A SEQUENT SYSTEM OF THE LOGIC R FOR ROSSER SENTENCES 2. Abstract

Similar documents
Two constructions of non-equivalent modal formulas 1

cse371/mat371 LOGIC Professor Anita Wasilewska Fall 2018

A generalization of modal definability

A simplified proof of arithmetical completeness theorem for provability logic GLP

On the Craig interpolation and the fixed point

An Introduction to Modal Logic III

The Modal Logic of Pure Provability

The Importance of Being Formal. Martin Henz. February 5, Propositional Logic

Propositional Logics and their Algebraic Equivalents

CHAPTER 11. Introduction to Intuitionistic Logic

1. Propositional Calculus

CHAPTER 10. Gentzen Style Proof Systems for Classical Logic

On the Complexity of the Reflected Logic of Proofs

KRIPKE S THEORY OF TRUTH 1. INTRODUCTION

Equivalents of Mingle and Positive Paradox

Propositional Logic: Models and Proofs

Lecture 2. Logic Compound Statements Conditional Statements Valid & Invalid Arguments Digital Logic Circuits. Reading (Epp s textbook)

Modal and temporal logic

Hypersequent Calculi for some Intermediate Logics with Bounded Kripke Models

On Modal Logics of Partial Recursive Functions

1. Propositional Calculus

Filtrations and Basic Proof Theory Notes for Lecture 5

Proof Theoretical Studies on Semilattice Relevant Logics

TR : Binding Modalities

Propositional logic (revision) & semantic entailment. p. 1/34

Canonical Calculi: Invertibility, Axiom expansion and (Non)-determinism

Chapter 11: Automated Proof Systems

Interpretability Logic

A NEW VERSION OF AN OLD MODAL INCOMPLETENESS THEOREM

Introduction to Metalogic

Propositional and Predicate Logic - V

Applied Logic. Lecture 1 - Propositional logic. Marcin Szczuka. Institute of Informatics, The University of Warsaw

RELATIONS BETWEEN PARACONSISTENT LOGIC AND MANY-VALUED LOGIC

On Modal Systems with Rosser Modalities

A CUT-FREE SIMPLE SEQUENT CALCULUS FOR MODAL LOGIC S5

Propositional and Predicate Logic - VII

Existential definability of modal frame classes

On Sequent Calculi for Intuitionistic Propositional Logic

Sequent calculi of quantum logic with strict implication

Deductive Systems. Lecture - 3

Positive provability logic

Propositional and Predicate Logic - II

Natural Deduction. Formal Methods in Verification of Computer Systems Jeremy Johnson

An Independence Relation for Sets of Secrets

Proving Completeness for Nested Sequent Calculi 1

Neighborhood Semantics for Modal Logic Lecture 3

Informal Statement Calculus

Axiomatizing hybrid logic using modal logic

Propositional Logic Language

BETWEEN THE LOGIC OF PARMENIDES AND THE LOGIC OF LIAR

The Logic of Proofs, Semantically

CSE 1400 Applied Discrete Mathematics Definitions

Chapter 4: Classical Propositional Semantics

Modal Logic of Forcing Classes

Handbook of Logic and Proof Techniques for Computer Science

Learning Goals of CS245 Logic and Computation

Propositional Dynamic Logic

Cut-free Ordinary Sequent Calculi for Logics Having Generalized Finite-Valued Semantics

CSC Discrete Math I, Spring Propositional Logic

Propositional Logic. CS 3234: Logic and Formal Systems. Martin Henz and Aquinas Hobor. August 26, Generated on Tuesday 31 August, 2010, 16:54

Packet #1: Logic & Proofs. Applied Discrete Mathematics

An Introduction to Proof Theory

3. Only sequences that were formed by using finitely many applications of rules 1 and 2, are propositional formulas.

Natural Deduction for Propositional Logic

Chapter 11: Automated Proof Systems (1)

02 Propositional Logic

A SIMPLE AXIOMATIZATION OF LUKASIEWICZ S MODAL LOGIC

Tableau-based decision procedures for the logics of subinterval structures over dense orderings

