On Devaney Chaos and Dense Periodic Points: Period 3 and Higher Implies Chaos

Similar documents
ON DEVANEY S DEFINITION OF CHAOS AND DENSE PERIODIC POINTS

CHAOTIC UNIMODAL AND BIMODAL MAPS

Problem Set 2: Solutions Math 201A: Fall 2016

PERIODIC POINTS OF THE FAMILY OF TENT MAPS

A note on Devaney's definition of chaos

CHAPTER 7. Connectedness

CHAOTIC BEHAVIOR IN A FORECAST MODEL

LINEAR CHAOS? Nathan S. Feldman

Introductory Analysis I Fall 2014 Homework #5 Solutions

STRONGLY CONNECTED SPACES

Connectedness. Proposition 2.2. The following are equivalent for a topological space (X, T ).

MH 7500 THEOREMS. (iii) A = A; (iv) A B = A B. Theorem 5. If {A α : α Λ} is any collection of subsets of a space X, then

Math 117: Topology of the Real Numbers

NAME: Mathematics 205A, Fall 2008, Final Examination. Answer Key

MORE ON CONTINUOUS FUNCTIONS AND SETS

2 Topology of a Metric Space

Thus, X is connected by Problem 4. Case 3: X = (a, b]. This case is analogous to Case 2. Case 4: X = (a, b). Choose ε < b a

ω-limit Sets of Discrete Dynamical Systems

Maths 212: Homework Solutions

Chapter 2 Metric Spaces

MAT 570 REAL ANALYSIS LECTURE NOTES. Contents. 1. Sets Functions Countability Axiom of choice Equivalence relations 9

Course 212: Academic Year Section 1: Metric Spaces

Math 320-2: Midterm 2 Practice Solutions Northwestern University, Winter 2015

MATH 51H Section 4. October 16, Recall what it means for a function between metric spaces to be continuous:

Dynamical Systems 2, MA 761

B 1 = {B(x, r) x = (x 1, x 2 ) H, 0 < r < x 2 }. (a) Show that B = B 1 B 2 is a basis for a topology on X.

Discrete dynamics on the real line

INDECOMPOSABILITY IN INVERSE LIMITS WITH SET-VALUED FUNCTIONS

arxiv: v2 [math.gn] 28 Jul 2016

Measure and Category. Marianna Csörnyei. ucahmcs

Some Background Material

A Countably-Based Domain Representation of a Non-Regular Hausdorff Space

Fragmentability and σ-fragmentability

SELF-DUAL UNIFORM MATROIDS ON INFINITE SETS

PERIODS IMPLYING ALMOST ALL PERIODS FOR TREE MAPS. A. M. Blokh. Department of Mathematics, Wesleyan University Middletown, CT , USA

Introduction to Proofs in Analysis. updated December 5, By Edoh Y. Amiran Following the outline of notes by Donald Chalice INTRODUCTION

Introduction to Dynamical Systems

Topology. Xiaolong Han. Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA address:

HW 4 SOLUTIONS. , x + x x 1 ) 2

COUNTABLY S-CLOSED SPACES

CHAPTER 5. The Topology of R. 1. Open and Closed Sets

From continua to R trees

Math 421, Homework #6 Solutions. (1) Let E R n Show that = (E c ) o, i.e. the complement of the closure is the interior of the complement.

PREVALENCE OF SOME KNOWN TYPICAL PROPERTIES. 1. Introduction

TOPOLOGY TAKE-HOME CLAY SHONKWILER

Generalized Pigeonhole Properties of Graphs and Oriented Graphs

MAXIMAL INDEPENDENT COLLECTIONS OF CLOSED SETS

Uniform Convergence, Mixing and Chaos

1 The Local-to-Global Lemma

Measures and Measure Spaces

Solutions to Tutorial 8 (Week 9)

