The Boolean Ring of Intervals

Similar documents
Axioms of Measure Theory

Here are some examples of algebras: F α = A(G). Also, if A, B A(G) then A, B F α. F α = A(G). In other words, A(G)

If a subset E of R contains no open interval, is it of zero measure? For instance, is the set of irrationals in [0, 1] is of measure zero?

It is always the case that unions, intersections, complements, and set differences are preserved by the inverse image of a function.

Integrable Functions. { f n } is called a determining sequence for f. If f is integrable with respect to, then f d does exist as a finite real number

Chapter 0. Review of set theory. 0.1 Sets

(A sequence also can be thought of as the list of function values attained for a function f :ℵ X, where f (n) = x n for n 1.) x 1 x N +k x N +4 x 3

The Borel hierarchy classifies subsets of the reals by their topological complexity. Another approach is to classify them by size.

Lecture Notes for Analysis Class

Product measures, Tonelli s and Fubini s theorems For use in MAT3400/4400, autumn 2014 Nadia S. Larsen. Version of 13 October 2014.

Solution. 1 Solutions of Homework 1. Sangchul Lee. October 27, Problem 1.1

Measure and Measurable Functions

1 Introduction. 1.1 Notation and Terminology

Introduction to Probability. Ariel Yadin. Lecture 7

Singular Continuous Measures by Michael Pejic 5/14/10

HOMEWORK #4 - MA 504

Exercises 1 Sets and functions

2.1. The Algebraic and Order Properties of R Definition. A binary operation on a set F is a function B : F F! F.

FUNDAMENTALS OF REAL ANALYSIS by. V.1. Product measures

Lecture 3 : Random variables and their distributions

3 Gauss map and continued fractions

Solutions to Math 347 Practice Problems for the final

Math 220A Fall 2007 Homework #2. Will Garner A

Math 451: Euclidean and Non-Euclidean Geometry MWF 3pm, Gasson 204 Homework 3 Solutions

What is Probability?

Advanced Stochastic Processes.

Theorem 3. A subset S of a topological space X is compact if and only if every open cover of S by open sets in X has a finite subcover.

Chapter 3. Strong convergence. 3.1 Definition of almost sure convergence

CHAPTER 10 INFINITE SEQUENCES AND SERIES

Introduction to Probability. Ariel Yadin. Lecture 2

} is said to be a Cauchy sequence provided the following condition is true.

Archimedes - numbers for counting, otherwise lengths, areas, etc. Kepler - geometry for planetary motion

Math 299 Supplement: Real Analysis Nov 2013

Metric Space Properties

Ma 530 Introduction to Power Series

Homework 1 Solutions. The exercises are from Foundations of Mathematical Analysis by Richard Johnsonbaugh and W.E. Pfaffenberger.

Math 104: Homework 2 solutions

Sets and Probabilistic Models

On Random Line Segments in the Unit Square

Lecture 10: Mathematical Preliminaries

5 Many points of continuity

Convergence of random variables. (telegram style notes) P.J.C. Spreij

Part A, for both Section 200 and Section 501

page Suppose that S 0, 1 1, 2.

Cardinality Homework Solutions

Notes #3 Sequences Limit Theorems Monotone and Subsequences Bolzano-WeierstraßTheorem Limsup & Liminf of Sequences Cauchy Sequences and Completeness

The multiplicative structure of finite field and a construction of LRC

B Supplemental Notes 2 Hypergeometric, Binomial, Poisson and Multinomial Random Variables and Borel Sets

Arkansas Tech University MATH 2924: Calculus II Dr. Marcel B. Finan

Math 61CM - Solutions to homework 3

2.4 Sequences, Sequences of Sets

Homework 2. Show that if h is a bounded sesquilinear form on the Hilbert spaces X and Y, then h has the representation

lim za n n = z lim a n n.