Extensions of Analytic Pure Sequent Calculi with Modal Operators

AI Principles, Semester 2, Week 2, Lecture 5 Propositional Logic and Predicate Logic

Partially commutative linear logic: sequent calculus and phase semantics

A MODAL EXTENSION OF FIRST ORDER CLASSICAL LOGIC Part I

From Frame Properties to Hypersequent Rules in Modal Logics

Abstract In this paper, we introduce the logic of a control action S4F and the logic of a continuous control action S4C on the state space of a dynami

S4LP and Local Realizability

Přednáška 12. Důkazové kalkuly Kalkul Hilbertova typu. 11/29/2006 Hilbertův kalkul 1

2. The Logic of Compound Statements Summary. Aaron Tan August 2017

A Note on Graded Modal Logic

On Constructive Linear-Time Temporal Logic

Kazimierz SWIRYDOWICZ UPPER PART OF THE LATTICE OF EXTENSIONS OF THE POSITIVE RELEVANT LOGIC R +

Formal Epistemology: Lecture Notes. Horacio Arló-Costa Carnegie Mellon University

Graph Theory and Modal Logic

Marie Duží

Axiomatizing hybrid logic using modal logic

MONADIC FRAGMENTS OF INTUITIONISTIC CONTROL LOGIC

On Urquhart s C Logic

Cut-elimination for Provability Logic GL

Proofs. Joe Patten August 10, 2018

Mathematical Logic. An Introduction

The logic of subset spaces, topologic and the local difference modality K

HENNESSY MILNER THEOREM FOR INTERPRETABILITY LOGIC. Abstract

Equivalence for the G 3-stable models semantics

Some consequences of compactness in Lukasiewicz Predicate Logic

Computation and Logic Definitions

5-valued Non-deterministic Semantics for The Basic Paraconsistent Logic mci

Boolean bunched logic: its semantics and completeness

Propositional Logic: Syntax

Review CHAPTER. 2.1 Definitions in Chapter Sample Exam Questions. 2.1 Set; Element; Member; Universal Set Partition. 2.

Automated Support for the Investigation of Paraconsistent and Other Logics

Modal Logic XX. Yanjing Wang

Transcription:

Bulletin of the Section of Logic Volume 33/1 (2004), pp. 11 21 Katsumi Sasaki 1 Shigeo Ohama A SEQUENT SYSTEM OF THE LOGIC R FOR ROSSER SENTENCES 2 Abstract To discuss Rosser sentences, Guaspari and Solovay [2] enriched the modal language by adding, for each A and B, the formulas A B and A B, with their arithmetic realizations the Σ 1 -sentences A is provable by a proof that is smaller than any proof of B, and A is provable by a proof that is smaller than or equal to any proof of B. They axiomatized modal logics R, R and R ω, each of which satisfies a kind of arithmetic completeness theorem concerning the above interpretation. Among these three logics, R is the most preliminary one and provability of the other logics can be described by the provability of R. Here we introduce a sequent system for R with a kind of subformula property. 1. The logic R In this section, we introduce the logic R. We use logical constant (contradiction), and logical connectives (conjunction), (disjunction), (implication), (provability), (witness comparison), and (witness comparison). Formulas are defined inductively as follows: 1 The first author was supported by Nanzan University Pache Research Subsidy I-A-2 2 An early version of the paper was presented at the 36th meeting on Mathematical Logic at Kinosaki, Japan, in December, 2002.