Math General Topology Fall 2012 Homework 6 Solutions

Solve EACH of the exercises 1-3

A Note on the Generalized Shift Map

Topological properties

Walker Ray Econ 204 Problem Set 3 Suggested Solutions August 6, 2015

Chaos induced by coupled-expanding maps

2. Metric Spaces. 2.1 Definitions etc.

DENSELY k-separable COMPACTA ARE DENSELY SEPARABLE

Math 541 Fall 2008 Connectivity Transition from Math 453/503 to Math 541 Ross E. Staffeldt-August 2008

SHADOWING AND ω-limit SETS OF CIRCULAR JULIA SETS

Topology, Math 581, Fall 2017 last updated: November 24, Topology 1, Math 581, Fall 2017: Notes and homework Krzysztof Chris Ciesielski

COMPLETELY INVARIANT JULIA SETS OF POLYNOMIAL SEMIGROUPS

P-adic Functions - Part 1

Uniquely Universal Sets

Math 105A HW 1 Solutions

Section 2: Classes of Sets

Spaces of continuous functions

ANOTHER PROOF OF HUREWICZ THEOREM. 1. Hurewicz schemes

FAMILIES OF TRANSITIVE MAPS ON R WITH HORIZONTAL ASYMPTOTES

MATH 54 - TOPOLOGY SUMMER 2015 FINAL EXAMINATION. Problem 1

3 COUNTABILITY AND CONNECTEDNESS AXIOMS

More on sg-compact spaces

Introduction to Proofs

DYNAMICAL PROPERTIES OF MONOTONE DENDRITE MAPS

APPLICATIONS OF ALMOST ONE-TO-ONE MAPS

Introduction to Topology

SOLUTIONS TO EXERCISES FOR. MATHEMATICS 205A Part 1. I. Foundational material

MA651 Topology. Lecture 9. Compactness 2.

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved.

After taking the square and expanding, we get x + y 2 = (x + y) (x + y) = x 2 + 2x y + y 2, inequality in analysis, we obtain.

FUNCTIONS WITH MANY LOCAL EXTREMA. 1. introduction

Math 220A Complex Analysis Solutions to Homework #2 Prof: Lei Ni TA: Kevin McGown

Turbulence and Devaney s Chaos in Interval

ORBITAL SHADOWING, INTERNAL CHAIN TRANSITIVITY

ADDING MACHINES, ENDPOINTS, AND INVERSE LIMIT SPACES. 1. Introduction

Introduction to Real Analysis Alternative Chapter 1

1 Topology Definition of a topology Basis (Base) of a topology The subspace topology & the product topology on X Y 3

Sets and Functions. MATH 464/506, Real Analysis. J. Robert Buchanan. Summer Department of Mathematics. J. Robert Buchanan Sets and Functions

Tree sets. Reinhard Diestel

A VERY BRIEF REVIEW OF MEASURE THEORY

Section 31. The Separation Axioms

g 2 (x) (1/3)M 1 = (1/3)(2/3)M.

MORE ABOUT SPACES WITH A SMALL DIAGONAL

Homogeneity and rigidity in Erdős spaces

The small ball property in Banach spaces (quantitative results)

CLASS NOTES FOR APRIL 14, 2000

Part III. 10 Topological Space Basics. Topological Spaces

Analysis III. Exam 1

WHAT IS A CHAOTIC ATTRACTOR?

Transcription:

