Interval-Valued Cores and Interval-Valued Dominance Cores of Cooperative Games Endowed with Interval-Valued Payoffs

Similar documents
Math-Net.Ru All Russian mathematical portal

Interval values for strategic games in which players cooperate

Solutions without dummy axiom for TU cooperative games

Consistency, anonymity, and the core on the domain of convex games

An axiomatization of minimal curb sets. 1. Introduction. Mark Voorneveld,,1, Willemien Kets, and Henk Norde

Convex Interval Games

Shapley like values for interval bankruptcy games. Abstract

CORVINUS ECONOMICS WORKING PAPERS. Young's axiomatization of the Shapley value - a new proof. by Miklós Pintér CEWP 7/2015

ENCOURAGING THE GRAND COALITION IN CONVEX COOPERATIVE GAMES

Lecture 2 The Core. 2.1 Definition and graphical representation for games with up to three players

האוניברסיטה העברית בירושלים

2.1 Definition and graphical representation for games with up to three players

Analytic Solution for the Nucleolus of a Three-Player Cooperative Game

Department of Applied Mathematics Faculty of EEMCS. University of Twente. Memorandum No Owen coalitional value without additivity axiom

A Farsighted Stable Set for Partition Function Games

Neutrosophic Linear Equations and Application in Traffic Flow Problems

The Shapley Value for games with a finite number of effort levels. by Joël Adam ( )

On Bankruptcy Game Theoretic Interval Rules

Game Theory: Spring 2017

On 1-convexity and nucleolus of co-insurance games

COOPERATIVE GAME THEORY: CORE AND SHAPLEY VALUE

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India November 2007

Col.lecció d Economia E13/301. Cooperative games with size-truncated information. F. Javier Martínez-de-Albéniz

Set-valued Solutions for Cooperative Game with Integer Side Payments

Consistent Beliefs in Extensive Form Games

Game Theory: Spring 2017

Noncooperative Games, Couplings Constraints, and Partial Effi ciency

Neutrosophic Permeable Values and Energetic Subsets with Applications in BCK/BCI-Algebras

Existence of Order-Preserving Functions for Nontotal Fuzzy Preference Relations under Decisiveness

Power in the US Legislature

Inclusion Relationship of Uncertain Sets

Coincidence of Cooperative Game Theoretic Solutions in the Appointment Problem. Youngsub Chun Nari Parky Duygu Yengin

6.891 Games, Decision, and Computation February 5, Lecture 2

The Lottery Contest is a Best-Response Potential Game

A simple algorithm for the nucleolus of airport profit games

A remark on discontinuous games with asymmetric information and ambiguity

SANDWICH GAMES. July 9, 2014

Two-Person Non Zero-Sum Bimatrix Game with Fuzzy Payoffs and Its Equilibrium Strategy

Representation of TU games by coalition production economies

A partial characterization of the core in Bertrand oligopoly TU-games with transferable technologies

A Note on the Core of TU-cooperative Games with Multiple Membership Externalities

On the Shapley-Scarf Economy: The Case of Multiple Types of Indivisible Goods

No CHARACTERIZING CONVEXITY OF GAMES USING MARGINAL VECTORS. By Bas van Velzen, Herbert Hamers, Henk Norde. February 2003 ISSN

Values for Strategic Games in Which Players Cooperate

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 7: Supermodular Games

Monotone variational inequalities, generalized equilibrium problems and fixed point methods

ECONOMIC STRENGTH IN COOPERATIVE GAMES

EC516 Contracts and Organisations, LSE

The Role of Monotonicity in the Epistemic Analysis of Strategic Games

Analytic Solution for the Nucleolus of a Three-Player Cooperative Game 1

Academic Editor: Ulrich Berger Received: 12 August 2016 ; Accepted: 5 September 2016 ; Published: 9 September 2016

Entropic Selection of Nash Equilibrium

Compromise Stable TU-Games Quant, Marieke; Borm, Peter; Reijnierse, Hans; van Velzen, S.

BIPARTITE GRAPHS AND THE SHAPLEY VALUE

Efficiency, Fairness and Competitiveness in Nash Bargaining Games

Research Article A Fictitious Play Algorithm for Matrix Games with Fuzzy Payoffs

SAMPLE CHAPTERS UNESCO EOLSS NTU-GAMES. Hans Peters University of Maastricht, The Netherlands.

Acta Mathematica Academiae Paedagogicae Nyíregyháziensis 21 (2005), ISSN

Merging and splitting in cooperative games: some (im-)possibility results

DOCUMENTS DE TREBALL DE LA FACULTAT D ECONOMIA I EMPRESA. Col.lecció d Economia

Equilibria in Games with Weak Payoff Externalities

Decomposition and Intersection of Two Fuzzy Numbers for Fuzzy Preference Relations

5.2 A characterization of the nonemptiness of the core

Contracts under Asymmetric Information

Core Equivalence Theorems for Infinite Convex Games*

WEAKLY DOMINATED STRATEGIES: A MYSTERY CRACKED

International Journal of Pure and Applied Mathematics Volume 22 No , ON THE INVERSE PROBLEM FOR SEMIVALUES OF COOPERATIVE TU GAMES

An Infinitely Farsighted Stable Set

Stackelberg oligopoly TU-games: characterization of the core and 1-concavity of the dual game

Social and economic network formation: a dynamic model

Convexity of Bertrand oligopoly TU-games with differentiated products

Department of Applied Mathematics Faculty of EEMCS. University of Twente. Memorandum No. 1796

Cooperative Games. M2 ISI Systèmes MultiAgents. Stéphane Airiau LAMSADE

Mathematical Social Sciences

Aumann-Shapley Values on a Class of Cooperative Fuzzy Games

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 8: Supermodular and Potential Games

Values for cooperative games with incomplete information: An eloquent example

Majority Decision Rules with Minority Protections: Cost Assignments for Public Projects

The Distribution of Optimal Strategies in Symmetric Zero-sum Games

A Primal-Dual Algorithm for Computing a Cost Allocation in the. Core of Economic Lot-Sizing Games

Divisible Load Scheduling: An Approach Using Coalitional Games

Prisoner s Dilemma. Veronica Ciocanel. February 25, 2013

NOTE. A Characterization of Ordinal Potential Games

TOHOKU ECONOMICS RESEARCH GROUP

Convex Sets Strict Separation. in the Minimax Theorem

Correlated Equilibria of Classical Strategic Games with Quantum Signals

NOTES ON COOPERATIVE GAME THEORY AND THE CORE. 1. Introduction

Fixed Point Theorems for Condensing Maps

A True Expert Knows which Question Should be Asked.

Payoff Continuity in Incomplete Information Games

Cooperative Games. Stéphane Airiau. Institute for Logic, Language & Computations (ILLC) University of Amsterdam

EFFICIENT, WEAK EFFICIENT, AND PROPER EFFICIENT PORTFOLIOS

NOTE. A 2 2 Game without the Fictitious Play Property

Handout 4: Some Applications of Linear Programming

Bayesian Persuasion Online Appendix

Efficiency and converse reduction-consistency in collective choice. Abstract. Department of Applied Mathematics, National Dong Hwa University

EXISTENCE OF PURE EQUILIBRIA IN GAMES WITH NONATOMIC SPACE OF PLAYERS. Agnieszka Wiszniewska Matyszkiel. 1. Introduction