12 Katsumi Sasaki and Shigeo Ohama (1) propositional variables and are formulas, (2) if A and B are formulas, then so are (A B), (A B), (A B), ( A), ( A B) and ( A B). A formula of the form A is said to be a -formula. Also a formula of the form A B ( A B) is said to be a -formula ( -formula). By Σ, we mean the set of all -formulas, all -formulas and all -formulas. The modal system R is defined by the following axioms and inference rules. Axioms of R A1 : all tautologies, A2 : (A B) ( A B), A3 : ( A A) A, A4 : A A, where A Σ, A5 : ( A B) A, A6 : (( A B) ( B C)) ( A C), A7 : ( A B) (( A B) ( B A)), A8 : ( A B) ( A B), A9 : (( A B) ( B A)), Inference rules of R MP : A, A B R implies B R, N : A R implies A R. In [2] and Smoriński [4], the following two formulas are also axioms of R, but they are redundant (cf. De Jongh [3] and Voorbraak [5]). A10 : A ( A A), A11 : ( A ( B )) ( A B). We introduce Kripke semantics for R, following [4]. 3 Definition 1.1. A Kripke pseudo-model for R is a triple W, <, = where (1) W is a non-empty finite set, (2) < is an irreflexive and transitive binary relation on W satisfying α < γ and β < γ imply either one of α = β, α < β or β < α, (3) = is a valuation satisfying, in addition to the usual boolean laws, α = A if and only if for any β α (= {γ α < γ}), β = A. 3 [4] uses a rooted frame, but our frame does not necessarily be rooted.

A Sequent System of the Logic R for Rosser Sentences 13 Definition 1.2. A Kripke pseudo-model W, <, = for R is said to be a Kripke model for R if the following conditions hold, for any formula D, (1) if D Σ and α = D, then for any β α, β = D, (2) if D is either one of the axioms A5, A6, A7, A8 and A9, then α = D. Lemma 1.3 (2). for R. A R if and only if A is valid in any Kripke model 2. A sequent system for R In this section we introduce a sequent system GR for R. We use Greek letters, Γ and, possibly with suffixes, for finite sets of formulas. The expression Γ denotes the set { A A Γ}. By a sequent, we mean the expression Γ. For brevity s sake, we write instead of A 1,, A k, Γ 1,, Γ l 1,, m, B 1,, B n {A 1,, A k } Γ 1 Γ l 1 m {B 1,, B n }. By Sub(A), we mean the set of subformulas of A. We put Sub + (A) = Sub(A) { B C B, C Sub(A)} Sub(Γ ) = { B C B, C Sub(A)}, B Γ Sub(B), Sub + (Γ ) = B Γ Sub + (B). The system GR is obtained from the sequent system LK for classical propositional logic by adding the following axioms and inference rules in the usual way. Additional axioms of GR GA1: A B, B C A C GA2: A A B, B A GA3: B A B, B A GA4: A B A B GA5: A B, B A

14 Katsumi Sasaki and Shigeo Ohama Additional inference rules of GR A, Σ f, Γ A A, Σ f ( ), Γ A Γ A B, Γ ( ) Γ, A Γ, A A ( ) where Σ f is a finite subset of Σ. The system GR 1 is the system obtained from GR by restricting a cut to the following form: Γ, A B A B, Γ Γ where {, }, and A and B are subformulas of a formula occurring in the lower sequent. Theorem 2.1. The following conditions are equivalent: (1) A 1,, A m B 1,, B n GR 1, (2) A 1,, A m B 1,, B n GR, (3) A 1 A m B 1 B n R, (4) A 1 A m B 1 B n is valid in any Kripke model for R. (1) implies (2) is clear. From Lemma 1.3, it follows that (3) implies (4). (2) implies (3) is shown by checking the corresponding formula of each axiom in GR is provable in R and each inference rule in GR preserves the provability of R. The former can be easily seen and the latter can be shown in the usual way. To prove (4) implies (1), we need some preparations. Definition 2.2. A sequent Γ is said to be saturated if the following conditions hold: (1) if A B Γ, then A, B Γ, (2) if A B, then A or B, (3) if A B Γ, then A Γ or B Γ, (4) if A B, then A, B, (5) if A B Γ, then A or B Γ, (6) if A B, then A Γ and B, (7) if A B Γ, then A Γ, (8) if A A, then A, (9) if A, B Sub(Γ ), then A B, A B Γ.