On Devaney Chaos and Dense Periodic Points: Period 3 and Higher Implies Chaos Syahida Che Dzul-Kifli and Chris Good Abstract. We look at density of periodic points and Devaney Chaos. We prove that if f is Devaney Chaotic on a compact metric space with no isolated points, then the set of points with prime period at least n is dense for each n. Conversely, we show that if f is a continuous function from a closed interval to itself, for which the set of points with prime period at least n is dense for each n, then there is a decomposition of the interval into closed subintervals on which either f or f 2 is Devaney Chaotic. (In fact, this result holds if the set of points with prime period at least 3 is dense.) There are a number of different definitions of what it means for a function f, from a compact metric space X, to itself, to be chaotic (see, for example, [2]). One of the most frequently discussed (not least in this journal) is Devaney s [6], which isolates three essential characteristics of a chaotic function. A function is said to be Devaney Chaotic provided: it is (topologically) transitive, that is for any two open nonempty sets U and V, there is some n N such that f n (U) V is nonempty; has a dense set of periodic points, i.e., that every open set contains a periodic point; and is sensitive to initial conditions (or has sensitive dependence on initial conditions), so that there is a sensitivity constant δ>0 such that for every x X and every ε>0, there is some point y and some n N such that d(x, y) <εbut d( f n (x), f n (y)) δ. Banks et al. [3] prove that the sensitivity condition is unnecessary; if f : X X is a transitive continuous map on an infinite compact metric space X that has a dense set of periodic points, then f has sensitive dependence on initial conditions. Assif and Gadbois [1] show that, for general X, neither transitivity nor dense periodicity are implied by the other two conditions. However, Vellekoop and Berglund [11] prove that, for a continuous map of a compact interval, transitivity implies a dense set of periodic points, so that transitive maps of compact intervals are Devaney Chaotic. Silverman [9] proves equivalent results, at least in the case of compact metric spaces without isolated points where transitivity is equivalent to the existence of a dense orbit. See also [5, 7, 10] for interesting perspectives on Devaney s definition. As simple examples, we note that a rational rotation of the circle has a dense set of periodic points but is not transitive and an irrational rotation has no periodic points but is transitive. Neither of these functions are sensitive to initial conditions. It turns out, however, that a notion somewhat stronger than dense periodic points does imply Devaney Chaos in some situations. Given f : X X, for each n N we define P n ( f ) ={x : x is a periodic point of f with prime period m n}. We write P n when f is clear from the context. http://dx.doi.org/10.4169/amer.math.monthly.122.8.773 MSC: Primary 37D45, Secondary 54H20 October 2015] DEVANEY CHAOS AND DENSE PERIODIC POINTS 773

Theorem 1. Let X be a compact metric space without isolated points. If f : X X is a continuous Devaney Chaotic function, then for all n N, is dense in X. P n ( f ) ={x : x is periodic with prime period m n} Proof. Suppose that, for some n, P n is not dense. Let U be the (nonempty) complement of the closure of P n. Since X has no isolated points, U is infinite (in fact it has the cardinality of the continuum). Since the periodic points are dense, every nonempty open subset of U must contain periodic points, but, by the definition of P n, they all have periods strictly less than n. By the result of Silverman mentioned above, there is a point z with a dense, hence infinite, orbit. It follows that there is some fragment, z 0, z 1,...,z n 1, of the orbit of z of length n starting with z 0 = f k (z) in U and ending with z n 1 = f k+n 1 (z) (it need not stay in U). Let ε be the minimum of the distances d(z i, z j ),for0 i j < n. Then the open balls B i = B ε/2 (z i ), i < n, are pairwise disjoint. Let V n 1 = B n 1, and given V n j, define V n j 1 = B n j 1 f 1 (V n j ),for each j < n. Then each V i is open, contains z i, and f (V i ) is a subset of V i+1, which is a subset of B i+1. But then V 1 U is nonempty (it contains z 0 ), so there is some periodic point y V 1 U. Since y U, y has period no more than n 1, but y V 1,so f i (y) V 1+i, for each i n 1, so that period of y is at least n, which is a contradiction. As mentioned above, having a dense set of periodic points does not imply transitivity. Theorem 1 shows that if f is transitive and has a dense set of periodic points, then P n is dense for all n N. The following example shows that a map can be sensitive to initial conditions and have P n dense for all n N but not be transitive. It also shows that a map can have P n dense for all n N but be neither transitive nor sensitive to initial conditions. Example 2. Let D ={re iθ C : r [0, 1],θ [0, 2π)} be the closed unit disk in the complex plane. Define f : D D by f (re iθ ) = re i(θ+2rπ). Then f is a homeomorphism of D and the restriction f r of f to C r ={z : z =r} is a rotation of order r. If r is irrational, then each point of C r has infinite orbit and f r is transitive. If r = p/q is rational, with p and q in lowest terms, then every point in C r has period q. Since the set of rationals with denominator at least n is dense in [0, 1], P n ( f ) is dense for all n. Since d( f n (0), f n (z)) = z for any z and any n, f is not sensitive to initial conditions (points cannot move away from 0). It is also clear that f is not transitive; for example, for no n does f n (B 1/8 (1/4)) meet B 1/8 (3/4).Ifg is the restriction of f to {z :1/2 z 1}, then P n (g) is dense for all n and g is sensitive to initial conditions but not transitive. It turns out, however, that if f is a map of the interval [0, 1] and P 3 ( f ) is dense, then f is chaotic in the following sense: [0, 1] can be written as a union of countably many closed nondegenerate subintervals; if two of these intervals intersect, they intersect only at their end points; either f or f 2 is Devaney Chaotic on each of the intervals. Barge and Martin [4] prove related results describing the structure of a continuous function f of a compact interval I for which there is a dense set of periodic points. They prove that for such an f there is a (possibly finite or empty) collection of closed subintervals {J 1, J 2,...} meeting only at their end points such that: 774 c THE MATHEMATICAL ASSOCIATION OF AMERICA [Monthly 122

