RUNS: A_B, A_B', A'_B,

Similar documents
Is Bell s Locality Condition Necessary for The Derivation of Bell s Inequality?

Bell s inequalities and their uses

The nature of Reality: Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen Argument in QM

Closing the Debates on Quantum Locality and Reality: EPR Theorem, Bell's Theorem, and Quantum Information from the Brown-Twiss Vantage

Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen paradox and Bell s inequalities

1.1.1 Bell Inequality - Spin correlation

A proof of Bell s inequality in quantum mechanics using causal interactions

Mathematical and Physical Examination of the Locality Condition in Bell s Theorem

Spatial Locality: A hidden variable unexplored in entanglement experiments

The Common Cause Principle

The CHSH game as a Bell test thought experiment

Logical difficulty from combining counterfactuals in the GHZ-Bell theorems

The controlled-not (CNOT) gate exors the first qubit into the second qubit ( a,b. a,a + b mod 2 ). Thus it permutes the four basis states as follows:

Computer Simulation of Einstein-Podolsky. Podolsky-Rosen- Bohm Experiments with Photons.

EPR Paradox and Bell s Inequality

A No-Go Result on Common Cause Approaches via Hardy s Paradox

EPR Paradox and Bell Inequalities

Solving the Einstein Podolsky Rosen puzzle: The origin of non-locality in Aspect-type experiments

Is Entanglement Sufficient to Enable Quantum Speedup?

Take that, Bell s Inequality!

Collapse versus correlations, EPR, Bell Inequalities, Cloning

Another Assault on Local Realism

Singlet State Correlations

Testing Quantum Mechanics and Bell's Inequality with Astronomical Observations

Lecture 12c: The range of classical and quantum correlations

NON HILBERTIAN QUANTUM MECHANICS ON THE FINITE GALOIS FIELD

Probabilistic exact cloning and probabilistic no-signalling. Abstract

arxiv:quant-ph/ v2 21 Jun 2004

arxiv:quant-ph/ v1 14 Sep 1999

Has CHSH-inequality any relation to EPR-argument?

Locality and the Hardy theorem

Logical difficulty from combining counterfactuals in the GHZ-Bell theorems

A Bell Theorem Without Inequalities for Two Particles, Using Efficient Detectors. Daniel M. Greenberger City College of New York, New York, NY 10031

THE COMMON CAUSE PRINCIPLE AND THE EPR-BELL SCENARIO

ON ARTHUR FINE'S INTERPRETATION QUANTUM MECHANICS

EPR, Bell Inequalities, Cloning (continued);

The Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen thought experiment and Bell s theorem

INTRODUCTORY NOTES ON QUANTUM COMPUTATION

Quantum mechanics and reality

The Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen thought-experiment and Bell s theorem

Michael H. Shulman, 2006 (Revisited ) WHY QUANTUM MECHANICS IS NON-LOCAL?

arxiv: v2 [quant-ph] 22 Sep 2008

Bell tests in physical systems

Small probability space formulation of Bell s theorem

EPR correlations, Bell s theorem, and entanglement at a distance: the naive view of an experimentalist

Q8 Lecture. State of Quantum Mechanics EPR Paradox Bell s Thm. Physics 201: Lecture 1, Pg 1

Introduction to Bell s theorem: the theory that solidified quantum mechanics

Hardy s Paradox. Chapter Introduction

Is Howard s Separability Principle a sufficient condition for Outcome Independence?

Understanding Long-Distance Quantum Correlations

Violation of Bell Inequalities

Timeline: Bohm (1951) EPR (1935) CHSH (1969) Bell (1964) Theory. Freedman Clauser (1972) Aspect (1982) Weihs (1998) Weinland (2001) Zeilinger (2010)

Finite Automata, Random Fields, Quantum Fluctuations, and Bell Inequalities

arxiv:quant-ph/ v1 5 Sep 2002

arxiv:quant-ph/ v1 19 Jun 1996

Entanglement and Bell s Inequalities Edward Pei. Abstract

Bell s Theorem, Uncertainty, and Conditional Events

Super-Quantum, Non-Signaling Correlations Cannot Exist

Odd Things about Quantum Mechanics: Abandoning Determinism In Newtonian physics, Maxwell theory, Einstein's special or general relativity, if an initi

Holism and Non-separability Applied to Quantum Mechanics

Causality and Local Determinism versus Quantum Nonlocality.