A Sequent System of the Logic R for Rosser Sentences 15 Lemma 2.3. If Γ GR 1, then there exists a sequent Γ satisfying the following three conditions: (1) Γ GR 1, (2) Γ is saturated, (3) Γ Γ Sub + (Γ ) and Sub + (Γ ). Proof. Since Sub + (Γ ) is finite, there exist formulas A 0, A 1,, A n 1 such that Sub + (Γ ) = {A 0, A 1,, A n 1 }. We define a sequence of sequents (Γ 0 0 ), (Γ 1 1 ),, (Γ k k ), inductively as follows. Step 0: (Γ 0 0 ) = (Γ ). Step k + 1: If A k mod n = B C, then S 1 if S 1 GR 1 and B C (Γ (Γ k+1 k+1 ) = k k, B B, B) if S 1 GR 1 and B = C ( B, B C, Γ k k ) if S 1 GR 1 and S 2 GR 1 (Γ k k ) otherwise where S 1 = (Γ k k, B C) and S 2 = ( B C, Γ k k ). If A k mod n = B C, then S 1 if S 1 GR 1 (Γ k+1 k+1 ) = S 2 if S 1 GR 1 and S 2 GR 1 (Γ k k ) otherwise where S 1 = (Γ k k, B C) and S 2 = ( B C, Γ k k ). If A k mod n is a -formula, then (Γ k+1 k+1 ) = (Γ k k ). In the other cases, (Γ k+1 k+1 ) is defined in the usual way. Also in the usual way, we can prove that i=1 Γ i i=1 i is a sequent and satisfies the conditions (1),(2) and (3). Definition 2.4. For Γ GR 1, we fix a sequent satisfying the three conditions in the above lemma and call it a saturation of Γ, write sat(γ ). For Γ GR 1, we put sat(γ ) = (Γ ).

16 Katsumi Sasaki and Shigeo Ohama A sequence of formulas is defined as follows: (1) [ ] is a sequence of formulas, (2) if [A 1,, A n ] is a sequence of formulas, then so is [A 1,, A n, B]. A binary operator is defined by [A 1,, A m ] [B 1,, B n ] = [A 1,, A m, B 1,, B n ]. We use τ and σ, possibly with suffixes, for sequences of formulas. Definition 2.5. Let S 0 be a sequent, which is not provable in GR 1. We define the set W(S 0 ) of pairs of a sequent and a sequence of formulas as follows: (1) (sat(s 0 ); [ ]) W(S 0 ), (2) if a pair (Γ, A; τ) belongs to W(S 0 ), then so does the pair (sat( A, {D D Γ}, Γ Σ A); τ [ A]). Lemma 2.6. Let S 0 be a sequent, which is not provable in GR 1 (S; τ) be a pair in W(S 0 ). Then (1) S GR 1, (2) S consists of only formulas in Sub + (S 0 ), (3) τ consists of only -formulas in Sub(S 0 ). and let Proof. We use an induction on (S; τ) as an element in W(S 0 ). If (S; τ) = (sat(s 0 ); [ ]), then the lemma is clear. Suppose that (S; τ) (sat(s 0 ); [ ]). Then by Definition 2.5, there exists a pair (Γ, A; σ) W(S 0 ) such that (S; τ) = (sat( A, {D D Γ}, Γ Σ A); σ [ A]) for some σ. By the induction hypothesis, we have the following three: (4) Γ, A GR 1, (5) Γ, A consists only formulas in Sub + (S 0 ) (6) σ consists of only -formulas in Sub(S 0 ). From (5) and (6), we obtain (3). By Definition 2.4 and (5), we have (2). Also by (4), we have Γ Σ A GR 1. Using ( ), we have A, {D D Γ}, Γ Σ A GR 1, and neither is its saturation S. We have (1). Lemma 2.7. Let S 0 be a sequent, which is not provable in GR 1. Then (1) S 1 = S 2 for any (S 1 ; τ), (S 2 ; τ) W(S 0 ), (2) (Γ 1 1 ; τ), (Γ 2 2 ; τ σ) W(S 0 ) implies Γ 1 Σ Γ 2,