1. for each i, f 2 (J i ) = J i ; 2. for each i, there is x J i such that { f 4n (x) : n 0} is dense in J i ; 3. for each x I i J i, f 2 (x) = x. Their results, however, make use of the structure of the inverse limit space; here our proofs are entirely elementary. Our proof is based on the following simple observation, which we extend in Lemmas 3, 4, and 5. Suppose that f :[0, 1] [0, 1] has a dense set of periodic points. Let 0 < a < b < 1 and let I = [0, a], J = [a, b], and K = [b, 1] and suppose that the interval J is invariant, i.e., f (J) = J, see Figure 1. The graph of f must be contained in the boxes (I I ) (J J) (K K ) or in the boxes (I K ) (J J) (K I ). For example, if there is point of the graph in (the interior of) I J, then some open subinterval I of I is mapped into J, which is invariant, so points of I are mapped into J and then stay there, so that I cannot contain any periodic points. K J I I J K Figure 1. The basic idea Recall that any union of nondegenerate intervals can be written as a countable collection of disjoint intervals (by joining together intervals that overlap). Note that if the periodic points are dense, the continuous image of any interval is a nondegenerate interval, i.e., is not a single point. In general, any continuous function on a compact metric space with a dense set of periodic points is a surjection. To see this, note that the image f (X) is compact, hence closed, and it contains all the periodic points. Lemma 3. Let f :[0, 1] [0, 1] be a continuous interval map with a dense set of periodic points. Suppose that 0 a < b c < d 1 and that f permutes the intervals [a, b] and [c, d]. Then f (b) = c, f (c) = b, and f fixes [b, c]. Moreover, 0 < a if and only if d < 1, in which case f (a) = d, f (d) = a, and f permutes the intervals [0, a] and [d, 1]. Proof. Since [a, b] and [c, d] are permuted by f,ifx is a point that is mapped from the complement of [a, b] [c, d] into [a, b] [c, d], then x cannot be periodic. So, if any point of (b, c) were mapped below b or above c, then some subinterval of [b, c] would be mapped into [a, b] [c, d]. Since the set of periodic points is dense, this is impossible and f must map [b, c] to itself. (If b = c, then f (b) = b, so[b, c] is October 2015] DEVANEY CHAOS AND DENSE PERIODIC POINTS 775

