Since the two-sided limits exist, so do all one-sided limits. In particular:

Similar documents
5.1 Increasing and Decreasing Functions. A function f is decreasing on an interval I if and only if: for all x 1, x 2 I, x 1 < x 2 = f(x 1 ) > f(x 2 )

2.2 Graphs of Functions

5.6 Asymptotes; Checking Behavior at Infinity

1 Lecture 25: Extreme values

Homework for Section 1.4, Continuity and One sided Limits. Study 1.4, # 1 21, 27, 31, 37 41, 45 53, 61, 69, 87, 91, 93. Class Notes: Prof. G.

Induction, sequences, limits and continuity

O.K. But what if the chicken didn t have access to a teleporter.

Recitation 7: Existence Proofs and Mathematical Induction

2.3 Composite Functions. We have seen that the union of sets A and B is defined by:

V. Graph Sketching and Max-Min Problems

35. SOLVING ABSOLUTE VALUE EQUATIONS

Intermediate Value Theorem

1.10 Continuity Brian E. Veitch

Limits: An Intuitive Approach

(a) For an accumulation point a of S, the number l is the limit of f(x) as x approaches a, or lim x a f(x) = l, iff

1.4 Mathematical Equivalence

37. FINISHING UP ABSOLUTE VALUE INEQUALITIES

33. SOLVING LINEAR INEQUALITIES IN ONE VARIABLE

Calculus with Analytic Geometry I Exam 8 Take Home Part.

8. TRANSFORMING TOOL #1 (the Addition Property of Equality)

Mean Value Theorem. Increasing Functions Extreme Values of Functions Rolle s Theorem Mean Value Theorem FAQ. Index

1.1 The Language of Mathematics Expressions versus Sentences

Exam 3 MATH Calculus I

3.4 Using the First Derivative to Test Critical Numbers (4.3)

Polynomial functions right- and left-hand behavior (end behavior):

REVIEW FOR THIRD 3200 MIDTERM

Replacing the a in the definition of the derivative of the function f at a with a variable x, gives the derivative function f (x).

Section 4.2: The Mean Value Theorem

30. TRANSFORMING TOOL #1 (the Addition Property of Equality)

WEEK 8. CURVE SKETCHING. 1. Concavity

Written Assignment #1 - SOLUTIONS

2.4 The Precise Definition of a Limit

9. TRANSFORMING TOOL #2 (the Multiplication Property of Equality)

Lesson 3-1: Solving Linear Systems by Graphing

Section 3.1 Extreme Values

CH 2: Limits and Derivatives

Math 1120 Calculus, sections 3 and 10 Test 1

Consequences of Continuity and Differentiability

AP Calculus AB/IB Math SL2 Unit 1: Limits and Continuity. Name:

Applications of Differentiation

Test 3 Review. y f(a) = f (a)(x a) y = f (a)(x a) + f(a) L(x) = f (a)(x a) + f(a)

LECTURE 1. Logic and Proofs

Connectedness. Proposition 2.2. The following are equivalent for a topological space (X, T ).

Math Section Bekki George: 08/28/18. University of Houston. Bekki George (UH) Math /28/18 1 / 37

We are going to discuss what it means for a sequence to converge in three stages: First, we define what it means for a sequence to converge to zero

APPLICATIONS OF DIFFERENTIATION

Limits, Continuity, and the Derivative

1 What is numerical analysis and scientific computing?

Solutions to Math 41 First Exam October 18, 2012

The Derivative Function. Differentiation

The following techniques for methods of proofs are discussed in our text: - Vacuous proof - Trivial proof

Chapter 2: Functions, Limits and Continuity

9 Sequences of Functions

School of the Art Institute of Chicago. Calculus. Frank Timmes. flash.uchicago.edu/~fxt/class_pages/class_calc.

27. THESE SENTENCES CERTAINLY LOOK DIFFERENT

Topic 1: Propositional logic

4.1 Real-valued functions of a real variable

3.1 Graphs of Polynomials

WEEK 7 NOTES AND EXERCISES

Continuity, Intermediate Value Theorem (2.4)

Continuity. MATH 161 Calculus I. J. Robert Buchanan. Fall Department of Mathematics

Maximum and Minimum Values section 4.1

3 The language of proof

27. THESE SENTENCES CERTAINLY LOOK DIFFERENT

Properties of Sequences

Lesson 59 Rolle s Theorem and the Mean Value Theorem

Math 131 Exam 1 October 4, :00-9:00 p.m.