A Sequent System of the Logic R for Rosser Sentences 17 (3) if there exists a -formula in the antecedent of sat(s 0 ), then Sub + (S 0 ) Σ = Sub + (S) Σ, for any (S; τ) W(S 0 ), (4) (Γ ; τ σ) W(S 0 ) implies (Γ 1 1 ; τ) W(S 0 ) for some Γ 1 1, (5) (Γ ; τ [ A] σ) W(S 0 ) implies A Γ, (6) (S; τ 1 [ A] τ 2 [ A] τ 3 ) W(S 0 ), for any A and S, (7) W(S 0 ) is finite. Proof. For (1). By an induction on τ. For (2). We use an induction on σ. If σ = [ ], then by (1), we have Γ 1 = Γ 2. Suppose that σ = σ [ A]. Then by Definition 2.5, there exists (Γ 3 3, A; τ σ ) W(S 0 ) such that (Γ 2 2 ) = sat( A, {D D Γ 3 }, Γ 3 Σ A). By the induction hypothesis, Γ 1 Σ Γ 3. Using Definition 2.4, Γ 1 Σ Γ 3 Σ Γ 2. For (3). By Lemma 2.6(2), we have Sub + (S 0 ) Σ Sub + (S) Σ. We show Sub + (S 0 ) Σ Sub + (S) Σ. Suppose that C belongs to the antecedent of sat(s 0 ) and E Sub + (S 0 ) Σ. If E = A, then A C, C A Sub + (S 0 ) Σ. Since sat(s 0 ) is saturated, they belong to the union of the antecedent and the succeedent of sat(s 0 ). By Lemma 2.6(1) and the axiom GA2, there does not occur the case that both formula belong the succeedent. Hence one of them belongs to the antecedent, and by (2), it also belongs to the antecedent of S. Hence A Sub + (S) Σ. If E is either a -formula A B or a -formula A B, then A, B Sub + (S 0 ) Σ. By the proof for the case that E = A, we have A, B Sub + (S) Σ, and so, E Sub + (S) Σ. For (4). By an induction on σ. For (5). By (4), (Γ 1 1 ; τ [ A]) W(S 0 ) for some Γ 1 1. Using Definition 2.4 and Definition 2.5, we have A Γ 1. Using (2), we have A Γ. For (6). Suppose that (S; τ 1 [ A] τ 2 [ A] τ 3 ) W(S 0 ). Then by (4), (Γ ; τ 1 [ A] τ 2 [ A]) W(S 0 ) for some Γ. By Definition 2.5, there exists (Γ 1 1, A; τ 1 [ A] τ 2 ) W(S 0 ). Using (5), A Γ 1. So, Γ 1 1, A GR 1. This is contradictory to Lemma 2.6. For (7). By (1), (6) and Lemma 2.6(3). Definition 2.8. Let S 0 be a sequent, which is not provable in GR 1. We define a structure K(S 0 ) = W(S 0 ), <, = as follows:

18 Katsumi Sasaki and Shigeo Ohama (1) (Γ 1 1 ; τ 1 ) < (Γ 2 2 ; τ 2 ) if and only if τ 2 = τ 1 σ for some σ [ ], (2) = is a valuation satisfying, in addition to the conditions in Definition 1.1(3), (2.1) p Γ if and only if (Γ ; τ) = p, for any propositional variable p, (2.2) A Γ if and only if (Γ ; τ) = A, for any -formula A Sub + (S 0 ), (2.3) A Γ if and only if (Γ ; τ) = A, for any -formula A Sub + (S 0 ). Lemma 2.9. Let S 0 be a sequent, which is not provable in GR 1. Then for any A Sub + (S 0 ) and for any (Γ ; τ) W(S 0 ), (1) A Γ implies (Γ ; τ) = A, (2) A implies (Γ ; τ) = A. Proof. We use an induction on A. If A =, then by Lemma 2.6(1), A Γ. So we have (1). On the other hand, (Γ ; τ) = A, and so, we have (2). If A is a propositional variable, then (1) is clear. Suppose that p. By Lemma 2.6(1), p Γ, and so, we have (2). Suppose that A is not a propositional variable. If A is a -formula or a -formula, then the lemma can be shown similarly to the case that A is a propositional variable. Other cases can be shown in the usual way (cf. Avron [1]). Here we show only the case that A = B. For (1). Suppose that B Γ and (Γ ; τ) < (Γ 1 1 ; τ 1 ). Then τ 1 = τ σ [ C] for some σ and C. Hence there exists (Γ 2 2, C; τ σ) W(S 0 ) such that (Γ 1 1 ) = sat( C, {D D Γ 2 }, Γ 2 Σ C). By Lemma 2.7(2), we have B Γ 2. Using Definition 2.4, B Γ 1. By the induction hypothesis, we have (Γ 1 1 ; τ 1 ) = B. Hence (Γ ; τ) = B. For (2). Suppose that B. Then (Γ ; τ) < (sat( B, {D D Γ}, Γ Σ B); τ [ B]) W(S 0 ). By Definition 2.4, B belongs to the succeedent of the above saturation. By the induction hypothesis, B is false at the new pair above. Hence (Γ ; τ) = B. Corollary 2.10. Let A 1,, A m B 1,, B n be a sequent, which is not provable in GR 1. Then in K(A 1,, A m B 1,, B n ), (sat(a 1,, A m B 1,, B n ); [ ]) = A 1 A m B 1 B n.