still fixed.) Since f (b) must lie both in the image of [b, c] and in the image [c, d] = f ([a, b]),so f (b) = c. Similarly f (c) = b. If 0 < a, then (arguing as above) f (a) is either c or d, but if f (a) = c, then some subinterval J of [0, a] maps to [b, c], which maps to itself, or [a, b], which permutes with [c, d]. This would imply that J has no periodic points. Hence f (a) = d. Since [0, a] contains periodic points and f maps [a, d] to itself, we see that d < 1 and f permutes [0, a] and [d, 1] with f (d) = a. Our main theorem partitions the interval into subintervals that are invariant under f or f 2 via the following two lemmas. Lemma 4. Let f :[0, 1] [0, 1] be a continuous function with a dense set of periodic points. If f has a proper invariant nondegenerate subinterval [a, b], then either: 1. 0 = a < b < 1, f(b) = b and [b, 1] is also invariant; or 2. 0 < a < b = 1, f(a) = a and [0, a] is also invariant; or 3. 0 < a < b < 1, f(a) = a, f (b) = b and the intervals [0, a] and [b, 1] are also invariant under f ; or 4. 0 < a < b < 1, f(a) = b, f (b) = a and f permutes the intervals [0, a] and [b, 1], which are also invariant under f 2. Proof. Suppose that [a, b] is a proper invariant subinterval. One of 0 = a < b < 1, 0 < a < b = 1, or 0 < a < b < 1 must hold. The arguments for cases (1) and (2) are is similar to that for (3), so we suppose that 0 < a < b < 1. If a < f (a) <b, then by continuity, there is some interval (a ε, a) whose image is a subset of (a, b). But since f fixes [a, b], no point of (a ε, a) can be periodic, which is a contradiction. Hence f (a) is either a or b. Similarly f (b) is either a or b. Suppose that f (a) = a. Then f must fix [0, a], otherwise some subinterval of [0, a] must map into [a, b], contradicting the fact that [0, a] has a dense set of periodic points. But now if f (b) = a, then some subinterval of [b, 1] maps either into [0, a] or into [a, b], neither of which are possible, so f (b) = b and f fixes [b, 1]. This is case (3). On the other hand, case (4) follows if f (a) = b, since then f must map [0, a] to the interval [b, 1] (else some subinterval of [0, a] maps into [a, b]).butas[0, a] contains periodic points, f must map [b, 1] back to [0, a], and we conclude as well that f (b) = a. Lemma 5. Let f :[0, 1] [0, 1] be a continuous function with a dense set of periodic points. If f has no proper invariant nondegenerate subinterval, then either: 1. f is transitive; or 2. f permutes two subintervals [0, a] and [a, 1] for some 0 < a < 1. Proof. Suppose now that f has no proper invariant subinterval. Certainly it has no interval of fixed points. Suppose that f is not transitive. Then there are two nonempty open subintervals U and V of [0, 1] such that U = 0 i f i (U) and V are disjoint. U can be written as a union of at most countably many disjoint, nondegenerate intervals. If one of these intervals is, say J = i N f i (U), for some subset N of N, then its image under f, f (J) = i N f i+1 (U), is a subset of another of these intervals. But since J must contain a periodic point of period k, then f k (J) must be a subset of J. Moreover, f k (J) must be dense in J, since otherwise J f k (J) contains some open subinterval that contains no periodic points. We may, therefore, express the closure of 776 c THE MATHEMATICAL ASSOCIATION OF AMERICA [Monthly 122