On selective influences, marginal selectivity, and Bell/CHSH inequalities

A Superluminal communication solution based on Four-photon entanglement

Violation of local realism with freedom of choice

Inequalities for Dealing with Detector Inefficiencies in Greenberger-Horne-Zeilinger Type Experiments

arxiv:quant-ph/ v1 10 Jan 1997

No Fine Theorem for Macrorealism

Classical Bell s Inequalities. Vesselin C. Noninski

arxiv: v1 [quant-ph] 4 Jun 2018

A history of entanglement

SUPPLEMENTARY INFORMATION

PRESELECTED QUANTUM OPTICAL CORRELATIONS

arxiv: v1 [quant-ph] 1 May 2011

Testing Quantum Mechanics and bell s inequality with Observations of Causally Disconnected cosmological events Andrew Friedman

arxiv: v2 [quant-ph] 6 Aug 2007

Bohmian particle trajectories contradict quantum mechanics

arxiv: v2 [quant-ph] 21 Nov 2017

A Stronger Bell Argument for (Some Kind of) Parameter Dependence

arxiv: v4 [math-ph] 28 Aug 2013

Measurement Independence, Parameter Independence and Non-locality

Stochastic Processes

Quantum mysteries revisited again

The quantum world is not built up from correlations Found. Phys. 36, (2006).

J = L + S. to this ket and normalize it. In this way we get expressions for all the kets

Lecture 29 Relevant sections in text: 3.9

arxiv: v4 [quant-ph] 28 Feb 2018

A Reexamination on Bell s Theorem

A review on quantum teleportation based on: Teleporting an unknown quantum state via dual classical and Einstein- Podolsky-Rosen channels

Quantum Entanglement and Bell s Inequalities Zachary Evans, Joel Howard, Jahnavi Iyer, Ava Dong, and Maggie Han

nm are produced. When the condition for degenerate

Entanglement. arnoldzwicky.org. Presented by: Joseph Chapman. Created by: Gina Lorenz with adapted PHYS403 content from Paul Kwiat, Brad Christensen

Quantum Communication. Serge Massar Université Libre de Bruxelles

Quantum Optics and Quantum Information Laboratory Review

No Fine theorem for macroscopic realism

Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen correlations and Bell correlations in the simplest scenario

Contextuality and the Kochen-Specker Theorem. Interpretations of Quantum Mechanics

Quantum Measurement and Bell s Theorem

Super-Quantum, Non-Signaling Correlations Cannot Exist

10 Interpreting Quantum Mechanics

Analysis of Bell inequality violation in superconducting phase qubits

Transcription:

A. Fine, 2013 THE BELL THEOREM The Bell theorem is a demonstration that a plausible way of picturing (or modeling) how the results of measurements occur, when made precise, leads to definite relations between the statistics in different measurements (the "Bell inequalities"), relations that are violated for a certain class of quantum mechanical experiments. In the experiments an atomic source steadily decays and emits pairs of spin-1/2 particles (e.g., electrons) in the singlet state (so, the total spin is 0, and it is conserved). After emission, the electrons in a pair separate and move in opposite directions to distinct wings of the experimental apparatus for observation. In the wings there are instruments that can be set to measure the spin component of an electron along one of two directions in the plane perpendicular to the electron's line of motion. Bernard's Wing Amalie's Wing RUNS: A_B, A_B', A'_B, A'_B' Thus the experiment involves the measurement of four variables either A or A' (for one particle in a pair) and either B or B' (for the other particle in the same pair), corresponding to the four possible orientations for the measurement of spin. A particular spin measurement has two possible outcomes: the electron is either spinning clockwise ("up") or counterclockwise ("down") in the measured direction. We will record the "up" result with a "+1" and the "down" with a "-1". Under these conventions each of the four variables takes either +1 or -1 as a value. In four separate runs, on paired particles, we measure orientations A with B, then A with B' then A' with B, and finally A' with B'. The best tested experimental geometry corresponds to the situation where the relative angle between directions in the first three runs (A/B, A/B', and A'/B) is 135 o and the relative angle between the orientations in the last run (A'/B') is 45 o, as in the diagram below.