MATH 113: ELEMENTARY CALCULUS

DR.RUPNATHJI( DR.RUPAK NATH )

Undergraduate Notes in Mathematics. Arkansas Tech University Department of Mathematics

One-to-one functions and onto functions

2.1 Definition. Let n be a positive integer. An n-dimensional vector is an ordered list of n real numbers.

The Intermediate Value Theorem If a function f (x) is continuous in the closed interval [ a,b] then [ ]

Math 261 Calculus I. Test 1 Study Guide. Name. Decide whether the limit exists. If it exists, find its value. 1) lim x 1. f(x) 2) lim x -1/2 f(x)

Introduction to Topology

Math 4606, Summer 2004: Inductive sets, N, the Peano Axioms, Recursive Sequences Page 1 of 10

5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting

Jim Lambers MAT 460 Fall Semester Lecture 2 Notes

THS Step By Step Calculus Chapter 1

PART I Lecture Notes on Numerical Solution of Root Finding Problems MATH 435

Logic. Quantifiers. (real numbers understood). x [x is rotten in Denmark]. x<x+x 2 +1

Section 3.7. Rolle s Theorem and the Mean Value Theorem

SOLUTIONS TO ALL IN-SECTION and END-OF-SECTION EXERCISES

Maximum and Minimum Values (4.2)

Topic 2 Limits and Continuity c and d) Continuity Handout Notes Assigned Problems: Intro book pg 73, 1-3 and 6-8

Lecture 1: Period Three Implies Chaos

HOW TO CREATE A PROOF. Writing proofs is typically not a straightforward, algorithmic process such as calculating

Supplementary Material for MTH 299 Online Edition

Solving with Absolute Value

Final Examination 201-NYA-05 May 18, 2018

Families of Functions, Taylor Polynomials, l Hopital s

Math 341 Summer 2016 Midterm Exam 2 Solutions. 1. Complete the definitions of the following words or phrases:

Math 111, Introduction to the Calculus, Fall 2011 Midterm I Practice Exam 1 Solutions

Continuity. To handle complicated functions, particularly those for which we have a reasonable formula or formulas, we need a more precise definition.

MSM120 1M1 First year mathematics for civil engineers Revision notes 4

Calculus 1 Math 151 Week 10 Rob Rahm. Theorem 1.1. Rolle s Theorem. Let f be a function that satisfies the following three hypotheses:

INTERMEDIATE VALUE THEOREM

Logic and Mathematics:

Assignment 3 Logic and Reasoning KEY

ELEMENTARY NUMBER THEORY AND METHODS OF PROOF

Transcription:

SECTION 3.6 IN-SECTION EXERCISES: EXERCISE 1. The Intermediate Value Theorem 1. There are many correct graphs possible. A few are shown below. Since f is continuous on [a, b] and π is between f(a) = 3 and f(b) = 4, there MUST (by the Intermediate Value Theorem) be a number c (a, b) with f(c) = π. Such value(s) of c are shown on the graphs below.. If f is continuous on ( 5, 5), then for every c ( 5, 5), lim x c f(x) = f(c). In particular, when x is or : lim f(x) = f( ) and lim f(x) = f() x x Since the two-sided limits exist, so do all one-sided limits. In particular: lim x x f(x) = f( ) and lim f(x) = f() + Thus, f is continuous on [, ]. Indeed, if f is continuous on the interval (a, b), then it is continuous on any closed interval contained in (a, b). 3. Since f is continuous on [a, b], and 0 is a number between f(a) and f(b), the Intermediate Value Theorem guarantees existence of c (a, b) with f(c) = 0. 4. If f were continuous on [0, 1], then there would have to be a number c between 0 and 1 with f(c) =.5. Thus, f is NOT continuous on [0, 1]. EXERCISE. 64

copyright Dr. Carol JV Fisher Burns http://www.onemathematicalcat.org 65. 3. Exact solutions: x 4 8x = 15 x 4 8x + 15 = 0 (x ) 8(x ) + 15 = 0 (x 5)(x 3) = 0 (x 5)(x + 5)(x 3)(x + 3) = 0 x = ± 5 or x = ± 3 In Exercise 1, you were finding the solution x = 3. x = 5. In Exercise, you were finding the solution EXERCISE 3. First: x 3 x = 5x 5 x 3 x 5x + 5 = 0 Define f(x) := x 3 x 5x + 5. The tables of function values shown below help us to locate a solution:

66 copyright Dr. Carol JV Fisher Burns http://www.onemathematicalcat.org EXERCISE 4. 1. This is a bit of a trick question. Since we are told that f(a) = f(b) = D, take d = a or d = b. Then, f(d) = D.. There need not be any d (a, b) with f(d) = D, as the sketches below illustrate. EXERCISE 5. 1.. Let c < d. Then, the distance from c to d is d c. The number exactly halfway between c and d is: c + d c = c + d c = c + d c = c + d 3. There are really two cases to be considered: Case 1. f(a) = f(b) In this case, f(a) + f(b) = f(a) + f(a) and this value is taken on when x = a, or when x = b. Case. f(a) f(b) = f(a), In this case, the average value f(a)+f(b) is a number between f(a) and f(b), and the Intermediate Value Theorem says that there must exist d (a, b) with f(d) = f(a)+f(b). EXERCISE 6. The hypotheses of a theorem are the things that MUST be true, in order to use the theorem. That is, the conclusion of the theorem is only guaranteed to be true if the hypotheses are true. If the hypotheses are not true, the conclusion of the theorem may be true or may not be true; further investigation is required. The hypothesis of a (true) implication must be true to guarantee that the conclusion of the implication is true. That is, if A = B is a true sentence, this means that whenever the hypothesis A is true, then the conclusion B must also be true. If A isn t true, no information can be reached about B. Therefore, the words have very similar meanings in both contexts. EXERCISE 7. 1. TRUE. Whenever the sentence x = 3 is true, so is the sentence x = 9. Indeed, the hypothesis is only true when x is 3; and 3 = 9.

copyright Dr. Carol JV Fisher Burns http://www.onemathematicalcat.org 67. FALSE. Just because x is a number which, when squared, equals 9, we cannot conclude that x is 3. Here s a counterexample: Let x = 3. Then the hypothesis ( 3) = 9 is true, but the conclusion 3 = 3 is false. This is the only possible counterexample for this problem. 3. TRUE. Whenever x is equal to, the absolute value of x is also equal to. 4. FALSE. Just because x is a number whose distance from zero is, we cannot conclude that x is. Here s a counterexample: Let x =. Then the hypothesis = is true, but the conclusion = is false. This is the only possible counterexample for this problem. 5. You must think to yourself: whenever a is any number that lies to the left of b on the number line, are we guaranteed that a s distance from zero is less than b s distance from zero? Several sketches show that the answer is NO. That is, the sentence is FALSE. Here s a counterexample: Let a = 3 and b = 1. Then, the hypothesis 3 < 1 is true, but the conclusion 3 < 1 is false. There are an infinite number of counterexamples for this problem. Here s another: Let a = 4 and b = 3. Then, the hypothesis 4 < 3 is true, but the conclusion 4 < 3 is false. 6. TRUE. Whenever a and b are both positive numbers with a < b, then a s distance from 0 is less than b s distance from zero. EXERCISE 8. Keep in mind that we are assuming that the sentence A = B is TRUE. There are three lines of the truth table where this happens: 1. Nothing can be concluded about the truth value of A. It could be true (line 1) or false (lines 3 and 4).. Nothing can be concluded about the truth value of B. It could be true (lines 1 and 3) or false (line 4). 3. If A is true, then B must be true (line 1). 4. If B is true, nothing can be concluded about the truth value of A. A might be true (line 1) or false (line 3). 5. If A is false, nothing can be concluded about the truth value of B. B might be true (line 3) or false (line 4). 6. If B is false, then A must be false (line 4). For if A were true, then B would also have to be true! END-OF-SECTION EXERCISES: 1. TRUE. This is a statement of the Intermediate Value Theorem.. TRUE. This is an application of the Intermediate Value Theorem. 3. TRUE. Whenever the hypothesis of an implication is false, the implication itself is automatically true. (In this situation, the implication is said to be vacuously true.)

68 copyright Dr. Carol JV Fisher Burns http://www.onemathematicalcat.org 4. FALSE. Look at the truth table for A = B. There are two lines where B is false, line and line 4. Is the sentence false in both cases? No. Here s a counterexample: Let A be false and B be false. Then, the hypothesis B is false is true, but the conclusion the sentence A = B is false is false. 5. TRUE. Look at the truth table for A = B. There are two lines where B is true; line 1 and line 3. In both cases, the sentence A = B is true. That is, whenever the conclusion of an implication is true, the implication itself is true. 6. FALSE. Look at the truth table for A = B. There are two lines where A is true; line 1 and line. Is the sentence A = B true in both cases? No. Here s a counterexample: Let A be true and B be false. Then the hypothesis A is true is true, but the conclusion A = B is true is false. 7. TRUE. Whenever t is a number whose distance from 0 is 0, t itself must be zero. 8. FALSE. Just because t is a number whose distance from 0 is 1, we cannot conclude that t is 1. Here s a counterexample: Let t = 1. Then the hypothesis 1 = 1 is true, but the conclusion 1 = 1 is false. 9. TRUE. Whenever t is 1, it is also true that t is 1. 10. TRUE. Whenever t is 1, it is also true that t is 1.