Converse consistency and the constrained equal benefits rule in airport problems

Total Expected Discounted Reward MDPs: Existence of Optimal Policies

Tijmen Daniëls Universiteit van Amsterdam. Abstract

Transcription:

mathematics Article Interval-Valued Cores and Interval-Valued Dominance Cores of Cooperative Games Endowed with Interval-Valued Payoffs Hsien-Chung Wu Department of Mathematics, National Kaohsiung Normal University, Kaohsiung 802, Taiwan; hcwu@nknucc.nknu.edu.tw Received: 25 October 2018 ; Accepted: 14 November 2018 ; Published: 16 November 2018 Abstract: Cooperative games endowed with interval-valued payoffs are studied in this paper. Based on the interval-valued payoff and the different types of orderings, we can propose many types of so-called interval-valued cores and interval-valued dominance cores. The main issue of this paper is to establish the equalities of different types of interval-valued cores and interval-valued dominance cores under a mild assumption. Without considering the individual rationality, we also establish the equalities of different types of interval-valued pre-cores and interval-valued dominance pre-cores without any extra assumptions. Keywords: cores; dominance cores; Hukuhara difference; interval-valued payoffs; null set 1. Introduction The game theory in economics comes from the pioneering work by von Neumann and Morgenstern [1]. The game theory mainly concerns the behavior of players whose decisions affect each other. The topic of cooperative games can also be regarded as games in coalitional form. Nash [2] defined the concept of a general two-person cooperative game and a solution concept of such games. The cooperation means that the players have complete freedom of communication and comprehensive information on the structure of the game. Young [3] studied the monotonic solutions of cooperative games. The principle of monotonicity for cooperative games states that if a game changes such that some player s contribution to all coalitions increases or stays the same, then the player s allocation should not decrease. The well-known Shapley value is a unique symmetric and efficient solution concept that is also monotonic. In a cooperative game, the payoff of a coalition is assumed to be a real number that can also represent the worth under this coalition. Owing to unexpected situations and fluctuation in the real market, the payoff cannot be measured precisely. In other words, the payoff is uncertain in the real world. Based on the probability theory, the stochastic payoffs were studied by Fernández et al. [4], Granot [5] and Suijs et al. [6], where the payoffs were assumed to be random variables. The other types of stochastic games were also proposed by Chakrabarti [7], Alvarez-Mena and Hernández-Lerma [8], Dshalalow and Huang [9], Dekel et al. [10] and Guo and Yang [11]. A general model of cooperative games whose characteristic function takes values in a partially ordered linear space has also been studied by Puerto et al. [12]. Another concept of uncertain payoff is to consider the interval-valued payoff in which the uncertain worth of a given coalition is assumed to be located in a bounded closed interval instead of assuming it to be a random variable. The advantage with considering interval-valued payoffs is that the determination of uncertainty is easily performed by simply determining the lower and Mathematics 2018, 6, 255; doi:10.3390/math6110255 www.mdpi.com/journal/mathematics

Mathematics 2018, 6, 255 2 of 26 upper end-points. However, the determination of uncertainty for stochastic payoffs by providing the probability distribution functions is not an easy task. Applying the interval analysis (ref. Moore [13]) to the conventional cooperative game establishes the so-called interval-valued cooperative games by referring to Branzei et al. [14], Alparslan Gok et al. [15] and Mallozzi et al. [16]. The cooperative games endowed with the interval-valued payoffs has also been investigated in Alparslan Gök et al. [17] and the references therein. The inclusion relationship between the interval-valued core and interval-valued dominance core has been established in Alparslan Gök et al. [17] by showing that the interval-valued core is contained in the interval-valued dominance core. Since the equalities of the interval-valued core and interval-valued dominance core were not established in Alparslan Gök et al. [17], in this paper, we shall establish the equalities of the interval-valued core and interval-valued dominance core by introducing different types of orderings. Branzei et al. [18] considered the interval-valued bankruptcy games that arose from bankruptcy situations with interval-valued claims in which two interval-valued Shapley-like values are proposed and the interrelations using the interval arithmetic operations (ref. Moore [13]) are studied. Mallozzi et al. [16] introduced a solution concept of core-like cooperative games in which the fuzzy intervals were taken into account. Also, a necessary condition was provided to assure the non-emptiness of core-like games. The more detailed fuzzy cooperative games can refer to Mares [19]. On the other hand, Han et al. [20] proposed the interval-valued core and the interval Shapley-like value of cooperative games by defining a new order relation of intervals. Alparslan Gok et al. [21] considered the Weber set and the Shapley value for interval-valued cooperative games and established their relations with the interval-valued core of convex interval-valued cooperative games. Branzei et al. [22] and Alparslan Gok et al. [17] also studied the interval-valued core, the interval-valued dominance core, the interval-valued square dominance core and the interval-valued stable sets of cooperative games under interval uncertainty. Li et al. [23 25] proposed several concepts of interval-valued solutions such as the interval-valued Shapley value, the interval-valued solidarity value and the interval-valued Banzhaf value in which an effective nonlinear programming method for computing interval-valued cores was established. Meng et al. [26] proposed a generalized form of fuzzy games with interval characteristic functions in which the interval Shapley function and interval population monotonic allocation function were studied. A bounded closed interval subtracting itself cannot be a zero element. Therefore the additive inverse element of a bounded closed interval does not exist. In this paper, we introduce the concept of a null set that can be used to define the orderings and almost identical concept in the space consisting of all bounded and closed intervals. We also introduce the concept of Hukuhara difference for the bounded closed intervals, which is used to propose the different types of cores and dominance cores. The argument for studying the relationships between the interval-valued core and interval-valued dominance core in this paper is completely different from that of Alparslan Gök et al. [17], since the concepts of null set and Hukuhara difference are invoked. Especially, based on these settings, we can establish the equalities of the interval-valued core and interval-valued dominance core, which was not studied in Alparslan Gök et al. [17]. In Section 2, we propose the concept of a null set and present the interesting properties of bounded closed intervals in R that will be used for the further investigation. We also introduce many types of orderings that will be used to study the interval-valued cores and interval-valued dominance cores. In Section 3, we introduce the concept of a cooperative game endowed with the interval-valued payoffs. In Sections 4 and 5, based on the different orderings introduced in Section 2, we propose many types of cores and dominance cores. On the other hand, using the Hukuhara difference, we also introduce the so-called H-cores and dominance H-cores. In Section 6, we study the relationships between cores and dominance cores. Without considering the individual rationality, in Section 7, we also study the relationships between pre-cores and dominance pre-cores.

Mathematics 2018, 6, 255 3 of 26 2. Intervals in R We write [a, b] to denote a bounded closed interval in R, where a is the left-endpoint and b is the right-endpoint. The center of [a, b] is defined by the average c (a + b)/2 of the left-endpoint and right-endpoint. The bounded closed interval [a, b] can also be regarded as an approximated real number c with symmetric uncertainty u b c = c a, where u is the half-width of the bounded closed interval [a, b]. We denote by I the collection of all bounded closed intervals in R. For convenience, for any A I, we write A = [a L, a U ]. Let denote any of the four basic arithmetic operations,,, between two bounded closed intervals A = [a L, a U ] and B = [b L, b U ]. We define Then we have the following operations: A B = c : c = a + b for all a A and b B. A B = [a L + b L, a U + b U] [ A B = a L b U, a U b L], [ A B = min a L b L, a L b U, a U b L, a U b U, max a L b L, a L b U, a U b L, a U b U], [ A B = min a L /b L, a L /b U, a U /b L, a U /b U, max a L /b L, a L /b U, a U /b L, a U /b U] for 0 B. Since A B is a bounded closed interval, we also write (A B) L and (A B) U to denote the left-endpoint and right-endpoint of A B, respectively. In particular, we have A A = [ a L a U, a U a L] [ ( = a U a L), a U a L], which says that each A A is an approximated zero with symmetric uncertainty a U a L. Therefore, we say that A A is an interval zero. The zero interval is defined to be [0, 0]. Let Ω = A A : A I that collects all interval zeros. Equivalently, ω Ω if and only if ω U 0 and ω L = ω U, i.e., [ ω = ω L, ω U] [ = ω U, ω U], where the bounded closed interval ω is an approximated zero with symmetric uncertainty ω U. We also call Ω as the null set in I. It is also clear that the zero interval [0, 0] is in the null set Ω. Remark 1. It is not hard to check that the null set Ω is closed under the interval addition. In other words, for any ω 1, ω 2 Ω, we have ω 1 ω 2 Ω. Let A and B be two bounded closed intervals. We say that A and B are almost identical if and only if the centers of A and B are equal. Suppose that their common centers are κ R. Then A and B can both be regarded as the approximated real number κ. The only difference is the uncertainty. In this case, if A B then we say that B is more uncertain than A. For any bounded closed interval A = [a L, a U ] and any ω = [ω L, ω U ], we see that A and A ω are almost identical in the sense of A ω being more uncertain than A. Therefore we can define the almost identical concept in I below. Definition 1. Given any two bounded closed intervals A and B, we define A = Ω B if and only if there exist ω 1, ω 2 Ω such that A ω 1 = B ω 2.