Figure 2. Schematic of Theorem 6: the graph of f is contained inside boxes; Case (1) on the left, f is Devaney Chaotic on each subinterval; Case (2) on the right, the intervals are permuted by f about the central invariant interval A, f 2 is Devaney Chaotic on each interval. U as a finite union of closed, nondegenerate, intervals I i = [r i, s i ], with r i < s i r i+1, for 1 i n, that are permuted by f. Since U is not equal to I and f has no proper invariant subintervals, n > 1. Consider the least k such that f (I k ) = I j and j < k. Clearly k > 1 and f (I k 1 ) = I m for some m > k 1. We consider three cases: (a) j = k 1 and k = m; (b) j k 1 and m > k; (c) j < k and m k. We claim that the second two cases are impossible. The arguments are similar in both cases so we consider case (b). In this case, we have that f (s k 1 ) [r m, s m ] = I m, so that f (s k 1 ) s k and, similarly, f (r k ) s k 1. This implies that the image of the interval L = [s k 1, r k ] under f contains the interval I k. But no point of I k is mapped into L, so some subinterval of L does not contain any periodic points, which is a contradiction. So the only possibility is case (a). Since f permutes the intervals I i,fori n, (a) implies that n = 2. By Lemma 3, we have that f permutes [0, r 1 ] and [s 2, 1], but then f permutes [0, s 1 ] and [r 2, 1] and fixes [s 1, r 2 ], which implies that s 1 = r 2 as f has no proper invariant subintervals. Before proving our main result, we first observe that P nk ( f ) is a subset of P n ( f k ). To see this, suppose that x is in P nk ( f ). This means that x has prime period m nk with respect to f. Certainly f kj (x) = x for some j,but j n since x has prime period greater than nk (with respect to f ). Hence x is in P n ( f k ). It follows, in particular, that if P n ( f ) is dense for all n, then P n ( f k ) is dense for all n. Now,P 3 ( f ) is the union of P 4 ( f ), which is a subset of P 2 ( f 2 ) and the set of points of period 3 under f. But if x has period 3 under f, then it has period 3 under f 2. It follows that P 3 ( f ) is a subset of P 2 ( f 2 ), so that if P 3 ( f ) is dense, then so is P 2 ( f 2 ) and both f and f 2 have a dense set of periodic points that are not fixed. Our main theorem says that if f :[0, 1] [0, 1] is a continuous function and that P 3 is dense (which certainly holds if P n is dense for all n), then there is a collection of closed intervals whose union is dense in [0, 1] on which either f or f 2 is Devaney Chaotic. As one of our referees mentions, this adds another perspective on Li and Yorke s classic result that period 3 implies chaos [8]. Theorem 6. Suppose that f :[0, 1] [0, 1] is a continuous function and that P 3 ={x : x is periodic with prime period m 3} is dense. One of the two following conditions must hold. October 2015] DEVANEY CHAOS AND DENSE PERIODIC POINTS 777

1. There is a finite or countably infinite collection I of closed nondegenerate subintervals of [0, 1] such that: (a) the union of all intervals in I, I I I, is dense in [0, 1]; (b) the intervals in I meet only at their end points; (c) each interval in I is invariant under f and its end points are fixed, except possibly if the end point is 0 or 1; (d) f is Devaney Chaotic on each interval in I. 2. There is a finite or countably infinite collection I of closed nondegenerate subintervals of [0, 1], and a central interval A, which might be degenerate, such that: (a) f 2 and J satisfy conditions (1)(a) to (1)(d) above, where J is I, ifais degenerate, or I {A}, if A is nondegenerate; (b) f fixes A (whether it is degenerate or not) and acts as an order-reversing permutation of the intervals in I, transposing them in pairs about A. Proof. Suppose that f :[0, 1] [0, 1] is a continuous function and that P 3 ( f ) is dense. By the observation above, both f and f 2 have a dense subset of periodic points that are not fixed and therefore the set of fixed points must be nowhere dense. Let us assume first that f has a proper nondegenerate invariant subinterval [a, b]. By Lemma 4, either: (1) both [0, b] and [b, 1] are invariant and nondegenerate; or (2) [0, a] and [a, 1] are invariant and nondegenerate; or (3) [0, a], [a, b], and [b, 1] are invariant and nondegenerate; or (4) [a, b] is invariant and f permutes [0, a] and [b, 1], neither of which is degenerate. In each of cases (1), (2), and (3), at least one of the points a and b is not equal to 0 or 1 and is fixed, so that by Lemma 3, f does not permute any subintervals of [0, 1] in pairs. Let J be the set of end points of the proper closed nondegenerate invariant subinterval of [0, 1]. Since each point in J, except possibly 0 or 1, is fixed, J must be nowhere dense. It follows that [0, 1] decomposes into a collection I of closed proper nondegenerate invariant subintervals none of which contains a proper invariant nondegenerate subinterval and each of which satisfies conditions (1) (a), (b), and (c) of the theorem. Since f does not permute any intervals in pairs, Lemma 5 implies that f is transitive on each I I and hence, by the result of Vellekoop and Berglund mentioned above, Devaney Chaotic on each I I. In case (4) let K be the collection of closed invariant proper subintervals [c, d] such that 0 < c < d < 1 and f permutes [0, c] and [d, 1]. Obviously K is nonempty as it contains [a, b]. Moreover, if [c, d] and [e, f ]areink, then [c, d] [e, f ] or vice versa, since f permutes [0, c] with [d, 1] and [0, e] with [ f, 1] and has a dense set of periodic points that are not fixed. Let A = [α, β] be the intersection of all intervals in K. Either A is a nondegenerate interval or it is a singleton fixed point, but in either case it is invariant and f permutes both the intervals [0,α] and [β,1] and the points α and β. This implies that [0,α], A, and [β,1] are invariant under f 2. Since f 2 fixes α and β and P 2 ( f 2 ) is dense, it cannot permute any proper nondegenerate subintervals, so that the map f 2 satisfies case (3) (or case (1), if α = β). Therefore, f 2 has a collection I of closed proper nondegenerate invariant subintervals satisfying conditions (1) (a) to (d) of the theorem, each of which is either A or a subset of [0,α]orof[β,1]. Since P 3 ( f ) is dense, these intervals must be permuted by f. But since f permutes [0,α] and [β,1], these intervals must be permuted in pairs as required (other than A, which is invariant). Suppose now that f has no proper invariant subinterval. By Lemma 5, either f is transitive and we are done setting I ={[0, 1]} or f permutes the intervals [0, a] and 778 c THE MATHEMATICAL ASSOCIATION OF AMERICA [Monthly 122

