Towards a Contemporary Ontology

Similar documents
Towards a Contemporary Ontology

Victoria Gitman and Thomas Johnstone. New York City College of Technology, CUNY

Introduction to Logic and Axiomatic Set Theory

A Dual Ontology of Nature, Life, and Person

Theory of Computation CS3102 Spring 2014

Part II Logic and Set Theory

Class 15: Hilbert and Gödel

Gödel in class. Achim Feldmeier Brno - Oct 2010

Logic in Computer Science. Frank Wolter

Axiomatic set theory. Chapter Why axiomatic set theory?

Propositional and Predicate Logic - XIII

This section will take the very naive point of view that a set is a collection of objects, the collection being regarded as a single object.

Lecture 14 Rosser s Theorem, the length of proofs, Robinson s Arithmetic, and Church s theorem. Michael Beeson

Truthmaker Maximalism defended again. Eduardo Barrio and Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereyra

185.A09 Advanced Mathematical Logic

The roots of computability theory. September 5, 2016

Handbook of Logic and Proof Techniques for Computer Science

How Philosophy Impacts on Mathematics

The Limit of Humanly Knowable Mathematical Truth

Automata Theory. Definition. Computational Complexity Theory. Computability Theory

Paradox Machines. Christian Skalka The University of Vermont

Model Theory MARIA MANZANO. University of Salamanca, Spain. Translated by RUY J. G. B. DE QUEIROZ

The Reflection Theorem

Philosophy of Mathematics Intuitionism

Gödel s Incompleteness Theorem. Overview. Computability and Logic

the logic of provability

GÖDEL S COMPLETENESS AND INCOMPLETENESS THEOREMS. Contents 1. Introduction Gödel s Completeness Theorem

Set Theory and the Foundation of Mathematics. June 19, 2018

MAGIC Set theory. lecture 1

LOGIC. Mathematics. Computer Science. Stanley N. Burris

An Intuitively Complete Analysis of Gödel s Incompleteness

NONSTANDARD MODELS AND KRIPKE S PROOF OF THE GÖDEL THEOREM

Review: Stephen G. Simpson (1999) Subsystems of Second-Order Arithmetic (Springer)

On some Metatheorems about FOL

Bootstrapping Mathematics

Model Theory in the Univalent Foundations

CHAPTER 11. Introduction to Intuitionistic Logic

Proseminar on Semantic Theory Fall 2013 Ling 720 Propositional Logic: Syntax and Natural Deduction 1

Cogito ergo sum non machina!

Gödel s Incompleteness Theorems by Sally Cockburn (2016)

Between proof theory and model theory Three traditions in logic: Syntactic (formal deduction)

Abstract and Variable Sets in Category Theory 1

Chapter 2: Introduction to Propositional Logic

Gödel s Incompleteness Theorems

What are the recursion theoretic properties of a set of axioms? Understanding a paper by William Craig Armando B. Matos

The Calculus of Inductive Constructions

Open access to the SEP is made possible by a world-wide funding initiative. Please Read How You Can Help Keep the Encyclopedia Free

Completeness Theorems and λ-calculus

Hilbert and the concept of axiom

2.2 Lowenheim-Skolem-Tarski theorems

KRIPKE S THEORY OF TRUTH 1. INTRODUCTION

MAGIC Set theory. lecture 2

Gödel s Theorem: Limits of logic and computation

Mathematical Logic. An Introduction

Gödel s Incompleteness Theorem. Overview. Computability and Logic

Marie Duží

Contradictions in mathematics

cse541 LOGIC FOR COMPUTER SCIENCE

Class 29 - November 3 Semantics for Predicate Logic

Basic Algebraic Logic

The Philosophy of Mathematics after Foundationalism

Lecture 9. Model theory. Consistency, independence, completeness, categoricity of axiom systems. Expanded with algebraic view.

DEFINITE DESCRIPTIONS: LANGUAGE, LOGIC, AND ELIMINATION

Peano Arithmetic. CSC 438F/2404F Notes (S. Cook) Fall, Goals Now

Church s undecidability result

Poincaré s Thesis CONTENTS. Peter Fekete

Proof Theory and Subsystems of Second-Order Arithmetic

O1 History of Mathematics Lecture XII 19th-century rigour in real analysis, part 2: real numbers and sets. Monday 13th November 2017 (Week 6)

Gödel s Proof. Henrik Jeldtoft Jensen Dept. of Mathematics Imperial College. Kurt Gödel

The problem of foundations - summary

Why is the Universe Described in Mathematics? This essay attempts to address the questions, "Why is the Universe described in

Lecture Notes for MATH Mathematical Logic 1

Krivine s Intuitionistic Proof of Classical Completeness (for countable languages)

Incompleteness Theorems, Large Cardinals, and Automata ov

Semantic methods in proof theory. Jeremy Avigad. Department of Philosophy. Carnegie Mellon University.