Mathematics 2018, 6, 255 4 of 26 Remark 2. Suppose that A = Ω B. Since [0, 0] Ω, it can happen that one of the following situations is satisfied: A = B when ω 1 = ω 2 = [0, 0]; there exists ω Ω such that B ω = A when ω 1 = [0, 0] and ω 2 = ω; there exists ω Ω such that A ω = B when ω 2 = [0, 0] and ω 1 = ω. It is clear that A (B B) = Ω A. More interpretation regarding the equality A = Ω B is presented below. We first observe that the center of A ω 1 is (a L + a U )/2 and the center of B ω 2 is (b L + b U )/2. This says that if A = Ω B then the centers of A and B are all identical. Therefore we may say that A = Ω B means A and B being identical with different symmetric uncertainties. Proposition 1. Let A and B be two bounded closed intervals. (i) If C = A B, then C B = Ω A. (ii) If C = (A ω 1 ) (B ω 2 ) for some ω 1, ω 2 Ω, then C B = Ω A. (iii) Suppose that Ā = Ω A and B = Ω B. Then we have the following properties. If C = Ā B, then C B = Ω A. If C = (Ā ω 1 ) ( B ω 2 ) for some ω 1, ω 2 Ω, then C B = Ω A. Proof. It suffices to prove the second case of part (iii). Since Ā = Ω A and B = Ω B, it follows that Ā ω 3 = A ω 4 and B ω 5 = B ω 6 for some ω (i) Ω for i = 3, 4, 5, 6. If C = (Ā ω 1 ) ( B ω 2 ), then, by adding B ω 2 on both sides, we have C ( B ω 2 ) = (Ā ω 1 ) ( B ω 2 ) ( B ω 2 ) = (Ā ω 1 ) ω 7, where ω 7 = ( B ω 2 ) ( B ω 2 ) Ω. By adding ω 3 ω 5 on both sides, we also have C ( B ω 5 ) ω 2 ω 3 = (Ā ω 3 ) ω 5 ω 1 ω 7, which implies C (B ω 6 ) ω 2 ω 3 = (A ω 4 ) ω 5 ω 1 ω 7. Using Remark 1, we obtain C B ω 8 = A ω 9, where ω 8 = ω 2 ω 3 ω 6 Ω and ω 9 = ω 1 ω 4 ω 5 ω 7 Ω. This shows C B = Ω A, and the proof is complete. Definition 2. Let A and B be two bounded closed intervals. We define three binary relations as follows: A B if and only if a L b L and a U b U ; A B if and only if a U b U ; A B if and only if a U b L. Remark 3. It is clear that the above three binary relations are reflexive and transitive on I; that is, they are partial orderings on I. We also see that A B implies A B, and that A B implies A B. If the bounded closed intervals A and B are not degenerated, then A = B cannot imply A B.

Mathematics 2018, 6, 255 5 of 26 Definition 3. Let A and B be two bounded closed intervals. We define three binary relations as follows: A B if and only if A B and A = B; A B if and only if a U < b U ; A B if and only if a U < b L. It is clear that A B if and only if A B and a L < b L or a U < b U. Therefore we also propose the following defintion. Definition 4. Let A and B be two bounded closed intervals. We define three binary relations as follows: A B if and only if A B and a L < b L and a U < b U. Remark 4. It is clear to see that A B implies A B, that A B implies A B, and that A B implies A B. Since Ω can be regarded as a kind of zero element in I, we also define the following binary relations. Definition 5. Given any two bounded closed intervals A and B, we define A Ω B if and only if A ω 1 B ω 2 for some ω 1, ω 2 Ω. We can similarly define A Ω B and A Ω B. The strict orderings can also be similarly defined. A Ω B, A Ω B, A Ω B, A Ω B Suppose that A Ω B. Since [0, 0] Ω, it can happen that one of the following situations is satisfied: A B when ω 1 = ω 2 = [0, 0]; there exists ω Ω such that A B ω when ω 1 = [0, 0] and ω 2 = ω; there exists ω Ω such that A ω B when ω 2 = [0, 0] and ω 1 = ω. The same situations can also apply to A Ω B and A Ω B. The following different relations of transitivity will be used for discussing the inclusions of cores and dominance cores. Proposition 2. Let A, B and C be bounded closed intervals. We have the following properties. (i) If A B Ω C then A Ω C, and if A B C then A C. (ii) If A B Ω C then A Ω C, and if A B C then A C. (iii) If A B Ω C then A Ω C, and if A B C then A C. (iv) If A B Ω C then A Ω C, and if A B C then A C. (v) If A B Ω C then A Ω C, and if A B C then A C. (vi) if A B Ω C then A Ω C, and if A B C then A C; Proof. To prove part (i), by definition, there exist ω 1, ω 2 Ω such that B ω 1 C ω 2. We also have a U < b U. Therefore we obtain a U + ω U 1 < bu + ω U 1 cl + ω L 2,

Mathematics 2018, 6, 255 6 of 26 which says that A ω 1 C ω 2. Without considering ω 1 and ω 2, we can similarly obtain that A B C implies A C. The other parts can be similarly obtained. This completes the proof. Remark 5. Based on Proposition 2, we can use Remarks 3 and 4 to obtain many other relations of transitivity as follows: Using (ii), if A B Ω C then A Ω C, and if A B C then A C. Using (i), if A B Ω C then A Ω C, and if A B C then A C; Using (ii), if A B Ω C then A Ω C, and if A B C then A C; Using (iii), if A B Ω C then A Ω C, and if A B C then A C; Using (iv), if A B Ω C then A Ω C, and if A B C then A C; Using (v), if A B Ω C then A Ω C, and if A B C then A C; 3. Cooperative Games with Interval-Valued Payoffs We consider a finite set N = 1, 2,, n of players. The subsets of N are called the coalitions. We denote by P(N) the collection of all coalitions. Let v : P(N) I be an interval-valued function defined on P(N). Then (N, v) is called a cooperative game with interval-valued payoff if and only if v( ) = [0, 0]. Given a coalition S, owing to the unexpected situation, the payoff v(s) regarding this coalition S is assumed to be uncertain. In other words, the map v assigns to each coalition a bounded closed interval telling what such a coalition can achieve in cooperation. Let (N, v) be a cooperative game with interval-valued payoff. For any S, T N with S T =, we define three types of superadditivity as follows: We say that (N, v) is -superadditive if and only if v(s T) v(s) v(t); We say that (N, v) is -superadditive if and only if v(s T) v(s) v(t); We say that (N, v) is -superadditive if and only if v(s T) v(s) v(t). Given a finite set N = 1, 2,, n of players, let S denote the cardinality of a subset S of N. Therefore we have N = n. Example 1. We consider a factory with n workers. Assume that each worker is doing the same task. Owing to the unexpected uncertainty and ability, the worker i can earn around A i dollars, where the statement around A i dollars can be modeled as a bounded closed interval in R. Therefore, we set v(i) = A i for i N. Given a coalition S N, the cooperation for the workers in S shows that there is an extra benefit S B can be earned, where the benefit depends on the cardinality of the coalition S and the benefit is around B dollars for each member. In this case, the interval-valued payoff v(s) can be defined as follows ( v(s) = A i ) ( S B). It is also reasonable to define v( ) = [0, 0].