[a, 1], for some fixed a (0, 1), in which case [0, a] and [a, 1] are invariant under f 2 and we may argue as in the previous paragraph. In this case, the central invariant interval is the degenerate interval [a, a] ={a}. An example of a function on [0, 1] with P 3 dense and 0 not a fixed point is the tent map core { 4 f (x) = x + 2, if x [ 0, 1 3 3 4], 4 x + 4, if x ( 1, 1]. 3 3 4 An example of a function [0, 1] with P 3 dense and an invariant central interval (namely [0, 1]) that has no proper invariant subinterval is 3x + 1, if x [ 0, 3] 1, g(x) = 3x 1, if x [ 1 3, 3] 2, 3x + 3, if x [ 2, 1]. 3 To see that these functions do indeed have P 3 dense, note that the modulus of the gradient is strictly greater than 1 in each case, so that f and g are transitive on [0, 1], and hence Devaney Chaotic, so that Theorem 1 applies. The interiors of the intervals in I form a pairwise disjoint collection of open intervals whose union is dense. The complement F of their union is a closed nowhere dense subset of [0, 1]. F is therefore finite, countable, or cardinality of the continuum. In this last case, F must contain a copy of the Cantor set. It is clear that any closed nowhere dense subset F of [0, 1] that contains 0 and 1 can be realized as such a set by defining the function h as follows. For each x F, h(x) = x. If(a, b) is a maximal open subinterval (a, b) of [0, 1] F, define 3x 2a, if x ( a, 2 a + 1 b], 3 3 h(x) = 3x + 2(a + b), if x ( 2 3 a + 1 b, 1 a + 2 b], 3 3 3 3x 2b, if x ( 1 a + 2 b, b), 3 3 so that h fixes a and b and is transitive on [a, b] which is invariant. ACKNOWLEDGMENT. The authors are grateful to the referees for improvements to the exposition. REFERENCES 1. D. Assif, S. Gadbois, Letters: Defnition of chaos, Amer. Math. Monthly 99 (1992) 865. 2. B. Aulbach, B. Kieninger, On three definitions of chaos, Nonlinear Dyn. Syst. Theory 1 (2001) 23 37. 3. J. Banks, J. Brooks, G. Cairns, G. Davis, P. Stacey, On Devaney s defnition of chaos, Amer. Math. Monthly 99 (1992) 332 334. 4. M. Barge, J. Martin, Dense periodicity on the interval, Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. 94 (1985) 731 735. 5. A. Crannell, The role of transitivity in Devaney s definition of chaos, Amer. Math. Monthly 102 (1995) 788 793. 6. R. L. Devaney, An Introduction to Chaotic Dynamical System. Addison-Wesley, Redwood City, CA, 1989. 7. C. Knudsen, Chaos without nonperiodicity, Amer. Math. Monthly 101 (1994) 563 565. 8. T. Li, J. A. Yorke, Period three implies chaos, Amer. Math. Monthly 82 (1975) 985 992. 9. S. Silverman, On maps with dense orbits and the definition of chaos, Rocky Mountain J. Math. 22 (1992) 353 375. 10. P. Touhey, Yet another definition of chaos, Amer. Math. Monthly 104 (1997) 411 414. 11. M. Vellekoop, R. Berglund, On interval, transitvity = chaos, Amer. Math. Monthly 101 (1994) 353 355. October 2015] DEVANEY CHAOS AND DENSE PERIODIC POINTS 779