Chapter 6 Infinite Series

MATH301 Real Analysis (2008 Fall) Tutorial Note #7. k=1 f k (x) converges pointwise to S(x) on E if and

M17 MAT25-21 HOMEWORK 5 SOLUTIONS

Rademacher Complexity

4.1 Sigma Notation and Riemann Sums

FUNDAMENTALS OF REAL ANALYSIS by

62. Power series Definition 16. (Power series) Given a sequence {c n }, the series. c n x n = c 0 + c 1 x + c 2 x 2 + c 3 x 3 +

Math 140A Elementary Analysis Homework Questions 3-1

MATH 324 Summer 2006 Elementary Number Theory Solutions to Assignment 2 Due: Thursday July 27, 2006

A gentle introduction to Measure Theory

Solutions to Tutorial 3 (Week 4)

Math 155 (Lecture 3)

Chain conditions. 1. Artinian and noetherian modules. ALGBOOK CHAINS 1.1

Assignment 5: Solutions

f(x)g(x) dx is an inner product on D.

An Introduction to Randomized Algorithms

# fixed points of g. Tree to string. Repeatedly select the leaf with the smallest label, write down the label of its neighbour and remove the leaf.

REMARKS ON SMALL SETS ON THE REAL LINE

Analytic Continuation

s = and t = with C ij = A i B j F. (i) Note that cs = M and so ca i µ(a i ) I E (cs) = = c a i µ(a i ) = ci E (s). (ii) Note that s + t = M and so

Topics. Homework Problems. MATH 301 Introduction to Analysis Chapter Four Sequences. 1. Definition of convergence of sequences.

Week 5-6: The Binomial Coefficients

NOTES ON PROBABILITY THEORY FOR ENEE 620. Adrian Papamarcou. (with references to Probability and Measure by Patrick Billingsley)

Infinite Sequences and Series

Seunghee Ye Ma 8: Week 5 Oct 28

4 The Sperner property.

MAT1026 Calculus II Basic Convergence Tests for Series

( ) = p and P( i = b) = q.

In number theory we will generally be working with integers, though occasionally fractions and irrationals will come into play.

REAL ANALYSIS II: PROBLEM SET 1 - SOLUTIONS

Math 341 Lecture #31 6.5: Power Series

Lecture 3 The Lebesgue Integral

PRACTICE FINAL/STUDY GUIDE SOLUTIONS

Notes on Snell Envelops and Examples

INFINITE SEQUENCES AND SERIES

Linear chord diagrams with long chords

Lecture 2. The Lovász Local Lemma

M A T H F A L L CORRECTION. Algebra I 1 4 / 1 0 / U N I V E R S I T Y O F T O R O N T O

ABOUT CHAOS AND SENSITIVITY IN TOPOLOGICAL DYNAMICS

Model Theory 2016, Exercises, Second batch, covering Weeks 5-7, with Solutions

Sequences and Series of Functions

Lecture 4: Grassmannians, Finite and Affine Morphisms

CS / MCS 401 Homework 3 grader solutions

DIVISIBILITY PROPERTIES OF GENERALIZED FIBONACCI POLYNOMIALS

Sets and Probabilistic Models

Chapter IV Integration Theory

Topologie. Musterlösungen

Transcription:

MATH 532 Lebesgue Measure Dr. Neal, WKU We ow shall apply the results obtaied about outer measure to the legth measure o the real lie. Throughout, our space X will be the set of real umbers R. Whe ecessary, we shall assume that R is a metric space with the distace betwee poits give by d (x, y ) = x y. The Boolea Rig of Itervals We ow let R(I) be the collectio of all fiite uios of disjoit itervals of the form [a, b) o the real lie where a b. To show that R (I) is a rig, we must argue that R (I) is closed uder fiite uios ad set differeces. We shall first use iductio to show that ay fiite uio of itervals ca be re-writte as a uio of at most disjoit itervals. First, cosider [a 1, b 1 ) [a 2, b 2 ), where a 1 a 2. If b 1 a 2, the [a 1, b 1 ) [a 2, b 2 ) is already a disjoit uio, ad if b 1 = a 2 the it actually ca be re-writte as [a 1, b 2 ). If a 1 a 2 < b 1, the [a 1, b 1 ) [a 2, b 2 ) is the sigle iterval [a 1, max{b 1, b 2 }). So ay two itervals are either already disjoit or ca be re-writte as a sigle iterval. Now assume that for 2 k, ay set of k itervals ca be re-writte as a uio of at most k disjoit itervals, ad cosider a uio of + 1 itervals. By the iductio hypothesis, we ca assume that the first itervals reduce to at most disjoit itervals. If the ( + 1)st iterval is already disjoit from all the others, the we have at most + 1 disjoit itervals. But if the ( + 1)st iterval itersects say the j th iterval, the those two ca be re-writte as oe iterval as discussed i the achor step above with just two itervals. So ow we are reduced to at most itervals, which by the iductio hypothesis, ca be re-writte as a uio of at most disjoit itervals. m Thus, if A = U [a i, b i ) R (I) ad B = U [c j,d j ) R (I), the A B is still a fiite j =1 uio of disjoit itervals of the form [a, b); thus, A B R (I). Note that = [a, a) R (I). Next cosider C = [a 1, b 1 ) [a 2, b 2 ), where a 1 a 2. If b 1 a 2, the C = R (I). If a 1 a 2 < b 1, the C = [a 2, mi{b 1, b 2 }) R (I). That is, C = [a 1, b 1 ) [a 2, b 2 ) always reduces to a sigle iterval of the form [a, b). So if m m A = U [a i, b i ) ad B = U [c j,d j ) are i R (I), the A B = U U [a i, b i ) [c j, d j ) is j =1 j =1 still i R (I) because it is a fiite uio of itervals of the form [a, b), which the reduces to a fiite uio of disjoit itervals of the form [a, b). So R (I) is closed uder fiite itersectios. Now cosider D = [a 1, b 1 ) [a 2, b 2 ). If a 2 a 1, the D = [b 2, b 1 ) which is empty if b 1 b 2. If a 1 < a 2, the D = [a 1, a 2 ) if b 1 b 2 ad D = [a 1, a 2 ) [b 2, b 1 ) if b 2 < b 1. I m ay case, we have D R (I). Now if A = U [a i, b i ) ad B = U [c j,d j ) are i R (I), j =1 m the we have A B = U I ([a i, b i ) [c j, d j )) R (I). Thus, R (I) is a Boolea rig. j =1

The Legth Measure Agai let R (I) be the collectio of all fiite uios of disjoit itervals of the form [a, b). Let : R (I) [0, ) be defied as follows: If [a i, b i ) is a collectio of { } disjoit itervals with A = U A i, the let ( A) = (b i a i ). I particular, let i= 1 ([a, b) ) = b a, which gives the legth of the iterval. Clearly, 0 ( A) < for all A R(I). We assert that is a measure o R (I). Let A, B R (I) with A B =. The A ad B are each fiite uios of disjoit itervals. Thus we ca write A = U [a i, b i ) where a 1 < b 1 <... < a < b, ad +m B = U [a i, b i ) where a +1 < b +1 <... < a +m < b +m. Because A B =, there is o i = +1 +m overlap amog ay of the itervals. Therefore, A B = U [a i,b i ) is still i the form of a disjoit uio of itervals; thus, +m + m ( A B) = (b i a i ) = (b i a i ) + (b i a i ) = (A) + ( B). i= +1 That is, is fiitely additive. Also ( ) = ([a,a)) = 0. But i order for to be a measure, it must be coutably additive. We develop this result ext. Lemma 3.1. Let B, C R (I) with B C. The (B) (C). Proof. We write C = B (C B) as a disjoit uio i R (I). The by the fiite additivity of, we have (C) = (B) + (C B) (B) because (C B) 0. Lemma 3.2. Let { A i } be a sequece of disjoit sets from R (I) such that A = U Ai is also i R (I). The (A i ) ( A). Proof. By the fiite additivity of ad Lemma 3.1, we have for all 1 that (A i ) = U A i ( A ). We obtai the result by takig the limit as.