Mathematics 2018, 6, 255 7 of 26 4. Cooperative Games with Interval-Valued Payoffs We consider a finite set N = 1, 2,, n of players. The subsets of N are called the coalitions. We denote by P(N) the collection of all coalitions. Let v : P(N) I be an interval-valued function defined on P(N). Then (N, v) is called a cooperative game with interval-valued payoff if and only if v( ) = [0, 0]. Given a coalition S, owing to the unexpected situation, the payoff v(s) regarding this coalition S is assumed to be uncertain. In other words, the map v assigns to each coalition a bounded closed interval telling what such a coalition can achieve in cooperation. Let (N, v) be a cooperative game with interval-valued payoff. For any S, T N with S T =, we define three types of superadditivity as follows: We say that (N, v) is -superadditive if and only if v(s T) v(s) v(t); We say that (N, v) is -superadditive if and only if v(s T) v(s) v(t); We say that (N, v) is -superadditive if and only if v(s T) v(s) v(t). Given a finite set N = 1, 2,, n of players, let S denote the cardinality of a subset S of N. Therefore we have N = n. Example 2. We consider a factory with n workers. Assume that each worker is doing the same task. Owing to the unexpected uncertainty and ability, the worker i can earn around A i dollars, where the statement around A i dollars can be modeled as a bounded closed interval in R. Therefore, we set v(i) = A i for i N. Given a coalition S N, the cooperation for the workers in S shows that there is an extra benefit S B can be earned, where the benefit depends on the cardinality of the coalition S and the benefit is around B dollars for each member. In this case, the interval-valued payoff v(s) can be defined as follows It is also reasonable to define v( ) = [0, 0]. v(s) = A i ( S B). 5. Cores of Cooperative Game with Interval-Valued Payoffs Given a finite set N = 1, 2,, n of players, we write A I N to denote the N -dimensional vector in the product set I N given by A = (A 1, A 2,, A n ) I I I. Let (N, v) be a cooperative game with interval-valued payoff. The set of pre-imputation of (N, v) is denoted and defined by I (v) = = A I N : A i = Ω v(n) A I N : A i ω 1 = v(n) ω 2 for some ω 1, ω 2 Ω.

Mathematics 2018, 6, 255 8 of 26 Suppose that the individual rationality is considered. The different sets of imputation of (N, v) are defined by I(v, ) = A I (v) : A i v(i) for each i N and I(v, Ω ) = A I (v) : A i Ω v(i) for each i N = A I (v) : for each i N, A i ω 1 v(i) ω 1 for some ω 1, ω 2 Ω. We can similarly define I(v, ), I(v, Ω ), I(v, ) and I(v, Ω ) based on the different binary relations. It is clear that I(v, ) I(v, Ω ), I(v, ) I(v, Ω ) and I(v, ) I(v, Ω ). Using Remark 3, we see that I(v, Ω ) I(v, Ω ) I(v, Ω ). Example 3. Continued from Example 2, we have ( v(n) = A i ) N B. Therefore the pre-imputation is given by I (v) = A I N : A i ω 1 = A i N B ω 2 for some ω 1, ω 2 Ω. The imputation of (N, v) are also given by I(v, ) = A I (v) : A i A i for each i N and I(v, Ω ) = A I (v) : for each i N, A i ω 1 A i ω 1 for some ω 1, ω 2 Ω. Let (N, v) be a cooperative game with interval-valued payoff. In order to define the core of (N, v). We first define the concept of anti-core. The different types of anti-core of (N, v) are denoted and defined as follows. Under the set of imputation I(v, ), we define Ĉ(v, ; ) = A I(v, ) : there exists S N such that A i v(s) and Ĉ(v, ; Ω ) = A I(v, ) : there exists S N such that A i Ω v(s). Under the set of imputation I(v, Ω ), we define Ĉ(v, Ω ; ) = A I(v, Ω ) : there exists S N such that A i v(s) and Ĉ(v, Ω ; Ω ) = A I(v, Ω ) : there exists S N such that A i Ω v(s).

Mathematics 2018, 6, 255 9 of 26 Since A B implies A Ω B, we have the inclusion Ĉ(v, ; ) Ĉ(v, ; Ω ) and Ĉ(v, Ω ; ) Ĉ(v, Ω ; Ω ). Based on the different binary relations, we can similarly define the other types of anti-core. For example, it is clear to see that Ĉ(v, ; ) = Ĉ(v, Ω ; Ω ) = Ĉ(v, ; Ω ) = A I(v, ) : there exists S N such that A i v(s) A I(v, Ω ) : there exists S N such that A i Ω v(s) A I(v, ) : there exists S N such that A i Ω v(s). Now the core of (N, v) is defined to be the complement set of anti-core with respect to the corresponding set of imputation. More precisely, the core C(v, ; ) of (N, v) is denoted and defined by C(v, ; ) = I(v, ) \ Ĉ(v, ; ), and the core C(v, ; Ω ) of (N, v) is denoted and defined by It is also clear to see that C(v, ; Ω ) = I(v, ) \ Ĉ(v, ; Ω ). C(v, ; Ω ) = I(v, ) \ Ĉ(v, ; Ω ) and C(v, Ω ; ) = I(v, Ω ) \ Ĉ(v, Ω ; ). Equivalently, we also see that C(v, ; ) = A I(v, ) : A i v(s) for all S N and C(v, Ω ; ) = A I(v, Ω ) : A i v(s) for all S N. Given any two bounded closed intervals A and B. If there exists another bounded closed interval C satisfying A = B C, then we say that the Hukuhara difference between A and B exists, and we write C = A H B. It is clear to see that c L = a L b L and c U = a U b U. Based on the Hukuhara difference, we also want to define the anti-cores and core of a cooperative game with interval-valued payoff. Under the set of imputation I(v, ), the H-anti-cores of (N, v) are denoted and defined by Ĉ H (v, ; ) = A I(v, ) : there exists S N such that A i v(s) and that the Hukuhara difference v(s) H A i exists

Mathematics 2018, 6, 255 10 of 26 and Ĉ H (v, ; Ω ) = A I(v, ) : there exist S N and ω 1, ω 2 Ω such that A i ω 1 v(s) ω 2 and that the Hukuhara difference (v(s) ω 2 ) H A i ω 1 exists. The H-cores of (N, v) are denoted and defined by C H (v, ; ) = I(v, ) \ Ĉ H (v, ; ) and C H (v, ; Ω ) = I(v, ) \ Ĉ H (v, ; Ω ). More precisely, we have C H (v, ; ) = A I(v, ) : for each S N, either A i v(s) or the Hukuhara difference v(s) H A i does not exist and C H (v, ; Ω ) = A I(v, ) : for each S N and for any ω 1, ω 2 Ω, either A i ω 1 v(s) ω 2 or the Hukuhara difference (v(s) ω 2 ) H A i ω 1 does not exist. Based on the different binary relations, we can similarly define the other types of H-core of (N, v). Using Remarks 3 and 4, we can obtain many inclusions regarding the different types of cores and H-cores. We omit the details. Without considering the individual rationality, we can similarly define the pre-core C and pre-h-core C H based on the pre-imputation I. Example 4. Continued from Example 3, if A C H (v, ; ), then, for each S N, either [ ] A i A i ( S B) or the Hukuhara difference does not exists. [ ] A i ( S B) H A i 6. Dominance Cores of Cooperative Game with Interval-Valued Payoffs Let (N, v) be a cooperative game with interval-valued payoff. We are going to define many types of dominance core and H-dominance core. For A, B I(v, ) and S N, we say that B ( ;, Ω )-dominates A via coalition S if and only if A i B i for each i S and B i Ω v(s).

