The Fundamental Welfare Theorems

Similar documents
The Fundamental Welfare Theorems

Pareto Efficiency (also called Pareto Optimality)

Adding Production to the Theory

Differentiable Welfare Theorems Existence of a Competitive Equilibrium: Preliminaries

Notes IV General Equilibrium and Welfare Properties

Economics 501B Final Exam Fall 2017 Solutions

The Debreu-Scarf Theorem: The Core Converges to the Walrasian Allocations

The Ohio State University Department of Economics. Homework Set Questions and Answers

Fundamental Theorems of Welfare Economics

Second Welfare Theorem

Economics 101 Lecture 5 - Firms and Production

Introduction to General Equilibrium

Competitive Equilibrium

EC487 Advanced Microeconomics, Part I: Lecture 5

Market Equilibrium and the Core

First Welfare Theorem

In the Name of God. Sharif University of Technology. Microeconomics 1. Graduate School of Management and Economics. Dr. S.

Lecture 2 The Centralized Economy

Microeconomic Theory -1- Introduction

Equilibrium and Pareto Efficiency in an exchange economy

Lecture 1. History of general equilibrium theory

The Consumer, the Firm, and an Economy

Nonlinear Programming and the Kuhn-Tucker Conditions

3. THE EXCHANGE ECONOMY

ECONOMICS 001 Microeconomic Theory Summer Mid-semester Exam 2. There are two questions. Answer both. Marks are given in parentheses.

1 General Equilibrium

General Equilibrium. General Equilibrium, Berardino. Cesi, MSc Tor Vergata

Microeconomics. Joana Pais. Fall Joana Pais

3.2 THE FUNDAMENTAL WELFARE THEOREMS

Advanced Microeconomics Problem Set 1

Welfare Economics: Lecture 12

4 Lecture Applications

Recitation #2 (August 31st, 2018)

; p. p y p y p y. Production Set: We have 2 constraints on production - demand for each factor of production must be less than its endowment

Core. Ichiro Obara. December 3, 2008 UCLA. Obara (UCLA) Core December 3, / 22

Seminars on Mathematics for Economics and Finance Topic 5: Optimization Kuhn-Tucker conditions for problems with inequality constraints 1

Economics 201b Spring 2010 Solutions to Problem Set 1 John Zhu

Question 1. (p p) (x(p, w ) x(p, w)) 0. with strict inequality if x(p, w) x(p, w ).

Week 7: The Consumer (Malinvaud, Chapter 2 and 4) / Consumer November Theory 1, 2015 (Jehle and 1 / Reny, 32

Economics 101. Lecture 2 - The Walrasian Model and Consumer Choice


Advanced Microeconomic Theory. Chapter 6: Partial and General Equilibrium

Microeconomics II. MOSEC, LUISS Guido Carli Problem Set n 3

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program May 2012

EconS Microeconomic Theory II Homework #9 - Answer key

Walrasian Equilibrium in an exchange economy

Department of Agricultural Economics. PhD Qualifier Examination. May 2009

Lecture Notes October 18, Reading assignment for this lecture: Syllabus, section I.

Nonlinear Programming (NLP)

Department of Economics The Ohio State University Final Exam Questions and Answers Econ 8712

Econ Slides from Lecture 14

Duality. for The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics, 2nd ed. Lawrence E. Blume

Competitive Equilibrium and the Welfare Theorems

ANSWERS TO ODD NUMBERED EXERCISES IN CHAPTER 3

Market Outcomes: Efficient or Fair?

Econ 401A: Economic Theory Mid-term. Answers

FINANCIAL OPTIMIZATION

The Envelope Theorem

5.1 THE ROBINSON CRUSOE ECONOMY

Notes on General Equilibrium

Mathematical Foundations -1- Constrained Optimization. Constrained Optimization. An intuitive approach 2. First Order Conditions (FOC) 7

Introductory Microeconomics

Introduction to General Equilibrium: Framework.

E 600 Chapter 4: Optimization

Notes I Classical Demand Theory: Review of Important Concepts

The Walrasian Model and Walrasian Equilibrium

Hicksian Demand and Expenditure Function Duality, Slutsky Equation

Firms and returns to scale -1- Firms and returns to scale

Utility Maximization Problem

The Kuhn-Tucker Problem

Recitation 2-09/01/2017 (Solution)

Existence, Computation, and Applications of Equilibrium

1 Second Welfare Theorem

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2016

Firms and returns to scale -1- John Riley

The general programming problem is the nonlinear programming problem where a given function is maximized subject to a set of inequality constraints.