Lemma 3.3. (a) Let [c, d ) be partitioed by c = e 1 < f 1 = e 2 < f 2 =... = e < f = d so that [c, d ) = U [e i, f i ) is a disjoit uio with strictly icreasig edpoits. The i= 1 ( f i e i ) = d c. (b) Let [c, d ) be partitioed by c = e 1 < f 1 = e 2 < f 2 =... = e < f =...< d so that [c, d ) = U [e i, f i ). The d = lim f ad ( f i e i ) = d c. i= 1 Proof. Part (a) follows from the fiite additivity of or by a telescopig sum usig the assumptio that f i = e i+1 for 1 i 1, e 1 = c, ad f = d. For Part (b), the sequece { f } is strictly icreasig ad bouded above by d ; thus lim f exists ad c lim f = sup{f } d. But if sup { f } < d, the there exists a poit x [c, d ) such that sup{ f } < x < d. But this x cotradicts the assumptio that [c, d ) = U [e i, f i ). Hece, lim f = d. The by telescopig series, we have i= 1 ( f i e i ) = lim ( f i e i ) = lim (f e 1 ) = d c. QED Lemma 3.4. Let { A i } be a sequece of disjoit sets from R (I) such that A = U Ai is also i R (I). The, ( A) ( A i ). i Proof. For each i, let A i = U [a ij, b ij ) be a fiite uio of disjoit itervals with strictly j =1 i icreasig edpoits. The A = U U [a ij, b ij ) is a deumerable uio of disjoit j =1 itervals. But because A is i R (I), A also ca be writte as a fiite uio of disjoit N itervals A = U [c k, d k ), also with strictly icreasig edpoits: c 1 < d 1 <... < c N < d N. k = 1

i Dr. Neal, WKU N Next we ca write A as A = U U U ([a ij, b ij ) [c k, d k )). Because we still have a j =1 deumerable uio of disjoit itervals [a ij, b ij ) [c k, d k ), we ca rewrite this uio further as A = U [e i, f i ) where ow all e i ad all f i are bouded withi [c 1, d N ), all itervals are disjoit, ad each iterval is completely cotaied withi [c k, d k ) for some k. For 1 k N, we ow partitio each [c k, d k ). Because c k A, let e k1 be the first edpoit such that c k [e k1, f k1 ). The we must have e k1 = c k ad [e k1, f k1 ) [c k, d k ). If f k1 = d k, the we stop. Otherwise, because f k1 A, we let e k 2 be the first edpoit such that f k1 [e k2, f k 2 ). Because all [e i, f i ) are disjoit, we must have f k1 = e k 2 ad still [e k 2, f k2 ) [c k, d k ). We cotiue as ecessary. We thereby obtai either a fiite or ifiite sequece c k = e k1 < f k1 = e k 2 < f k2 =... = e k < f k =... d k such that [c k, d k ) = U [e kl, f kl ). l By costructio, each [e i, f i ) is also cotaied i some particular iterval [a ij, b ij ). Thus, by Lemma 3.3, we have N N N ( A) = ([c k, d k )) = (d k c k ) = ( f kl e kl ) l i (b ij a ij ) = (b ij a ij ) = ( A i ). i, j j=1 QED Combiig Lemmas 3.2 ad 3.4, we obtai: Theorem 3.1. The legth measure is coutably additive o R (I). The Hereditary -algebra The hereditary -rig of R(I) is the collectio of all subsets of the real lie that have a coutable coverig of sets from R (I): C(R(I)) = A (, ) : A U A i, for some, where 1, ad all A i R (I). I particular, ay bouded subset of the real lie is cotaied i a sigle iterval of the form [, ) ; thus, C(R(I)) cotais all bouded sets. Of course, C(R(I)) the cotais every subset of a bouded set as well.