Mathematics 2018, 6, 255 11 of 26 We simply say that B ( ;, Ω )-dominates A if and only if there is a coalition S such that B ( ;, Ω )-dominates A via S. The ( ;, Ω )-dominance core of (N, v), denoted by DC(v, ;, Ω ), is the set of imputation I(v, ) that are ( ;, Ω )-nondominated. For A, B I(v, ) and S N, we say that B ( ;, )-H-dominates A via coalition S if and only if A i B i for each i S and B i v(s) and the Hukuhara difference v(s) H ( A i ) exists. We simply say that B ( ;, )-H-dominates A if and only if there is a coalition S such that B ( ;, )-H-dominates A via S. The ( ;, )-H-dominance core of (N, v), denoted by DC H (v, ;, ), is the set of imputation I(v, ) that are ( ;, )-H-nondominated. For A, B I(v, ) and S N, we say that B ( ;, Ω )-H-dominates A via coalition S if and only if A i B i for each i S, and there exist ω 1, ω 2 Ω such that B i ω 1 v(s) ω 2 and the Hukuhara difference (v(s) ω 2 ) H ( A i ω 1 ) exists. We simply say that B ( ;, Ω )-H-dominates A if and only if there is a coalition S such that B ( ;, Ω )-H-dominates A via S. The ( ;, Ω )-H-dominance core of (N, v), denoted by DC H (v, ;, Ω ), is the set of imputation I(v, ) that are ( ;, Ω )-H-nondominated. Based on the different binary relations, we can similarly define the other types of dominance cores and H-dominance cores. For example, it is clear to see that DC(v, Ω ;, Ω ) is the set of imputation I(v, Ω ) that are ( Ω ;, Ω )-nondominated, and DC H (v, ;, Ω ) is the set of imputation I(v, ) that are ( ;, Ω )-H-nondominated. Using Remarks 3 and 4, we can obtain many inclusions regarding the different types of dominance cores and H-dominance cores. We omit the details. Without considering the individual rationality, we can similarly define the dominance pre-core DC and H-dominance pre-core DC H based on the pre-imputation I. Example 5. Continued from Example 3, for A, B I(v, ) and S N, we see that B ( ;, )-H-dominates A via coalition S if and only if A i B i for each i S and [ ] B i A i ( S B) and the Hukuhara difference [ ] A i ( S B) H A i exists. 7. The Relations between Cores and Dominance Cores We are going to investigate the inclusions and equalities between cores (resp. H-cores) and dominance cores (resp. H-dominance cores). Proposition 3. Given a cooperative game with interval-valued payoff (N, v), under the set of imputation I(v, ), we have the following inclusions:

Mathematics 2018, 6, 255 12 of 26 C(v, ; Ω ) DC(v, ;, Ω ) and C(v, ; ) DC(v, ;, ); C(v, ; Ω ) DC(v, ;, Ω ) and C(v, ; ) DC(v, ;, ); C(v, ; Ω ) DC(v, ;, Ω ) and C(v, ; ) DC(v, ;, ); C(v, ; Ω ) DC(v, ;, Ω ) and C(v, ; ) DC(v, ;, ); C(v, ; Ω ) DC(v, ;, Ω ) and C(v, ; ) DC(v, ;, ); C(v, ; Ω ) DC(v, ;, Ω ) and C(v, ; ) DC(v, ;, ); C(v, ; Ω ) DC(v, ;, Ω ) and C(v, ; ) DC(v, ;, ); C(v, ; Ω ) DC(v, ;, Ω ) and C(v, ; ) DC(v, ;, ); C(v, ; Ω ) DC(v, ;, Ω ) and C(v, ; ) DC(v, ;, ); C(v, ; Ω ) DC(v, ;, Ω ) and C(v, ; ) DC(v, ;, ); C(v, ; Ω ) DC(v, ;, Ω ) and C(v, ; ) DC(v, ;, ); C(v, ; Ω ) DC(v, ;, Ω ) and C(v, ; ) DC(v, ;, ); Proof. We first prove the inclusion C(v,, Ω ) DC(v, ;, Ω ). The inclusion is obvious when I(v, ) =. Therefore we assume I(v, ) =. For A I(v, ) \ DC(v, ;, Ω ), there exists B I(v, ) such that B ( ;, Ω )-dominates A. By definition, there exists S N satisfying A i B i for each i S and Therefore we obtain B i Ω v(s). A i which says that A i Ω v(s) by Remark 5, i.e., B i Ω v(s), A Ĉ(v;, Ω ) = I(v, ) \ C(v;, Ω ). We can similarly obtain the inclusion C(v,, ) DC(v, ;, ). The other types of inclusions can be similarly obtained by Proposition 2 and Remark 5. This completes the proof. Proposition 4. Given a cooperative game with interval-valued payoff (N, v), under the set of imputation I(v, ), we have the following inclusions: C H (v, ; Ω ) DC H (v, ;, Ω ) and C H (v, ; ) DC H (v, ;, ); C H (v, ; Ω ) DC H (v, ;, Ω ) and C H (v, ; ) DC H (v, ;, ); C H (v, ; Ω ) DC H (v, ;, Ω ) and C H (v, ; ) DC H (v, ;, ); C H (v, ; Ω ) DC H (v, ;, Ω ) and C H (v, ; ) DC H (v, ;, ); C H (v, ; Ω ) DC H (v, ;, Ω ) and C H (v, ; ) DC H (v, ;, ); C H (v, ; Ω ) DC H (v, ;, Ω ) and C H (v, ; ) DC H (v, ;, ); C H (v, ; Ω ) DC H (v, ;, Ω ) and C H (v, ; ) DC H (v, ;, ); C H (v, ; Ω ) DC H (v, ;, Ω ) and C H (v, ; ) DC H (v, ;, ); C H (v, ; Ω ) DC H (v, ;, Ω ) and C H (v, ; ) DC H (v, ;, ); C H (v, ; Ω ) DC H (v, ;, Ω ) and C H (v, ; ) DC H (v, ;, ); C H (v, ; Ω ) DC H (v, ;, Ω ) and C H (v, ; ) DC H (v, ;, ); C H (v, ; Ω ) DC H (v, ;, Ω ) and C H (v, ; ) DC H (v, ;, ); Proof. We first prove the inclusion C H (v, ; ) DC H (v, ;, ). The inclusion is obvious when I(v, ) =. Therefore we assume I(v, ) =. For A I(v, ) \ DC H (v, ;, ), there exists

Mathematics 2018, 6, 255 13 of 26 B I(v, ) such that B ( ;, )-H-dominates A. By definition, there exists S N satisfying A i B i for each i S, ) A i exists. Therefore we obtain B i v(s) and the Hukuhara difference v(s) H ( A i which says that A i v(s) by Proposition 2, i.e., B i v(s), A Ĉ H (v, ; ) = I(v, ) \ C H (v, ; ). The other types of inclusions can be similarly obtained by Proposition 2 and Remark 5. This completes the proof. The inclusions in Propositions 3 and 4 are under the set of imputation I(v, ). We can obtain the similar inclusions under the different sets of imputation. We omit the details. Theorem 1. Let (N, v) be a cooperative game with an interval-valued payoff. Suppose that for each S N with S = N. Then v(n) v(s) v(i) (1) DC(v, ;, Ω ) C(v, ; Ω ) and DC(v, ;, Ω ) C(v, ; ). Proof. For proving the inclusion DC(v, ;, Ω ) C(v, ; Ω ), we want to show that A I(v, ) \ C(v, ; Ω ) = Ĉ(v, ; Ω ) implies A I(v, ) \ DC(v, ;, Ω ). For A Ĉ(v, ; Ω ), by the definition of anti-core, there exists S N such that A i Ω v(s), i.e., A i ω 1 v(s) ω 2 for some ω 1, ω 2 Ω. Let Then ɛ = (v(s) ω 2 ) A i ω 1. U L ɛ L = (v(s) ω 2 ) L A i ω 1 and ɛ U = (v(s) ω 2 ) U A i ω 1. Since A i ω 1 v(s) ω 2, i.e., (v(s) ω 2 ) L > ( A i ω 1 ) U, it follows that ɛ U ɛ L > 0. Using part (ii) of Proposition 1, we obtain ɛ A i = Ω v(s), (2) We are going to find an imputation B such that B ( ;, Ω )-dominates A via S.

