (OQT) fails to specify the precise nature of quantum systems, such as electrons and atoms, as they exist in space and time, due to a failure to solve the quantum wave/particle problem. As a result, OQT is obliged to be a theory, not about quantum systems per se, but rather about quantum systems undergoing measurement. This means that the purely quantum mechanical postulates of OQT are without physical content; it is only when some part of classical physics is adjoined to these postulates, so that the process of measurement may be described, that OQT becomes a physical theory. As a result of being made up of these two conceptually incoherent parts (quantal and classical), OQT is, despite its immense empirical success, a seriously defective theory. It is imprecise, ambiguous, ad hoc, non-explanatory, restricted in scope, and resistant to unification [1-7]. In order to develop a version of quantum theory (QT) free of these defects, it is necessary to solve the wave/particle problem, thus providing a consistent model of quantum systems as they are in space and time independent of measurement, and freeing QT of its present conceptual dependence on classical physics. Elsewhere [3-5] I have proposed the following solution to the wave/particle problem. The quantum domain is fundamentally probabilistic in character. The physical states of quantum systems evolve deterministically, in a quasi wave-like manner, in accordance with the Schrödinger equation: what evolves, however, are propensities to interact in a probabilistic and quasi particle-like manner with other quantum systems, should appropriate quantum physical conditions to do so arise. (The notion of "propensity" employed here, a modification of Popper's notion [8,9], is a probabilistic generalization of the deterministic notion of physical property associated with classical physics [3,5,10]. ) Because quantum systems are inherently probabilistic physical entities, they differ fundamentally from all deterministic physical entities encountered in classical physics, such as the classical panicle, wave or field. The wave-like and particle-like features of quantum systems are precisely the kind of features one would expect such

systems to possess, granted that they are fundamentally probabilistic entities. Electrons, protons and atoms are neither waves nor particles: they are propensitons - physical entities with evolving propensities as basic properties, which determine how the entities interact with one another probabilistically. The nature of quantum systems only remains a mystery as long as we persist in the misguided attempt to understand them as deterministic entities. Acknowledge their inherently probabilistic nature, and quantum systems can be seen to behave just as good, descent probabilistic entities should behave. On this view, OQT is a defective theory because its creators failed to acknowledge adequately the fundamentally probabilistic character of the quantum domain, and thus failed to develop QT as a fully realistic theory about inherently probabilistic quantum "beables". This proposed solution to the wave/particle dilemma requires that precise quantum mechanical conditions are specified for probabilistic transitions to occur, conditions which restrict the application of the (deterministic) Schrödinger equation, but which make no reference to measurement (as in the case of OQT). A number of different proposals have been put forward for quantum conditions for probabilistic events to occur [11-16]. My proposal, here, is that probabilistic transitions occur when and only when new stationary or bound states, new "particle" states, are created as a result of inelastic collisions [4,5]. However, in comparison with the version of QT put forward by Ghirardi et al. [16], my proposal has so far suffered from being somewhat imprecise [17]. I now formulate the idea precisely. 2. Precise formulation of quantum condition for probabilistic wave-packet-collapse Consider a rearrangement collision, with a two channel outcome, (ab) + c (ab) + c (A) a + b + c (B) (1) Here, a, b and c are spinless particles and (ab) is the bound state. According to OQT, the outcome of the interaction is a superposition of the two channel states, (A) and (B); only on measurement, is either (A) or (B) detected. But according to the propensiton version of QT being proposed here (PQT), the superposition of (A) and (B) collapses spontaneously and probabilistically into either (A) or (B), even in the absence of measurement. Indeed, according to PQT, all probabilistic quantum measurements are just physically unremarkable special cases of this kind of probabilistic transition. All such measurements, that detect quantum systems, do so by the creation of new stationary or bound states, by the ionization or dissociation of molecules, for example: it is this which ensures that probabilistic transitions occur. More precisely, the probabilistic collapse occurs when the interaction responsible for the inelastic part of the collision is very nearly at an end. Let the state of the entire system be ψ(t), and let the asymptotic states of the two channels (A) and (B) be ψ A (t) and ψ B (t), respectively, so that, according to OQT, there are states φ A (t) and φ B (t) such that as t φ A (t) ψ A (t), φ B (t) ψ B (t), (2a)