(ii) An input requirement set for this technology is clearly not convex as it

Unlinked Allocations in an Exchange Economy with One Good and One Bad

Consider this problem. A person s utility function depends on consumption and leisure. Of his market time (the complement to leisure), h t

Notes on Consumer Theory

Lecture #3. General equilibrium

Increasingly, economists are asked not just to study or explain or interpret markets, but to design them.

Tutorial 3: Optimisation

Microeconomic Analysis

Public Economics Ben Heijdra Chapter 9: Introduction to Normative Public Economics

Final Examination with Answers: Economics 210A

Macroeconomic Theory and Analysis Suggested Solution for Midterm 1

ECON5110: Microeconomics

Lecture Notes for January 8, 2009; part 2

Properties of Walrasian Demand

Advanced Microeconomic Analysis, Lecture 6

1 Jan 28: Overview and Review of Equilibrium

Optimization. A first course on mathematics for economists

Week 6: Consumer Theory Part 1 (Jehle and Reny, Chapter 1)

Department of Economics The Ohio State University Midterm Answers Econ 805

Dynamic Macroeconomic Theory Notes. David L. Kelly. Department of Economics University of Miami Box Coral Gables, FL

Utility Maximization Problem. Advanced Microeconomic Theory 2

Problem Set 1 Welfare Economics

Lecture 7: General Equilibrium - Existence, Uniqueness, Stability

IE 5531: Engineering Optimization I

Transcription:

The Fundamental Welfare Theorems The so-called Fundamental Welfare Theorems of Economics tell us about the relation between market equilibrium and Pareto efficiency. The First Welfare Theorem: Every Walrasian equilibrium allocation is Pareto efficient. The Second Welfare Theorem: Every Pareto efficient allocation can be supported as a Walrasian equilibrium. The theorems are certainly not true in the unconditional form in which we ve stated them here. A better way to think of them is this: Under certain conditions, a market equilibrium is efficient and Under certain conditions, an efficient allocation can be supported as a market equilibrium. Nevertheless, these two theorems really are fundamental benchmarks in microeconomics. We re going to give conditions under which they re true. One (very stringent) set of conditions will enable us to prove the theorems with the calculus (Kuhn- Tucker, Lagrangian, gradient) methods we ve used very fruitfully in our analysis of Pareto efficiency. Additionally, for each theorem we ll provide a much weaker set of conditions under which the theorem remains true. Assume to begin with, then, that the consumers preferences are very nice viz., that they re representable by utility functions u i that satisfy the following condition: u i is continuously differentiable, strictly quasiconcave, and x i R l + : u i k(x i ) > 0 ( ) The First Welfare Theorem: If ( p, ( x i ) n 1) is a Walrasian equilibrium for an economy E = ((u i, x i )) n 1 that satisfies ( ), then ( xi ) n 1 is a Pareto allocation for E. Because ( p, ( x i ) n 1) is a Walrasian equilibrium for E, each x i maximizes u i subject to x i 0 and to the budget constraint p x i p x i. Therefore, for each i N there is a λ i 0 that satisfies the first-order marginal conditions for i s maximization problem: k : u i k λ i p k, with equality if x i k > 0, (1) where of course the partial derivatives u i k are evaluated at xi k. In fact, because each ui k > 0, we have λ i > 0 and p k > 0 for each i and each k. The market-clearing condition in the definition of Walrasian equilibrium therefore yields

x i k = x i k for each k (because each p k > 0). (2) For each i we can define λ i = 1, because λ i > 0, and then we can rewrite (1) as λ i k : λ iu i k p k, with equality if x i k > 0, (3) for each i N. But (2) and (3) are exactly the first-order conditions that characterize the solutions of the Pareto maximization problem (P-max). And since each u i k > 0, a solution of (P-max) is a Pareto allocation. In the proof, we could have instead expressed the first-order marginal conditions for the individual consumers maximization problems in terms of marginal rates of substitution: k, k : MRS i kk = p k p k (4) (written for the interior case, to avoid a lot of inequalities), which yields the (Equal MRS) condition i, j, k, k : MRSkk i = MRSj kk. (5) The conditions (5) and (2) characterize the Pareto allocations. Now let s see if we can prove the First Welfare Theorem without any of the assumptions in ( ). It turns out that we can t quite do that; however, the only thing we need to assume is that each u i is locally nonsatiated. The First Welfare Theorem: If ( p, ( x i ) n 1) is a Walrasian equilibrium for an economy E = ((u i, x i )) n 1 in which each ui is locally nonsatiated, then ( x i ) n 1 is a Pareto allocation for E. Suppose ( x i ) n 1 is not a Pareto allocation i.e., some allocation ( x i ) n 1 is a Pareto improvement on ( x i ) n 1: (a) n 1 xi n 1 xi (b1) i N : u i ( x i ) u i ( x i ) (b2) i N : u i ( x i ) > u i ( x i ). Because ( p, ( x i ) n 1) is a Walrasian equilibrium for E, each x i maximizes u i on the budget set B( p, x i ) := { x i R l + p x i p x i }. Therefore, (b2) implies that and since each u i is locally nonsatiated, (b1) implies that p x i p x i, (6) 2