A Sequent System of the Logic R for Rosser Sentences 19 Lemma 2.11. Let S 0 be a sequent, which is not provable in GR 1. If there exists a -formula in the antecedent of sat(s 0 ), then K(S 0 ) is a Kripke pseudo-model for R satisfying the two conditions in Definition 1.2 for any D such that Sub(D) Σ Sub + (S 0 ). Proof. By Lemma 2.7(7), W(S 0 ) is finite. The irreflexivity and the transitivity of < can be shown easily. We show α < γ and β < γ imply either one of α = β, α < β or β < α. Suppose that (S 1 ; τ 1 ) < (S 3 ; τ 3 ) and (S 2 ; τ 2 ) < (S 3 ; τ 3 ). Then τ 3 = τ 1 σ 1 = τ 2 σ 2 for some non-empty sequences σ 1 and σ 2. Hence either τ 1 = τ 2 σ 2 or τ 1 σ 1 = τ 2 holds. Using Lemma 2.7(1), we have either one of (S 1 ; τ 1 ) = (S 2 ; τ 2 ), (S 1 ; τ 1 ) < (S 2 ; τ 2 ) or (S 2 ; τ 2 ) < (S 1 ; τ 1 ). We show the two conditions in Definition 1.2 conditions in Definition 1.2 for any D such that Sub(D) Σ Sub + (S 0 ). For (1). If D is -formula, then (1) is clear by the definition of =. Suppose that D is either a -formula or a -formula, (Γ 1 1 ; τ 1 ) = D and (Γ 1 1 ; τ 1 ) < (Γ 2 2 ; τ 2 ). Then D Γ 1. By Lemma 2.7(2), D Γ 2. Hence (Γ 2 2 ; τ 2 ) = D. For (2). We divide the cases. For the case that D is A5 (i.e., D = ( A B) A). Suppose that (Γ ; τ) = A B. Since Sub(D) Σ Sub + (S 0 ), we have A B Sub + (S 0 ), and so A B Γ. Since Γ is saturated, we have A Γ. Using Lemma 2.9, (Γ ; τ) = A. For the case that D is A6 (i.e., D = (( A B) ( B C)) ( A C). Suppose that (Γ ; τ) = A B and (Γ ; τ) = B C. Since Sub(D) Σ Sub + (S 0 ), we have A B, B C Sub + (S 0 ), and so, A B, B C Γ. Since Γ is saturated, we have A C Γ. By Lemma 2.6 and the axiom GA1, A C and so, A C Γ. Hence (Γ ; τ) = A C. For the case that D is A7 (i.e., D = ( A B) (( A B) ( B A))). Suppose that (Γ ; τ) = ( A B) ( B A). Since Sub(D) Σ Sub + (S 0 ), we have A B, B A Sub + (S 0 ), and so, A B Γ and B A Γ. Also by Lemma 2.7(3), we have A B, B A Sub + (S 0 ) Sub + (Γ ), and so, A B, B A since Γ is saturated. By Lemma 2.6 and the axiom GA2, we have A Γ, and so, A A Γ since Γ is saturated. By Lemma 2.7(3), we also have A