Truth, Subderivations and the Liar. Why Should I Care about the Liar Sentence? Uses of the Truth Concept - (i) Disquotation.

Supplement. Algebraic Closure of a Field

Philosophy of Mathematics Structuralism

A Little History Incompleteness The First Theorem The Second Theorem Implications. Gödel s Theorem. Anders O.F. Hendrickson

Russell s logicism. Jeff Speaks. September 26, 2007

INCOMPLETENESS I by Harvey M. Friedman Distinguished University Professor Mathematics, Philosophy, Computer Science Ohio State University Invitation

3.2. THE BASICS OF LOGIC

Set Theory. p p (COMP) Manuel Bremer Centre for Logic, Language and Information

Part II. Logic and Set Theory. Year

What is logic, the topic of this course? There are at least two answers to that question.

The Search for the Perfect Language

Gödel s Argument for Cantor s Cardinals Matthew W. Parker Centre for Philosophy of Natural and Social Science

INTRODUCTION TO CARDINAL NUMBERS

The Nuisance Principle in Infinite Settings

RESOLVING RUSSELL S PARADOX WITHIN CANTOR S INTUITIVE SET THEORY. Feng Xu ( Abstract

Philosophy of Set Theory

The Legacy of Hilbert, Gödel, Gentzen and Turing

Contents Propositional Logic: Proofs from Axioms and Inference Rules

There is No Standard Model of ZFC and ZFC 2

... The Sequel. a.k.a. Gödel's Girdle

Applied Logic. Lecture 1 - Propositional logic. Marcin Szczuka. Institute of Informatics, The University of Warsaw

Better Logic Through Algebra, Probability, and. Joseph W. Norman, M.D., Ph.D. University of Michigan, Ann Arbor

02 The Axiomatic Method

Informal Statement Calculus

Introduction to Metalogic

Transcription:

Towards a Contemporary Ontology The New Dual Paradigm in Natural Sciences: Part I Module 2 Class 3: The issue of the foundations of mathematics Course WI-FI-BASTI1 2014/15

Introduction Class 3: The issue of the foundations of mathematics from Riemann to Gödel and the Hilbert second problem 3

Course modules Modules Topic Suggested Readings SECTION ONE 0. Introduction and Course Overview 1. The Birth of Modern Science Refs.: 1, chs. 0, 1, 2. 2. The Question of Truth in Modern Science Refs.: 1, chs. 3, 4. SECTION TWO 3. The Information Theoretic Interpretation of QM Refs.: 4-10. 4. QFT interpretation as Second Quantization and the Physics of the Condensed Matter Refs.: 11, pp. vi-xii, 1-35, 137-178; 12; 13. SECTION THREE 5. The (Co)Algebraic Interpretation of QFT as q-deformed Hopf Refs.: 11, pp. 131-185; 14. Algebra / Coalgebra 6. The DDF Principle of QFT, its Cosmological Relevance and Refs.: 14-19; 1, ch. 5. Its Ontological Interpretation SECTION FOUR 7. Universal Coalgebra and the Interpretation of QFT Systems Refs.: 16; 20 as STS 8. Conclusions 4

Main Contents of the Module 2 This module 2 is mainly concerned with the problem of truth and/or the problem of foundation in pure and applied modern mathematical sciences. A problem emerging from the discovery of the hypotetical nature of mathematics, from which the, necessity derives of proving the consistency of mathematics geometries and arithmetics, before all given that the validity of the demonstrations is no longer granted by the soundness of the axioms. A particular subset of this more general problem concerns the soundness of the mathematical laws of physics. The four classes of this module concern: 1. The Greek origins of the Western science. 2. The issue of the V postulate of Euclidean geometry in the history of Western mathematics 3. The issue of the foundations of mathematics from Riemann to Gödel and the Hilbert second problem 4. The issue of the Skolem paradox and the relativity principle in the algebraic interpretation of set theory 5