and for all t, ψ(t) = c A φ A (t) + c B φ B (t), (2b) with c A 2 + c B 2 = 1. Here, the evolutions of ψ A (t) and ψ B (t ) are governed by the respective channel Hamiltonians, H A and H B, respectively. These differ from the Hamiltonian, H, governing the evolution of ψ (t), φ A (t) and φ B (t), in that forces between particles that are not in bound states are set to zero. We have H = - (T a + T b + T c )+ V ab + V ac + V bc, (3) H A = - (T a + T b + T c )+ V ab, (4) H B = - (T a + T b + T c ). (5) Here, T a, T b, T c represent kinetic energy, so that T a = (h 2 /2m a ) 2, where m a is the mass of particle a. V ab, V ac and V bc are potentials corresponding to the forces between a and b, a and c, and b and c, respectively. The condition for probabilistic collapse can now be stated as follows. Let ψ c (t) = c A ψ A (t) + c B ψ B (t ). Then: Condition 1. At the first instant t for which < ψ c (t) ψ(t) > > 1 - ε is satisfied, the state of the system, ψ(t), jumps probabilistically into either φ A (t) with probability c A 2 or into φ B (t) with probability c B 2, ε being a universal constant, a positive real number very nearly equal to zero. It is a straightforward matter to generalize condition 1 so that it applies to the case of an inelastic interaction with N channel outcomes, with N distinct asymptotic states, N > 2. Detection of a micro system as a part of the process of quantum measurement typically involves allowing an unlocalized system to interact elastically with billions of localized systems, as when a photon interacts with the billions of silver bromide crystals of a photographic plate. In this sort of case, the generalized version of condition 1 is to be straightforwardly applied. The outcome of the interaction is a superposition of billions of channels; these collapse to just one or other channel when condition l is satisfied. The outcome is the dissociation of one silver bromide molecule somewhere on the photographic plate. Granted condition 1, inelastic interactions can, but do not invariably, localize. In the case of inelastic scattering of neutrons by means of a crystal lattice, although the neutrons interact inelastically with the crystal lattice, they are not localized at one or other node of the lattice, as is demonstrated by the existence of interference effects in the scattered neutron beam. The inelastic interaction creates an unlocalized phonon in the crystal. In this case, there are just two channel outcomes: the outcome of the elastic interaction, and the inelastic interaction.

3. Experimental adequacy of PQT It might be thought that PQT cannot recover all the empirical success of OQT. OQT includes the following: Postulate I. If a measurement of observable A is performed on a system in a state ψ, then the probability of obtaining a value between a r and a r+dr = (α r, ψ) 2 dr, where a r, and α r are eigenvalues and eigenvectors of the Hermitian operator Ă corresponding to the observable A. PQT differs from OQT in that it dispenses with postulate 1, and replaces it with the generalized version of condition 1. PQT is thus restricted to making probabilistic predictions about the outcome of inelastic collisions. This means, on the face of it, that PQT is restricted to making predictions about position measurements - position, typically, being measured via ionization or dissociation of molecules. How can PQT make predictions about other observables, energy, momentum, spin? The answer is that all measurements, of all observables, that are not merely preparations (to use Margenau's term [18]), involve the detection of quantum systems via the creation of new bound states. For example, a measurement of energy or spin involves, typically, a preparation procedure, which associates distinct spatial regions with eigenstates of energy or spin, plus detection of systems in one or another spatial region (see Ref. [3], pp. 661-666; Ref. [4], pp. 622-626; and Ref. [5], pp. 35-37). PQT is thus able to reproduce all the empirical success of OQT without calling upon postulate I. In particular, whereas OQT must presuppose the existence of quasi classical macro objects, for measurement, PQT is able to predict the existence of such objects from purely quantal postulates. A macro object remains localized because it repeatedly suffers probabilistic localizations, in accordance with condition 1. In opposition to what has just been claimed, it may be argued that some measurements need only involve elastic collisions, in which case, according to condition 1, no probabilistic collapse will occur. This may, indeed, be thought to provide sufficient grounds for rejecting condition 1, and the version of PQT based on it. Consider, for example, the following thought experiment (suggested by an anonymous referee), intended to illustrate the general idea of measurement without inelastic collision. A massive particle is scattered elastically into two wavepackets, each ending up in distinct pans of a balance. Condition 1 implies that, as long as no inelastic collision occurs, the balance will go into a superposition of weighing the particle in one pan, and in the other pan (which only collapses into one or other state with the eventual occurrence of some random inelastic collision). But this, it may be argued, is absurd, since the balance is a macroscopic object. But is the idea that such macroscopic superpositions exist absurd? Surely not. According to PQT, the world is made up of propensitons, fundamentally probabilistic objects which, in appropriate conditions, evolve into superpositions of states and, as a result, smear out spatially in a way that is unlike anything encountered in deterministic classical physics. Composite objects, such as atoms, molecules, crystals and other macroscopic objects are just as much propensitons as electrons are. All this does violence to common sense, and to physical intuitions based on deterministic classical physics; but that does not in itself