Mathematics 2018, 6, 255 14 of 26 Suppose that S = N, i.e., N \ S =, we define A i 1 S ɛ, if i S B i = v(i) 1 v(n) v(i) v(s), if i N \ S. N \ S Then, according to (2), we have which says that for some ω 3, ω 4 Ω. We also have Let B i = A i ɛ = Ω v(s), B i ω 3 = v(s) ω 4 (3) B i = v(i) v(n) v(i) v(s). (4) ω 5 = v(i) v(i) Ω and ω 6 = v(s) v(s) Ω. (5) Then, from (3) (5), we obtain which says that B i ω 3 = ω 3 B i = ω 4 ω 5 ω 6 v(n), B i = ω 4 v(s) ω 5 v(n) v(s) B i = Ω v(n) by the fact of ω 4 ω 5 ω 6 Ω. Since A I(v, ) and ɛ U ɛ L > 0, we have 1 B i = A i S ɛ A i v(i) for each i S, which also implies B i v(i), i.e., B i v(i) for i S. Let C v(n) v(i) v(s) = v(n) v(s) v(i). and Then c L = (v(n)) L v(s) v(i) c U = (v(n)) U v(s) L v(i). U

Mathematics 2018, 6, 255 15 of 26 From (1), we see that c U c L 0, which says that B i v(i) for i N \ S. From (3), we also have B i Ω v(s). This shows that B I(v, ) and B ( ;, Ω )-dominates A via S. Suppose that S = N, for each i N, we define B i = A i 1 S ɛ. We can similarly show that B I(v, ) and B ( ;, Ω )-dominates A via N. Therefore we conclude that A I(v, ) \ DC(v, ;, Ω ), which proves DC(v, ;, Ω ) C(v, ; Ω ). We can similarly obtain the inclusion DC(v, ;, Ω ) C(v, ; ) using the above argument without considering ω 1 and ω 2. This completes the proof. Suppose that the cooperative game (N, v) with interval-valued payoff is -superadditive. Then we have v(n) v(s) v(i) for each S N with S = N. Theorem 2. Let (N, v) be a cooperative game with an interval-valued payoff. Suppose that for each S N with S = N. Then v(n) v(s) v(i) (6) DC H (v, ;, ) = C H (v, ; ) and DC H (v, ;, Ω ) = C H (v, ; Ω ). Proof. For proving the inclusion DC H (v, ;, Ω ) C H (v, ; Ω ), we want to show that A I(v, ) \ C H (v, ; Ω ) = Ĉ H (v, ; Ω ) implies A I(v, ) \ DC H (v, ;, Ω ). For A Ĉ H (v, ; Ω ), by the definition of anti-core, there exists S N such that A i ω 1 v(s) ω 1 for some ω 1, ω 2 Ω (7) and the Hukuhara difference ɛ (v(s) ω 2 ) H ( A i ω 1 ) exists. (8) By the definition of Hukuhara difference, we see that L U ɛ L = (v(s) ω 2 ) L A i ω 1 and ɛ U = (v(s) ω 2 ) U A i ω 1.

Mathematics 2018, 6, 255 16 of 26 Therefore, from (7), we obtain ɛ U ɛ L 0 with ɛ U > 0 or ɛ L > 0. We also have ɛ A i ω 1 = v(s) ω 2. (9) We are going to find an imputation B such that B ( ;, Ω )-H-dominates A via S. Suppose that S = N, i.e., N \ S =, we define A i 1 S ɛ, if i S B i = v(i) 1 v(n) v(i) v(s), if i N \ S. N \ S Then, according to (9), we have B i ω 1 = ɛ A i ω 1 = v(s) ω 2. (10) We also have B i = v(i) v(n) v(i) v(s). (11) Let ω 3 = v(i) v(i) Ω and ω 4 = v(s) v(s) Ω. (12) Then, from (10) (12), we obtain which says that B i ω 1 = ω 1 B i = ω 2 ω 3 ω 4 v(n), B i = v(s) ω 2 ω 3 v(n) v(s) B i = Ω v(n) by the fact of ω 2 ω 3 ω 4 Ω. Since A I(v, ) and ɛ U ɛ L 0 with ɛ U > 0 or ɛ L > 0, we have B i = A i 1 S ɛ A i v(i) for each i S, which also implies B i v(i), i.e., B i v(i) for i S. From (6), we see that B i v(i) for i N \ S. From (10), we also have B i Ω v(s). Since the Hukuhara difference in (8) exists, it says that B I(v, ) and B ( ;, Ω )-H-dominates A via S. Suppose that S = N, for each i N, we define B i = A i 1 N.

Mathematics 2018, 6, 255 17 of 26 We can similarly show that B I(v, ) and B ( ;, Ω )-H-dominates A via N. Therefore we conclude that A I(v, ) \ DC H (v, ;, Ω ), which proves DC H (v, ;, Ω ) C H (v, ; Ω ). Using Proposition 4, we obtain the desired equality. We can similarly obtain the inclusion DC H (v, ;, ) C H (v, ; ) using the above argument without considering ω 1 and ω 2. Using Proposition 4 again, we obtain the desired equality. This completes the proof. Theorem 3. Let (N, v) be a cooperative game with an interval-valued payoff. Suppose that for each S N with S = N. Then v(n) v(s) v(i) (13) DC(v, ;, Ω ) = C(v, ; Ω ) and DC(v, ;, ) = C(v, ; ). Proof. For proving the inclusion DC(v, ;, Ω ) C(v, ; Ω ), we want to show that i.e., A I(v, ) \ C(v, ; Ω ) = Ĉ(v, ; Ω ) implies A I(v, ) \ DC(v, ;, Ω ). For A Ĉ(v, ; Ω ), by the definition of anti-core, there exists S N such that A i Ω v(s), for some ω 1, ω 2 Ω. Let Using Proposition 1, we have A i ω 1 Ω v(s) ω 2 (14) ɛ = (v(s) ω 2 ) A i ω 1. ɛ A i = Ω v(s). (15) From (14), it follows that ɛ U > 0. We are going to find an imputation B such that B ( ;, Ω )- dominates A via S. Suppose that S = N, i.e., N \ S =, we define A i 1 S ɛ, if i S B i = v(i) 1 v(n) v(i) v(s), if i N \ S. N \ S Then, according to (15), we have B i = ɛ A i = Ω v(s), which says that B i ω 3 = v(s) ω 4 (16)