We have see that the hereditary -rig actually is a -rig. However, the etire real lie R is covered the sequece of sets {[, ) } = 1. Thus, R C(R (I)), which makes C(R(I)) a -algebra. The ay subset of R is covered by the same coverig as R; hece, C(R(I)) is actually the power set of R. The Borel -algebra ad the Lebesgue -algebra Previously, we defied the Borel -algebra B to be the smallest -algebra cotaiig all itervals of the form [a, b), where a b. But (R(I)), the smallest -algebra cotaiig R (I), also cotais all itervals of the form [a, b); so B (R(I)). However, B also cotais R (I), so (R(I)) B. I other words, (R(I)) is the Borel -algebra. I this cotext, the measurable sets M (C(R (I))) are called the Lebesgue measurable sets ad are deoted by L. So the rig of itervals is cotaied i the Borel -algebra, which is cotaied i the Lebesgue -algebra of measurable sets, which is cotaied i the hereditary - algebra which equals the power set of the real lie: R (I) (R(I)) M (C(R(I))) C(R(I)) = P(R) or R (I) B L P(R) The outer measure is defied for every set i C(R(I)) = P(R), which meas that it is defied for every subset of the real lie. Also, ( A) = ( A) for all A R(I). I particular, ([a, b) ) = ([a, b) ) = b a for all itervals [a, b). Moreover, is a coutably additive measure o the set of Lebesgue measurable sets L. Whe we are specifically evaluatig the outer measure of a arbitrary subset, the we will use. However, at this poit, if we are specifically evaluatig the measure of a Lebesgue measurable set, the we will simply use. Recall that E L if ad oly if ( A) = (A E) + ( A E c ) for all A P(R), which is satisfied by every set E that has outer measure 0 (Theorem 2.1). Ad every subset of a set of measure 0 is Lebesgue measurable ad also has measure 0. The sets of measure 0 are very importat; i fact, we will show that every Lebesgue measurable set differs from a Borel measurable set by a set of measure 0.

The Borel measurable sets are essetially the subsets of the real lie that ca be obtaied through a coutable umber of operatios o itervals of the form [a, b) that ivolve uios, complemets, or itersectios. For istace, (, ) = U [, ) Primes = U I [ p, p +1 / ) =1 p =1 Cator Set: C = I C, where = 0 C 0 = [0, 1], C 1 = C 0 (1 / 3, 2 / 3) = [0, 1/ 3] [2 / 3, 1], C 2 = C 1 (1 / 9, 2 / 9) (7 / 9, 8 / 9) = [0, 1/ 9] [2 / 9, 3/ 9] [6 / 9, 7 / 9] [8 / 9, 1], etc. Theorem 3.2. Every ope subset of the real lie is Borel measurable. Proof. Let E be ope. If E =, the E B. So assume that E. The there is some x E. Because E is ope, there is a eighborhood (x, x + ) E. Now there must be a ratioal umber withi (x, x + ). So E must cotai a ratioal umber. For every ratioal umber q E, there is ope iterval (q r q, q + r q ) E. By takig a smaller radius if ecessary, we ca assume that r q is ratioal. Now for each q E, let R q be the set of ratioal radii r such that (q r, q + r) E. Because the ratioals are deumerable, S q = U (q r, q + r) is a deumerable uio ad therefore r R q is Borel measurable because each iterval (q r, q + r) is i B. Moreover, S q E for all q E. The S = U S q = U U (q r, q + r) is also a Borel measurable set cotaied q E q E r R q i E, ad S clearly cotais all ratioal umbers i E. But if x is a irratioal umber i E, the there is a ope iterval (x, x + ) E for which is ratioal. The there is a ratioal umber q such that x < q < x + / 2. But the x (q / 2, q + / 2) (x, x ) E. So x S q S. Thus, E = S ad E is Borel measurable. QED Corollary 3.1. Let (O) be the -algebra geerated by the ope sets of the real lie. The (O) is the Borel -algebra. Proof. Because B is a -algebra that cotais all ope sets, B cotais the -algebra geerated by the ope sets (O). O the other had, (O) cotais all itervals of the form [a, b) = I (a 1/, b). Thus, (O) cotais the -algebra geerated by =1 itervals of the form [a, b) which is B. QED We ow show that a Lebesgue measurable set is always withi a set of measure 0 of two Borel measurable sets:

Theorem 3.3. Let E L. There exist Borel measurable sets B, A such that B E A ad ( A E) = 0 = (E B). Proof. First, assume that (E ) <. By the defiitio of outer measure, for every iteger 1, there exists a coutable collectio of sets { A i } from the rig of itervals R (I) such that E U A i ad ( A i ) < ( E) +1 /. Now let A = I U A i. The i i = 1 i A B ad E A U A i for all 1. Also, (E ) = (E ) by covetio. Hece, for i all, (E ) ( A) U A i i i (A i ) < ( E) +1 /. By lettig, we have (E ) ( A) (E) ; or (E ) = (A). Now we have the disjoit uio E (A E) = A, which gives (E ) + (A E) = ( A). Because (E ) = (A) <, we have ( A E) = 0. Now for E L, let E k = E [ k, k) for all itegers k 1. The E k L for all k ad (E k ) ([ k, k )) <. So for each k, there exists a Borel measurable set A k ad a set of measure 0, give by N k = A k E k, such that E k A k ad E k N k = A k. Now let A = U A k B. The E = U E k A so that E (A E) = A. Also, k = 1 A E U ( A k E k ) = U N k. By Propositio 1.2 (g), U N k still has measure 0, so ( A E) = 0. Because E c L, there exists C B, with E c C ad 0 = (C E c ) = (C E ). But the C c B, C c E, ad (E C c ) = ( E C) = 0. Lettig B = C c, we have B E, ad B ( E B) = E with (E B) = 0. QED The precedig theorem gives two way to characterize the Lebesgue measurable sets: L = {B N : B B ad ( N) = 0} ad L = {A N : A B ad (N ) = 0}. Lebesgue Measure The Lebesgue measure : L [0, ] is a extesio of the legth measure for which ([a, b) ) = b a. So gives a way of measurig the legth of other subsets of the real lie i a coutably additive way. Next are some immediate legth properties:

Theorem 3.4. For all a, b R with a < b: (a) ({a}) = 0 (b) ((a, b) ) = ((a, b] ) = ([a, b] ) = b a (c) ([a, ) ) = ((a, ) ) = ((, b) ) = ((, b] ) = + (d) ((, ) ) = + (e) If A is a coutable subset of R, the ( A) = 0. Proof. We simply use the properties of a measure o a -algebra. (a) Because {[a, a + 1/ i) } is a ested, decreasig sequece of measurable sets with ([a, a +1) ) <, we have by Propositio 1.3 (b), ({a}) = I [a, a + 1/ i) = lim ([a, a +1/ ) ) = lim 1 / = 0. (b) ((a, b) ) = ([a, b) {a}) = ([a, b) ) ({a}) = b a ((a, b] ) = ((a, b) {b}) = ((a, b) ) + ({b} ) = b a ([a, b] ) = ([a, b) {b}) = ([a, b) ) + ({b}) = b a (c) Because { [a, a + i) } is a ested, icreasig sequece of sets, we have ([a, ) ) = U [a, a + i) i= 1 = lim ([a, a + ) ) = lim = +. The other results of Part (c) are simple exercises. (d) Because [0, ) (, ), we have ((, ) ) ([0, ) ) = +. (e) Because is A coutable, we have A = {a i }, where 0, ad all a i R are distict. Thus, ( A) = U{a i } i= 1 = ({a i }) = 0. i= 1 Applyig (d) ad (e), we have: Corollary 3.2. O the real lie, the ratioals Q have Lebesgue measure 0 ad the irratioals I have ifiite Lebesgue measure.