p x i p x i for each i. (7) ((7) follows from a duality theorem that we ll state and prove momentarily.) Summing the inequalities in (6) and (7) yields i.e., p x i p p x i, (8) x i p Since p R l +, it follows from (9) that there is at least one k for which p k > 0 and x i. (9) x i k x i k. (10) Since p k > 0, the market-clearing equilibrium condition yields n xi k = n xi k, and (10) therefore yields n xi k n xi k. Therefore there are no Pareto improvements on ( xi ) n 1, and it s therefore a Pareto allocation. 3

The Second Welfare Theorem: Let ( x i ) n 1 be a Pareto allocation for an economy E in which the utility functions u 1,..., u n all satisfy ( ) and in which the total endowment of goods is x R l ++. Then there is a price-list p R l + such that for every ( x i ) n 1 that satisfies x i = x and i : p x i = p x i, (11) ( p, ( x i ) n ) 1 is a Walrasian equilibrium of the economy Ẽ = ((u i, x i )) n 1. i.e., ( p, ( x i ) n 1) is a Walrasian equilibrium of the economy in which each consumer has the utility function u i and the initial bundle x i. Let ( x i ) n 1 be a Pareto allocation for E. We first show that the conclusion holds for ( x i ) n 1 = ( x i ) n 1 i.e., if each consumer s initial bundle is x i. Since ( x i ) n 1 is a Pareto allocation, it is a solution of the Pareto maximization problem (P-max), and it therefore satisfies the first-order marginal conditions i, k : λ i, σ k 0 : λ i u i k σ k, with equality if x i k > 0. (12) Each λ i is the Lagrange multiplier for one of the utility-level constraints in (P-max), and since u i k > 0 for each i and each k, it s clear that each constraint s Lagrange multiplier must be positive: relaxing any one of the constraints will allow u 1 to be increased. For each k, let p k = σ k. Now (11) yields, for each i, λ i : k : u i k 1 λ i p k, with equality if x i k > 0. (13) These are exactly the first-order marginal conditions for consumer i s utility-maximization problem at the price-list p. Therefore, since each consumer s initial bundle is x i, each consumer is maximizing u i at x i ; moreover, the first equation in (11) ensures that all markets clear at ( x i ) n 1. Thus, we ve shown that all the conditions in the definition of Walrasian equilibrium are satisfied for ( p, ( x i ) n 1). If each consumer s initial bundle is x i instead of x i, then the first equation in (11) again ensures that markets clear, and the second equation in (11) implies that each consumer s budget constraint is the same for initial bundle x i as for initial bundle x i viz., n 1 p xi n 1 p xi = n 1 p xi and therefore x i maximizes u i subject to the budget constraint n 1 p xi n 1 p xi. Just as with the First Welfare Theorem, the Second Theorem is true under weaker assumptions than those in ( ) but in the case of the Second Theorem, not that much weaker: we can dispense with the differentiability assumption, and we can weaken the convexity assumption and the assumption that utility functions are strictly increasing. 4

The Second Welfare Theorem: Let ( x i ) n 1 be a Pareto allocation for an economy E in which each u i is continuous, quasiconcave, and locally nonsatiated. For each i, let x i = x i. Then there is a price-list p R l + such that for every ( x i ) n 1 that satisfies x i = x and i : p x i = p x i, (14) ( p, ( x i ) n ) 1 is a Walrasian equilibrium of the economy Ẽ = ((u i, x i )) n 1. The proof of the Second Theorem at this level of generality is not nearly as straightforward as the proof of the First Theorem. The proof requires a significant investment in the theory of convex sets, as well as some additional mathematical concepts. This is a case in which (for this course) the cost of developing the proof outweighs its value. 5