Mathematics 2018, 6, 255 18 of 26 for some ω 3, ω 4 Ω. We also have Let B i = v(i) v(n) v(i) v(s). (17) ω 5 = v(i) v(i) Ω and ω 6 = v(s) v(s) Ω. (18) Then, from (16), (17) and (18), we obtain which says that B i ω 3 = ω 3 B i = ω 4 ω 5 ω 6 v(n), by the fact of ω 4 ω 5 ω 6 Ω. Since A I(v, ) and ɛ U > 0, we have B i = ω 4 v(s) ω 5 v(n) v(s) B i = Ω v(n) B i = A i 1 S ɛ A i v(i) for each i S, which also implies B i v(i) for i S. From (13), we see that B i v(i) for i N \ S. From (16), we also have B i Ω v(s). This shows that B I(v, ) and B ( ;, Ω )-dominates A via S. Suppose that S = N, for each i N, we define B i = A i 1 N ɛ. We can similarly show that B I(v, ) and B ( ;, Ω )-dominates A via N. Therefore we conclude that A I(v, ) \ DC(v, ;, Ω ), which proves DC(v, ;, Ω ) C(v, ; Ω ). Using Proposition 3, we obtain the desired equality. We can similarly obtain the inclusion DC(v, ;, ) C(v, ; ) using the above argument without considering ω 1 and ω 2. Using Proposition 3 again, we obtain the desired equality. This completes the proof. Based on the different binary relations, we can similarly establish the other types of dominance cores (resp. H-dominance cores) that is contained in the cores (resp. H-cores) like Theorem 1, or the other types of dominance cores (resp. H-dominance cores) that is equal to the cores (resp. H-cores) like Theorems 2 and 3. We omit the details. Example 6. Continued from Examples 4 and 5, let ũ(s) = v(s) v(i).

Mathematics 2018, 6, 255 19 of 26 Suppose that ( B 1 N\S ) L α (ũ(s))u α (ũ(s))l α for all α [0, 1]. Then we can show that v(n) v(s) v(i). Using the above theorems, we have the following results: DC(v, ;, Ω ) C(v, ; Ω ) and DC(v, ;, Ω ) C(v, ; ); DC H (v, ;, ) = C H (v, ; ) and DC H (v, ;, Ω ) = C H (v, ; Ω ); DC(v, ;, Ω ) = C(v, ; Ω ) and DC(v, ;, ) = C(v, ; ). 8. The Relations between Pre-Cores and Dominance Pre-Cores Now we study the relations between pre-cores (resp. H-pre-cores) and dominance pre-cores (resp. H-dominance pre-cores). We shall see that the extra inequalities are not needed. Therefore the proofs are different. Proposition 5. Given a cooperative game with an interval-valued payoff (N, v), under the set of imputation I (v, ), we have the following inclusions: C (v, ; Ω ) DC (v, ;, Ω ) and C (v, ; ) DC (v, ;, ); C (v, ; Ω ) DC (v, ;, Ω ) and C (v, ; ) DC (v, ;, ); C (v, ; Ω ) DC (v, ;, Ω ) and C (v, ; ) DC (v, ;, ); C (v, ; Ω ) DC (v, ;, Ω ) and C (v, ; ) DC (v, ;, ); C (v, ; Ω ) DC (v, ;, Ω ) and C (v, ; ) DC (v, ;, ); C (v, ; Ω ) DC (v, ;, Ω ) and C (v, ; ) DC (v, ;, ); C (v, ; Ω ) DC (v, ;, Ω ) and C (v, ; ) DC (v, ;, ); C (v, ; Ω ) DC (v, ;, Ω ) and C (v, ; ) DC (v, ;, ); C (v, ; Ω ) DC (v, ;, Ω ) and C (v, ; ) DC (v, ;, ); C (v, ; Ω ) DC (v, ;, Ω ) and C (v, ; ) DC (v, ;, ); C (v, ; Ω ) DC (v, ;, Ω ) and C (v, ; ) DC (v, ;, ); C (v, ; Ω ) DC (v, ;, Ω ) and C (v, ; ) DC (v, ;, ); Proof. Since the individual rationality A i v(i) is not considered in I (v, ) for i N, it is clear that the proof of Proposition 3 is still valid. This completes the proof. Proposition 6. Given a cooperative game with interval-valued payoff (N, v), under the set of imputation I (v, ), we have the following inclusions: C H (v, ; Ω) DC H (v, ;, Ω) and C H (v, ; ) DC H (v, ;, ); C H (v, ; Ω) DC H (v, ;, Ω) and C H (v, ; ) DC H (v, ;, ); C H (v, ; Ω) DC H (v, ;, Ω) and C H (v, ; ) DC H (v, ;, ); C H (v, ; Ω) DC H (v, ;, Ω) and C H (v, ; ) DC H (v, ;, ); C H (v, ; Ω) DC H (v, ;, Ω) and C H (v, ; ) DC H (v, ;, ); C H (v, ; Ω) DC H (v, ;, Ω) and C H (v, ; ) DC H (v, ;, ); C H (v, ; Ω) DC H (v, ;, Ω) and C H (v, ; ) DC H (v, ;, ); C H (v, ; Ω) DC H (v, ;, Ω) and C H (v, ; ) DC H (v, ;, ); C H (v, ; Ω) DC H (v, ;, Ω) and C H (v, ; ) DC H (v, ;, );

Mathematics 2018, 6, 255 20 of 26 C H (v, ; Ω) DC H (v, ;, Ω) and C H (v, ; ) DC H (v, ;, ); C H (v, ; Ω) DC H (v, ;, Ω) and C H (v, ; ) DC H (v, ;, ); C H (v, ; Ω) DC H (v, ;, Ω) and C H (v, ; ) DC H (v, ;, ); Proof. Since the individual rationality A i v(i) is not considered in I (v, ) for i N, it is clear that the proof of Proposition 4 is still valid. This completes the proof. The inclusions in Propositions 5 and 6 are under the set of imputation I (v, ). We can obtain the similar inclusions under the different sets of imputation. We omit the details. Theorem 4. Let (N, v) be a cooperative game with an interval-valued payoff. Then DC (v, ;, Ω ) C (v, ; Ω ) and DC (v, ;, Ω ) C (v, ; ). Proof. For proving the inclusion DC (v, ;, Ω ) C (v, ; Ω ), we want to show that A I (v, ) \ C (v, ; Ω ) = Ĉ (v, ; Ω ) implies A I (v, ) \ DC (v, ;, Ω ). For A Ĉ (v, ; Ω ), by the definition of anti-pre-core, there exists S N such that A i Ω v(s), i.e., A i ω 1 v(s) ω 2 for some ω 1, ω 2 Ω. Let ɛ = (v(s) ω 2 ) A i ω 1. Since A i ω 1 v(s) ω 2, it follows that ɛ U ɛ L > 0. Using part (ii) of Proposition 1, we obtain ɛ A i = Ω v(s), (19) We are going to find a pre-imputation B such that B ( ;, Ω )-dominates A via S. Suppose that S = N, i.e., N \ S =, we define B i = Then, according to (19), we have A i 1 S ɛ, if i S 1 [v(n) v(s)], if i N \ S. N \ S B i = A i ɛ = Ω v(s), which says that for some ω 3, ω 4 Ω. We also have B i ω 3 = v(s) ω 4 (20) B i = v(n) v(s). (21) Let ω 5 = v(s) v(s) Ω.