In a number of experiments of this type ( more accurately, in experiments involving photon polarization, which is formally similar to electron spin) the statistics predicted by the quantum theory have been very well-confirmed. (See Weihs et al 1998.) The statistics are these (Clauser and Horne 1974). P(A) = P(B) = P(A') = P(B') = 0.5 (1) P(AB) = P(AB') = P(A'B) = 1 2 sin2 ( 135o 2 P(A'B') = 1 2 sin2 ( 45o 2 ) = 0.4268 and (2i) ) = 0.0732 (2ii) (We write P(A) for Prob(A=+1) and P(AB) for Prob(A=+1 & B=+1), and similarly for the other variables.) Suppose that there were factors ("hidden variables") that determined the experimental outcomes, or more generally, their probability. Let "λ" range over the factors that determine the probability of a measurement outcome in each individual case. Thus if an emitted pair is characterized by a particular factor λ and we measure A ( or A') on one particle in the pair then λ (or its relevant component) determines the probability that the result of the A-measurement is +1; similarly λ would determine the probability for the outcome to be +1 if we measure B (or B') on the other particle in the pair. This understanding represents the probability for the (+1) measurement outcomes by "response" functions p(a, λ), p(b, λ), p(a', λ) and p(b', λ) taking values between 0 and 1, depending on the determining factor λ (LOCALITY).We will show that under certain plausible assumptions, such a representation is inconsistent with the data in (1) and (2). For that purpose, notice that if numbers p, q and r all lie between 0 and 1, then qr = pqr + (1-p)qr pr + (1-p)q = pr pq + q, Page 2

since multiplying by numbers between 0 and 1 may only decrease the value of the original. Thus the following inequality holds qr pr pq + q. Because averaging over the values of variables preserves sums, differences and order, it follows that qr pr pq + q (Basic Inequality) if p, q, and r are variables taking values between 0 and 1, and denotes the average (or expected) value of the enclosed variable(s). To connect this with the correlation experiment, we suppose that the observed probability for a measurement outcome in a run is simply the average (over all the hidden factors) of the probabilities for individual outcomes; that is, we assume P(A) = p(a, λ) (and similarly for P(B), P(B'), and P(A'). We also assume that the outcomes at λ are uncorrelated, so the probability p(ab, λ) at a factor λ for the pair of outcomes A = +1 and B = +1 is the product of the probabilities at λ for each outcome separately; that is p(ab, λ) = p(a, λ) p(b, λ). (FACTORIZABILITY) Then, as in the case of the individual outcomes, the probability for pairs is obtained by averaging over all the hidden factors; i.e., P(AB) = p(ab, λ) = p(a, λ) p(b, λ). (and similarly for the other pairs AB', A'B and A'B'.) If in the basic inequality we now set q = p(b, λ), r = p(b', λ) and p = p(a', λ) then, when we substitute the overall probabilities for the averages as above, we find that p(b, λ). p(b', λ) P(A'B') - P(A'B) + P(B). If we perform the same substitutions for the averages, but this time setting q = p(a, λ), r = p(b', λ), and p = p(b, λ) in the basic inequality, then (after transposing) we have that P(AB') + P(AB) - P(A) p(b, λ). p(b', λ). Combining these two inequalities yields P(AB) + P(AB') + P(A'B) - P(A'B') P(A) + P(B). Page 3 (Bell Inequality) From (2) the left hand side equals 1.207 and from (1) the right hand side equals 1, in violation of the inequality. Thus the supposition that there are factors determining the probabilities for measurement outcomes, as above, leads to the Bell inequality, which is inconsistent with the experimental data in (1) and (2). In addition to factorizability, which blocks any correlation between the probable outcomes at λ, the preceding demonstration involves "locality" assumptions about the measurement procedure. In representing the probabilities for measurement outcomes as functions of certain determining factors λ, we suppose that the probability for an outcome