Uiform Probability Let a < b, let Ω = [a, b], ad let F be the -algebra of all Lebesgue measurable subsets of [a, b]. ( F = {E [a, b]: E L}.) Defie P : F [0, 1] by P(A) = ( A) b a. I particular, for [c, d ] [a, b], we have P([c, d ]) = d c ad also P(Ω) = 1. Because b a is coutably additive, it follows that P is a probability measure. This measure is used to compute probabilities whe choosig values at radom from the iterval [a, b]. Example 3.1. Pick a value x at radom from [0, 20]. What is the probability of it beig (a) at least 5? (b) at most 8? (c) at least 3 away from 10? (d) ratioal? Solutio. (a) P([5, 20]) = 15 / 20 (b) P([0, 8]) = 8 / 20 (c) P([0, 7] [13, 20]) = 14 / 20 (d) P(Q [0, 20]) (Q) = 0. The Cator Set We previously described the Cator Set as C = I C, where C 0 = [0, 1], = 0 C 1 = C 0 (1 / 3, 2 / 3) = [0, 1/ 3] [2 / 3, 1], C 2 = C 1 (1 / 9, 2 / 9) (7 / 9, 8 / 9) = [0, 1/ 9] [2 / 9, 3/ 9] [6 / 9, 7 / 9] [8 / 9, 1], etc. The C is Borel measurable beig the deumerable itersectio of Borel sets. Each set C is the uio of 2 disjoit closed itervals each of which has legth 1 / 3. Give C, set C +1 is created by removig the middle ope third of each closed iterval i C. The Cator set ca be uderstood easily by cosiderig the tertiary (base 3) expasio of the umbers x i [0, 1]. Each x [0, 1] ca be writte as x = 0. a 1 a 2 a 3... = a 1 / 3 + a 2 / 9+ a 3 / 27 +... where a i {0, 1, 2}. The expasio is ot uique; for istace, 1/3 = 0.1000... = 0.0222... The Cator Set cosists of those x [0, 1] that ca be writte with a i {0, 2} for all i. So if a 1 = 0, the the largest x ca be is 0.0222... = 1/3. If a 1 = 2, the the smallest x ca be is 0.20000 = 2/3. So havig a 1 {0, 2} meas that x C 1 = [0, 1 / 3] [2 / 3, 1]. Next we have x = 0.00..., or x = 0.02..., or x = 0.20..., or x = 0.22..., which meas that x [0, 1/ 9] [2 / 9, 3 / 9] [6 / 9, 7 / 9] [8 / 9, 1].

So C = {0.a 1 a 2 a 3... : a i {0, 2} for all i}. Thus C is i oe-to-oe correspodece with the set B = {0. b 1 b 2 b 3... : b i {0,1} for all i}, which gives the biary expasios of all x [0, 1]. So C ~ B ~[0, 1] ~ R, which meas that the Cator set is ucoutable. But C C for all ; thus, (C) (C ) = 2 ( 1/ 3) = (2 / 3) for all 1. By lettig, we see that (C) = 0. Thus, the Cator Set gives a example of a ucoutable set that has Lebesgue measure 0. Moreover, ay subset of the Cator Set is also Lebesgue measurable ad also has measure 0. Note: With some more advaced set theory, it ca be show that the collectio of Borel sets is also i oe-to-oe correspodece with the real lie. Thus, B = C = R = c. But every subset of C is Lebesgue measurable, ad the cardiality of the umber of subsets of the Cator Set is 2 c > c = B. So there must be more Lebesgue measurable sets tha Borel measurable sets. I other words, there exist Lebesgue measurable sets that are ot Borel measurable. Exercises Exercise 3.1. Let (Cl) be the -algebra geerated by the closed sets of the real lie. Prove that (Cl) is the Borel -algebra. Exercise 3.2. Let N = { A L : (A) = 0} be the collectio of all sets of Lebesgue measure 0. Prove that N is a -rig. Exercise 3.3. Cosider the followig sets o the real lie: (i) I (10 1/ i,15 + 1/ i) (ii) U [20 +1 / i, 30 1/ i] For each: (a) Derive its Lebesgue measure by usig a limit theorem for ested sets. (b) Evaluate the set as oe iterval ad give its Lebesgue measure directly. Exercise 3.4. Cosider the base 10 decimal expasio of values i [0, 1]. (The expasio is ot uique: 1/2 = 0.5000... = 0.4999...) Fid the Lebesgue measure of the followig sets: A 1 = {x : x = 0.4 a 2 a 3...} A 2 = {x : x = 0.53 a 3 a 4...} A 3 = {x : x = 0.872 a 4 a 5...} Exercise 3.5. Cosider the base 3 expasio of values i [0, 1]. Fid the Lebesgue measure of the followig sets: B 1 = {x : x = 0.1 a 2 a 3...} B 2 = {x : x = 0.21a 3 a 4...} B 3 = {x : x = 0.102 a 4 a 5...}