provide grounds for rejecting the idea that propensitons exist, that even macroscopic objects are propensitons, and superpositions of macroscopically distinct states exist in appropriate circumstances. Whether a macroscopic balance can exist in the kind of superposition of states indicated above is a factual question, the answer to which cannot be decided a priori. In principle it is possible to determine the answer experimentally; in practice this is difficult, due in part to the large mass of macroscopic objects such as the balance, and due in part to the ubiquity of inelastic collisions. (We would never be able to see the balance in a superposition of states, since seeing involves the occurrence of inelastic interactions.) The fact that the two-slit experiment can be done with atoms, and presumably with molecules, with tiny crystals, may incline us to the view that interference effects could in principle be detected even if the experiment is done with macroscopic objects (since the difference between micro and macro is here a matter of degree rather than kind). It is worth noting, finally, in connection with this point, that PQT and OQT agree that superpositions of macroscopically distinct states can exist. However, the version of QT proposed by Ghirardi et al. [16], referred to above, implies that sufficiently large macroscopic objects do not persist in superpositions of macroscopically distinct states, even in the absence of inelastic collisions. There is here, perhaps, the possibility of a crucial experiment capable of deciding between OQT and PQT on the one hand, and the version of QT proposed by Ghirardi et al. on the other hand. 4. Crucial experiment How can experiment decide between PQT and OQT? As long as ε is sufficiently small to ensure that no probabilistic transitions occur during inelastic collisions in physical experiments until measurements are performed, PQT will accurately reproduce all the predictions of OQT. (The two theories employ the same dynamic laws of evolution.) Indeed, even if probabilistic transitions do occur before measurement, the distinct predictions of OQT and PQT will not ordinarily be detected. In the case of the rearrangement collision, the difference between the superposition c A φ A (t) + c B φ B (t), predicted by OQT, and the mixture φ A (t) (probability c A 2 ) or φ B (t) (probability c B 2 ), predicted by PQT, will not be detected by ordinary experiments. In order to detect the difference, it will be necessary to recombine the two channels, (ab ) + c and a+b+c, so that the a+b+c channel becomes (ab) + c, and interference effects can be detected. This requires that the experimental setup is such that no measurement can determine along which route, (ab) + c or a + b + c, the system evolves. Granted that the value of ε is such that, in these circumstances, PQT predicts that the superposition c A φ A (t) + c B φ B (t) collapses into either φ A (t) or φ B (t) (before measurement) then, whereas OQT will predict interference, PQT will predict no interference. The possibility, in principle, of performing this crucial experiment establishes that OQT and PQT are empirically distinct theories. The crucial experiment is however extremely difficult to do in practice, and has not as yet been performed as far as the present author is aware.

Acknowledgement I wish to thank Elliot Leader, Ian Thompson, Chris Isham, Gordon Fleming, Euan Squires and Robert Seymour for invaluable help at various times in developing the idea of this paper. References [1] N. Maxwell, Am. J. Phys. 40 (1972) 1431. [2] N. Maxwell, Am. J. Phys. 41 ( 1973 ) 1022. [3] N. Maxwell, Found. Phys. 6 (1976) 275, 661. [4] N. Maxwell, Found. Phys. 12 (1982) 607. [5] N. Maxwell, Brit. J. Philos. Sci. 39 (1988) 1. [6] N. Maxwell, in: Bell's theorem and the foundations of modern physics, eds. A. van der Merwe, F. Selleri and G. Tarozzi (World Scientific, Singapore, 1993 ) p. 362. [7] J.S. Bell, Speakable and unspeakable in quantum mechanics (Cambridge Univ. Press, Cambridge, 1987). [8] K.R. Popper, Brit. J. Philos. Sci. 10 (1959) 25. [9] K.R. Popper, in: Quantum theory and reality, ed. M. Bunge (Springer, Berlin, 1967) p. 7. [10] N. Maxwell, Philos. Sci. 52 (1985) 23. [11] F. Karolyhazy, Nuovo Cimento A 42 (1966) 390. [12] D. Bedford and D. Wang, Nuovo Cimento B 37 (1977) 55. [13] P.J. Bussey, Phys. Lett. A 106 (1984) 407. [14] S. Machida and M. Namiki, in: Foundations of quantum mechanics, eds. S. Kamefuchi et al. (Physical Society of Japan, Tokyo, 1984) p. 136. [15] R. Penrose, in: Quantum concepts of space and time, eds. C. Isham and R. Penrose (Oxford Univ. Press, Oxford, 1986) p. 129. [16] G. Ghirardi, A. Rimini and T. Weber, Phys. Rev. D 34 (1986) 470. [17] E. Squires, Brit. J. Philos. Sci. 40 (1989) 413. [18] H. Margenau, Philos. Sci. 4 ( 1968 ) 337.