SYAHIDA CHE DZUL-KIFLI obtained her BSc and MSc (Mathematics) from the School of Mathematical Sciences, Universiti Kebangsaan Malaysia in 2005, joining the school as a tutor in 2006. She obtained her doctorate in 2013 from University of Birmingham, UK. She is currently an academic at UKM. As a wife, mother of three with another on the way, cooking good dishes and decorating her home are her other main activities after working hours in the office. School of Mathematical Sciences, Faculty of Science and Technology, Universiti Kebangsaan Malaysia, Malaysia syahida@ukm.edu.my CHRIS GOOD studied for his BA and DPhil in mathematics at The Queen s College, Oxford, gaining his doctorate in 1992. After a research fellowship at Wadham College, Oxford, he moved to the University of Birmingham, where he is currently a Reader in Pure Mathematics. In the little spare time he has after helping to run around after his young son, he likes to make bread, pull espresso shots, and play rugby. School of Mathematics, University of Birmingham, B15 2TT, UK c.good@bham.ac.uk Funny Forms of the Mean Value Theorem f (b) f (a) Whenever one sees the relation f (c) = b a, then the mean value theorem comes to mind. This theorem is introduced in high school math classes and sometimes in the first year university calculus course. However, an ordinary passersby on a street in Beijing is familiar with this formula, as it decorates a bridge a few blocks from Tiananmen Square. See, e.g., [1]. Have you ever thought to replace the minus sign in the above relation by an addition, or a multiplication sign? With this in mind we obtain the following funny theorems. Theorem 1. Let a, b R,a< b, with a + b 0. Let f : [a, b] R be continuous on [a, b] and differentiable on (a, b), such that a f (b) = bf (a). Then there exists c (a, b) such that f (c) = f (b)+ f (a) b+a. Theorem 2. Let a, b R, a< b, with ab > 0. Let f : [a, b] R be continuous 1 on [a, b] and differentiable on (a, b), such that f (b) f 1 (a) = b 1 a 1. Then there exists c (a, b) such that f (c) = f (b) f (a) b a. Any such a point c is a zero of the functions G, H, respectively, where G (x) = f (x) f (b) + f (a) x, H (x) = f (x) b + a f (b) f (a) x. b a By Rolle s theorem, these functions G and H vanish at some points in (a, b), since in fact, the given conditions are G (a) = G (b) and H (a) = H (b), respectively. REFERENCE 1. http://www.maa.org/community/columns/maa-found-math/week-24-1 http://dx.doi.org/10.4169/amer.math.monthly.122.8.780 MSC: Primary 26A24 Submitted by Cristinel Mortici 780 c THE MATHEMATICAL ASSOCIATION OF AMERICA [Monthly 122