Bibliography Bibliography of the Class 3 of the Module 2

Bibliography Main References for this Module 1. G. Basti, Philosophy of Nature and of Science. Volume I: The Foundations, transl. by Philip Larrey, Rome 2012 (for student use only), ch. 0,1,2, 3 [attached]. 2. C. B. Boyer, A history of mathematics, J. Wiley & Sons, New York, 1968 (available online at: https://archive.org/details/ahistoryofmathematics (Second Edition, ed. by U. C. Merzbach, J. Wiley & Sons, New York, 1991). Other Reference: E. Nagel, J. R. Newmann, Gödel s proof. Revised edition, Ed. by D. R. Hofstadter, New York UP, New York, 2001 (1958 First edition available online at the Internet Archive of the University of Florida: https://archive.org/details/gdelsproof00nage ). M. Hallett, Cantorian set theory and limitation of size, Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1984. 7

Class 3 The issue of the foundations of mathematics from Riemann to Gödel and the Hilbert second problem

The problem of the existence of infinite mathematical objects The abandon of the naive supposition of the absolute truth of mathematical objects typical of the early modern interpretation of calculus problem of the proof of the existence (soundness) of the mathematical objects, even the infinite ones of calculus, through a proper meta-mathematical theory. The core notion of a metalanguage even though the distinction language/metalanguage in mathematics is due to the successive work of Hilbert is identified in the notion of set (Menge), starting from the essential works on the calculus foundations, and on the convergent series of real valued functions of Karl Weierstrass (1815-1897) (Weierstrass theorem, Bolzano-Weierstrass theorem, Stone-Weierstrass theorem, etc.). The core problem of the calculus foundations as to the existence of infinite objects (infinite sets, or sets with the cardinality of the universal class V) in mathematics is perfectly synthesized in this quotation of Georg Cantor (1845-1918): 9

The problem of actual infinity in mathematics Quotation starts: «Undoubtedly, we cannot avoid the existence of variable quantities in the sense of potential infinity; from this, one can demonstrate the necessity of actual infinity. For a variable quantity to exist in a mathematical theory, the «domain» of its variability must be known in advance, through a definition. However, this domain must not be, in turn, something variable, otherwise we lose any sound basis for the study of mathematics. Therefore, this domain is a defined, actually infinite set of values» Quotation ends (Cantor 1886, 9). Cantor attempt of a constructive «piecewise» foundation of infinite sets, even the continuum itself, through its powerful Cantor theorem discovery of the antinomies as to the constructive demonstration of existence of the universal set (in the realm of cardinal numbers), and/or of the maximal set (in the realm of ordinal numbers) by the Burali-Forti antinomy abandon of Cantor s set theory for different axiomatic set theories (ZF, ZFC, NGB, NF, NFU ), all characterized by the introduction of axioms for limiting the size of costructive sets, so to transform the antinomies into as many paradoxes (Hallett, 1984). 10

Russell s antinomy and the logical character of antinomies Logicist interpretation of foundations of mathematics through G. Frege (1848-1925) attempt of avoiding the antinomies by the foundation of number not on the notion of set, but on the notion of class (class of classes), by using his generalized abstraction principle («each property (predicate) determines the domain of the elements that satisfy it (it determines predicate extension ))» that in its axiomatic version (axiom of comprehension) by Russell reads: x y( x y ϕx) The discovery of Russell s antinomy reveals the logical character of antinomies, as well its syntactic and not semantic nature (like in the classical version of logical antinomies, e.g., the famous «liar s antinomy» well known since the disputes of Plato and Aristotle with the Sophist philosophers), as far as based on the notions of membership and of inclusion common also to the notion of set solution of the antinomy by B. Russell s (1872-1970) theory of types in the Principia, and later by W.V.O. Quine (1908-2000) New Foundations (NF) theory with the stratified character of membership predication. The syntactic nature of antinomies was definitively made clear by Gödel incompleteness theorems and of their extensions in computability theory as unavoidable limitation theorems of any formalized language, also because they definitively shelved Hilbert s formalistic program on foundations. 11

Hilbert s formalist program for the problem of foundations Just as the main contribution of G. Frege was not its logistic program for the problem of foundations, but the development of the formalism of the mathematical logic, based on the extension of the mathematical notion of function to logic by the notion of propostional function, formally unifying the classical sentential and predicate logic, and making of him the most influential logician in the history of Western thought, after Aristotle and Leibniz, and before Gödel, So, the main contribution of the formalist program of D. Hilbert (1862-1943) was not for the solution of the foundatons problem, but for its rigorous definition of modern axiomatic method in the scientfic enquiry. Hilbert s choice consisted thus in separating the logical-formal procedures of demonstration and inference (= syntax, logical calculus as symbol manipulation by rules) from the proof of their consistency and truth (= semantic, meta-logic justification and/or interpretation of a calculus) implicit recovering on a rigorous formal basis: 1. The Scholastic theory of suppositio (reference) of given terms/predicates, with the distinction between: Suppositio materialis or grammatical self-reference of any well-formed, i.e., unambiguous, logical symbol; Suppositio formalis or reference of logical symbols and/or predicative sentences, either intra-linguistic (logic) or extralinguistic (ontology); 2. The Scholastic distinction between logica minor (calculus) and logica maior (symbol constitution) without the ambiguities between logic and epistemology that such distinctions had in the modern transcendental philosophy of logic. 12