20 Katsumi Sasaki and Shigeo Ohama A Γ, and hence A A. Since Γ is saturated, we have A. Using Lemma 2.9, (Γ ; τ) = A. Similarly, we also have (Γ ; τ) = B. For the case that D is A8 (i.e., D = ( A B) ( A B)). Suppose that (Γ ; τ) = A B. Since Sub(D) Σ Sub + (S 0 ), we have A B Sub + (S 0 ), and so, A B Γ. By Lemma 2.6 and the axiom GA4, A B Γ, and so, (Γ ; τ) = A B. For the case that D is A9 (i.e., D = (( A B) ( B A)) ). Suppose that (Γ ; τ) = A B and (Γ ; τ) = B A. Since Sub(D) Σ Sub + (S 0 ), we have A B, B A Γ. Using the axiom GA5, Γ GR 1, which is contradictory to Lemma 2.6. Lemma 2.12 (2). Let S be a set of formulas satisfying A S implies Sub + (A) S and Let K be a Kripke pseudo-model for R satisfying the two conditions in Definition 1.2 for any D such that Sub(D) Σ S. Then there exists a Kripke model K for R such that for any A S, A is valid in K if and only if A is valid in K. Theorem 2.13. Let A 1,, A m B 1,, B n be a sequent, which is not provable in GR 1. Then there exists a Kripke model K for R, in which the formula A 1 A m B 1 B n is not valid. Proof. Let Γ and be the antecedent and succeedent of sat(a 1,, A m B 1,, B n ), respectively. For any A, S(A) denotes the sequent A, {D D Γ}, Γ Σ A. By ( ), we note S(A) GR 1. Also we note that there exists a -formula in the antecedent of the saturation of S(A). Using Corollary 2.10, Lemma 2.11 and Lemma 2.12, there exists a Kripke model K(A) = W(A), < A, = A for R having the same validity for the formulas in Sub + (S(A)) as K(S(A)) has. We construct a structure K = W, <, = as follows: (1) W = {r} A {(w, A) w W(A)}, (2.1) r < α if and only if α r, (2.2) (w 1, A 1 ) < (w 2, A 2 ) if and only if A 1 = A 2 and w 1 < A1 w 2, (3.1) r = C if and only if C Γ, (3.2) (w, A) = C if and only if w = A C, where C is either one of a propositional variable, a -formula or a - formula. We note that for any formula D and for any w K(A), w = A D

A Sequent System of the Logic R for Rosser Sentences 21 if and only if (w, A) = D. Also similarly to Corollary 2.10 and Lemma 2.11, we can check the situation at r W, and as a result, we have r = A 1 A m B 1 B n and K is a pseudo-kripke model for R satisfying two conditions in Definition 1.2 for any D such that Sub(D) Σ Sub + (A 1,, A m B 1,, B n ). Hence using Lemma 2.12, we obtain the theorem. From the above theorem, we obtain the proof of (4) implies (1) in Theorem 2.1, and hence, we obtain Theorem 2.1. Corollary 2.13. If a sequent S is provable in GR, then there exists a proof figure P for S such that each formula occurring in P belongs to Sub + (S). References [1] A. Avron, On modal systems having arithmetical interpretations, The Journal of Symbolic Logic 49 (1984), pp. 935 942. [2] D. Guaspari and R. M. Solovay, Rosser sentences, Annals of Mathematical Logic 16 (1979), pp. 81 99. [3] D. H. J. de Jongh, A simplification of a completeness proof of Guaspari and Solovay, Studia Logica 46 (1987), pp. 187 192. [4] C. Smoryński, Self-reference and modal logic, Springer-Verlag, 1985. [5] F. Voorbraak, A simplification of the completeness proofs for Guaspari and Solovay s R, Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 31 (1990), pp. 44 63. Department of Mathematical Sciences Nanzan University 27 Seirei-Cho, Seto 489-0863, Japan e-mail: sasaki@ms.nanzan-u.ac.jp Toyota National College of Technology 2-1 Eisei-Cho, Toyota 471-8525, Japan e-mail:ohama@toyota-ct.ac.jp