of a measurement in one wing, say A, is not affected by which of the variables (B or B') is measured in the other wing. If there were correlations between the measurement performed in one wing and the probability for an outcome obtained in the other wing we should have to represent the probability that A=+1 at λ not by p(a, λ) but by p(a, λ, B) or p(a, λ, B'). In that case, however, the preceding argument would not go through. For similar reasons we have to assume that the factor λ that determines the outcomeprobabilities does not depend on the particular measurements being carried out in the wings ("Measurement Independence"). In the quantum mechanical experiment described above we can arrange things so as to be reasonably certain that the spin measurements of the particles in an emitted pair are spacelike-separated; i.e., that the systems are so far apart and the times of separate measurements on a pair are so close that no signals (or "influences") with speeds less than (or equal to) that of light can pass between them (Aspect et al 1982 and Weihs et al 1998). To insure measurement independence (sometimes called "freedom of choice") we also want the emission of a pair with a given λ to be spacelike-separated from the operations that set the measurements to be performed. This too has been accomplished (Scheid et al 2010). APPENDIX There is another relation implied by the preceding locality and factorizability assumptions, one that bounds the quantity [P(AB) + P(AB') + P(A'B) - P(A'B')] from below. We can derive it using an argument similar to the one above. So suppose, as above, that the numbers p, q and r all lie between 0 and 1. Then So, since 0 (1-p)(1-q)(1-r), (1-p)(1-q)(1-r) = (1-p)(1-r) - q(1-p)(1-r) = 1 - p - r + pr - q(1-p) + q(1-p)r 1 - p - r + pr - q + pq + qr. p + q + r 1 + pq + pr + qr. If we now set q = p(b, λ), r = p(b', λ) and p = p(a, λ), and take the average over all the factors λ, then we have that P(A) + P(B) + P(B') 1 + P(AB) + P(AB') + p(b, λ). p(b', λ) i.e., that Also, so P(A) + P(B) + P(B') - 1- P(AB) - P(AB') p(b, λ). p(b', λ). qr = pqr + (1-p)qr pq + (1-p)r = pq - pr + r, qr pq - pr + r. Page 4

Putting q = p(b, λ), r = p(b', λ) and p = p(a', λ), and averaging, produces p(b, λ). p(b', λ) P(A'B) - P(A'B') + P(B'). Putting together the inequalities involving p(b, λ). p(b', λ) yields or P(A) + P(B) + P(B') - 1- P(AB) - P(AB') P(A'B) - P(A'B') + P(B'), P(A) + P(B) - 1 P(AB) + P(AB') + P(A'B) - P(A'B'). (Bell Inequality) As with the first Bell inequality this one is violated in the spin-1/2 experiments as well. Consider the situation where the relative angle between directions in the first three runs (A/B, A/B', and A'/B) is 45 o and the relative angle between the orientations in the last run (A'/B') is 135 o, as in the diagram below. P(AB) = P(AB') = P(A'B) = 1 2 sin2 ( 45o 2 ) = 0.0732 P(A'B') = 1 2 sin2 ( 135o 2 ) =0.4268. Here, again, all the single probabilities are 1 2. The preceding Bell inequality then implies that 0 0.207! If we combine the two Bell inequalities, we obtain P(A) + P(B) - 1 P(AB) + P(AB') + P(A'B) - P(A'B') P(A) + P(B). Page 5

In the spin-1/2 case the single probabilities are all 1 2 and this reduces to 0 P(AB) + P(AB') + P(A'B) - P(A'B') 1. There are three more Bell inequalities, obtained from the above by first interchanging A with A', then B with B', and finally both A with A' and B with B' together. The system of all these inequalities taken together constitutes the necessary and sufficient conditions that a correlation experiment involving the four distinct orientations A, A', B and B' has a statistical model that determines the probabilities for measurement outcomes in accord with the twin requirements of locality and factorizability (Fine 1982). The failure of the quantum statistics to satisfy these inequalities shows that it is not possible to model the quantum probabilities in this way. Of course there may be other sorts of models. Moreover, when inefficiencies of actual experiments are taken into account some models of the sort discussed here also become possible. REFERENCES 1. Aspect, A., J. Dalibard, and G.Roger. 1982. Experimental test of Bell's inequalities using time-varying analyzers. Physical Review Letters 49: 1804-7. (Classic experiment that nearly rules out subluminal signals.) 2. Bell, J. S. 1987. Speakable and unspeakable in quantum mechanics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Good expositions, and complete references to Bell's work.) 3. Clauser, J. F. and M. A. Horne 1974. Experimental consequences of objective local theories. Physical Review D 10: 526-35. (Extends Bell's initial analysis to the stochastic case governed by the system of inequalities set out above.) 4. Fine, A. 1982. Hidden variables, joint probability and the Bell inequalities. Physical Review Letters 48: 291-95. (Establishes the probabilistic content of the Bell inequalities, and their sufficiency for a local, factorizable stochastic model.) 5. Scheid, T. et al, 2010. Violation of local realism with freedom of choice. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 107 (November 16, 2010): 19708-19713. (Test of Bell inequalities with measurement independence satisfied and subluminal signalling ruled out.) 5. Weihs, G. et al, 1998. Violation of Bell s inequality under strict Einstein locality conditions. Physical Review Letters 81: 5039-43. (Improves the protocol for ruling out subluminal signals.) Page 6