Hilbert s axiomatization of geometry and its systematic use of a recursive method of proof After his early study on algebraic invariants, in which he had demonstrated the potential of a recursive (finite) method of proof, one of the first and more fundamental results of Hilbert s work was the famous demonstration of the calculus of distances, which constituted the core of Hilbert s treatise on the Foundations of Geometry (1898-99). This work aimed at demonstrating the independence of pure geometry from numbers, by showing that all (Euclidean) plane geometry can be represented as a particular, abstract algebraic structure: the commutative field. Therefore, the core of Hilbert s results on the foundations of the Euclidean geometry in this similar to Riemann s result for non-euclidea geometry was the demonstration that analytical geometry does not need to presume the existence of numbers in order to justify the use of algebra. 13

The core of Hilbert s formalistic interpretation as to Frege s logicistic one In an epistolary exchange with Frege (Webb 1980, 87) it is summarized the deep difference between the two, Frege s and Hilbert s foundational approaches: Frege: «Are there ways, perhaps, to demonstrate the consistency other than to exhibit an object that possesses all the properties? Anyway, if one has such an object at their disposal, one has no need to demonstrate its existence through the circular demonstration of its consistency» (i.e., existence and truth consistency). Hilbert: «This procedure of construction of an axiom by referring to its truth, and concluding from this that it is compatible with other defined concepts, is precisely the primary source of mistakes and confusion. If the arbitrarily established axioms do not contradict one another, then they are true, and the objects defined through them exist. For me, this is the one criterion of truth and existence» (i.e., consistency truth and existence). Hilbert s demonstration of the isomorphism between Euclidean geometric structures/ /relations, and algebraic structures/relations (fields) defined on real numbers was aimed: Not at the semantic goal of Riemann s demostration of the relative consistency of non-euclidean geometries by their Euclidean modeling, based on the intuitive truth of the Euclidean statements, But at the syntactic task of demonstrating the relative consistency of geometries as to the consistency of algebraic structures of arithmetics as defined on sets of real numbers. 14

From Hilbert s formalistic program to Gödel incompleteness theorem Hilbert s result centrality of the foundations of arithmetics for proving the consistency of modern mathematics despite the hypothetical character of its demonstration 2 Hilbert problem (of his famous list of 23 problems): «prove that the axioms of arithmetics are consistent», where the axioms of arithemtics are the Peano axioms in the Principia Mathematica (PM) formal language. The solution consists in the possibility of proving the absolute consistency of arithmetics by a finite procedure, i.e. by proving the consistency of formalized arithmetics from within arithmetics, in a similar way to which in Principia Mathematica (PM) it was possible to give an absolute consistency proof of the calculus of propositions from within it. The main difference is that, while the consistency of sentential calculus does not require any proof of its completeness, such a proof is a necessary condition in the case of arithmetics because it is a (first order) theory on numbers and not only a calculus necessity of proving its completeness: all the true proposistions in it must be proved as formally derived from its axioms. 15

Gödel incompleteness theorems and the two intermediate steps toward this historical result 1. The first step of such a formalistic Hilbert program was performed by K. Gödel by his demonstration of the completeness of first order predicate calculus (1929). 2. The second step is genious Gödel arithmetization of any formal language (Gödel coding) by using the theory of primes for assigning a univocal numerical value to whichever formula of a formalized language (= Gödel numbering). Two Gödel incompleteness theorems: 1. Any effectively generated theory capable of expressing elementary arithmetics in its Peano s formalization (PA), cannot be both consistent and complete. In particular, for any consistent, effectively generated formal theory that proves certain basic arithmetic truths, there is an arithmetical statement that is true, but not provable in the theory (Kleene 1967, p. 250) 2. For any formal effectively generated theory T including basic arithmetical truths and also certain truths about formal provability, if T includes a statement of its own consistency, then T is inconsistent. Because of the universal applicability of Gödel coding to whichever formalized language/theory Gödel theorems can be interpreted as universal limitation theorems for any formalized language/theory (i.e., any interpretation of the first order predicate calculus) fundamental limitation theorems of Tarski, Skolem and Turing. 16