Mathematics 2018, 6, 255 21 of 26 Then, from (20) and (21), we obtain B i ω 3 = ω 3 B i = ω 4 ω 5 v(n), B i = ω 4 v(s) v(n) v(s) which says that B i = Ω v(n) by the fact of ω 4 ω 5 Ω. Since ɛ U ɛ L > 0, we have 1 B i = A i S ɛ A i for each i S, From (20), we also have B i Ω v(s). This shows that B I (v, ) and B ( ;, Ω )-dominates A via S. Suppose that S = N, for each i N, we define 1 B i = A i S ɛ. We can similarly show that B I (v, ) and B ( ;, Ω )-dominates A via N. Therefore we conclude that A I (v, ) \ DC (v, ;, Ω ), which proves DC (v, ;, Ω ) C (v, ; Ω ). We can similarly obtain the inclusion DC (v, ;, Ω ) C (v, ; ) using the above argument without considering ω 1 and ω 2. This completes the proof. Theorem 5. Let (N, v) be a cooperative game with an interval-valued payoff. Then DC H (v, ;, ) = C H (v, ; ) and DC H (v, ;, Ω) = C H (v, ; Ω). Proof. For proving the inclusion DC H (v, ;, Ω) C H (v, ; Ω), we want to show that A I (v, ) \ C H (v, ; Ω) = Ĉ H(v, ; Ω ) implies A I (v, ) \ DC H (v, ;, Ω). For A Ĉ H(v, ; Ω ), by the definition of anti-pre-core, there exists S N such that A i ω 1 v(s) ω 1 for some ω 1, ω 2 Ω (22) and the Hukuhara difference ɛ (v(s) ω 2 ) H ( A i ω 1 ) exists. (23) By the definition of Hukuhara difference, we see that ɛ L = (v(s) ω 2 ) L L A i ω 1 and ɛ U = (v(s) ω 2 ) U U A i ω 1.

Mathematics 2018, 6, 255 22 of 26 Therefore, from (22), we obtain ɛ U ɛ L 0 with ɛ U > 0 or ɛ L > 0. We also have ɛ A i ω 1 = v(s) ω 2. (24) We are going to find an imputation B such that B ( ;, Ω )-H-dominates A via S. Suppose that S = N, i.e., N \ S =, we define B i = Then, according to (24), we have A i 1 S ɛ, if i S 1 [v(n) v(s)], if i N \ S. N \ S B i ω 1 = ɛ A i ω 1 = v(s) ω 2. (25) We also have B i = v(n) v(s). (26) Let ω 3 = v(s) v(s) Ω. Then, from (25) and (26), we obtain which says that B i ω 1 = ω 1 B i B i = v(s) ω 2 v(n) v(s) = ω 2 ω 3 v(n), B i = Ω v(n) by the fact of ω 2 ω 3 Ω. Since A I (v, ) and ɛ U ɛ L 0 with ɛ U > 0 or ɛ L > 0, we have From (25), we also have B i = A i 1 S ɛ A i for each i S. B i Ω v(s). Since the Hukuhara difference in (23) exists, it says that B I (v, ) and B ( ;, Ω )-Hdominates A via S. Suppose that S = N, for each i N, we define B i = A i 1 N. We can similarly show that B I (v, ) and B ( ;, Ω )-H-dominates A via N. Therefore we conclude that A I (v, ) \ DC H (v, ;, Ω), which proves DC H (v, ;, Ω) C H (v, ; Ω). Using Proposition 6, we obtain the desired equality. We can similarly obtain the inclusion DC H (v, ;, ) C H (v, ; ) using the above argument without considering ω 1 and ω 2. Using Proposition 6 again, we obtain the desired equality. This completes the proof.

Mathematics 2018, 6, 255 23 of 26 Theorem 6. Let (N, v) be a cooperative game with an interval-valued payoff. Then DC (v, ;, Ω ) = C (v, ; Ω ) and DC (v, ;, ) = C (v, ; ). Proof. For proving the inclusion DC (v, ;, Ω ) C (v, ; Ω ), we want to show that A I (v, ) \ C (v, ; Ω ) = Ĉ (v, ; Ω ) implies A I (v, ) \ DC (v, ;, Ω ). For A Ĉ (v, ; Ω ), by the definition of anti-pre-core, there exists S N such that A i Ω v(s), i.e., A i ω 1 Ω v(s) ω 2 (27) for some ω 1, ω 2 Ω. Let Using Proposition 1, we have ɛ = (v(s) ω 2 ) A i ω 1. ɛ A i = Ω v(s). (28) From (27), it follows that ɛ U > 0. We are going to find an imputation B such that B ( ;, Ω )- dominates A via S. Suppose that S = N, i.e., N \ S =, we define B i = Then, according to (28), we have A i 1 S ɛ, if i S 1 [v(n) v(s)], if i N \ S. N \ S B i = ɛ A i = Ω v(s), which says that for some ω 3, ω 4 Ω. We also have B i ω 3 = v(s) ω 4 (29) B i = v(n) v(s). (30) Let ω 5 = v(s) v(s) Ω. Then, from (29) and (30), we obtain B i ω 3 = ω 3 B i B i = ω 4 v(s) v(n) v(s) = ω 4 ω 5 v(n), which says that by the fact of ω 4 ω 5 Ω. B i = Ω v(n)

Mathematics 2018, 6, 255 24 of 26 Since A I (v, ) and ɛ U > 0, we have From (29), we also have B i = A i 1 S ɛ A i for each i S. B i Ω v(s). This shows that B I (v, ) and B ( ;, Ω )-dominates A via S. Suppose that S = N, for each i N, we define B i = A i 1 N ɛ. We can similarly show that B I (v, ) and B ( ;, Ω )-dominates A via N. Therefore we conclude that A I (v, ) \ DC (v, ;, Ω ), which proves DC (v, ;, Ω ) C (v, ; Ω ). Using Proposition 5, we obtain the desired equality. We can similarly obtain the inclusion DC (v, ;, ) C (v, ; ) using the above argument without considering ω 1 and ω 2. Using Proposition 5 again, we obtain the desired equality. This completes the proof. Based on the different binary relations, we can similarly establish the other types of relationships between the pre-cores (resp. H-pre-cores) and dominance pre-cores (resp. H-dominance pre-cores). We omit the details. Example 7. Continued from Examples 4 and 5, using the above theorems, we immediately have the following results: DC (v, ;, Ω ) C (v, ; Ω ) and DC (v, ;, Ω ) C (v, ; ); DC H (v, ;, ) = C H (v, ; ) and DC H (v, ;, Ω) = C H (v, ; Ω); DC (v, ;, Ω ) = C (v, ; Ω ) and DC (v, ;, ) = C (v, ; ). 9. Conclusions In this paper, we consider the cooperative game with interval payoffs. Since the payoffs are assumed to be closed and bounded intervals in R, the comparison between any two closed intervals are needed. Therefore many kinds of orderings and strict orderings are proposed. From Definitions 2 5, six orderings are proposed as follows A B, A B, A B, A Ω B, A Ω B, A Ω B, (31) and eight strict orderings are proposed as follows A B, A B, A B, A B, A Ω B, A Ω B, A Ω B, A Ω B. (32) In order to study the cores and dominance cores, based on the orderings in (31), six sets of imputation and six sets of pre-imputation I(v, ), I(v, Ω ), I(v, ), I(v, Ω ), I(v, ) and I(v, Ω ) I (v, ), I (v, Ω ), I (v, ), I (v, Ω ), I (v, ) and I (v, Ω ) are proposed. Under these different sets of imputation and pre-imputation, we define many kinds of anti-cores and pre-anti-cores

Mathematics 2018, 6, 255 25 of 26 Ĉ(v; µ, ν) and Ĉ (v; µ, ν), respectively, where µ is an ordering and ν is a strict ordering given by µ,,, Ω, Ω, Ω and ν,,,, Ω, Ω, Ω, Ω. Then the cores and pre-cores are defined to be the complement sets of anti-cores and pre-anti-cores, respectively, under the sets of imputations; that is, we have C(v; µ, ν) = I(µ) \ Ĉ(v; µ, ν) and C (v; µ, ν) = I (µ) \ Ĉ(v; µ, ν). We also consider the solution concepts of dominance cores DC(v; µ, ν, λ) and pre-dominance cores DC (v; µ, ν, λ) where µ, λ,,, Ω, Ω, Ω and ν,,,, Ω, Ω, Ω, Ω. Since the difference of any two closed intervals is not in a natural sense, the Hukuhara difference is considered, which leads to the different solution concepts of H-cores C H (v; µ, ν), H-pre-cores C H (v; µ, ν), H-dominance cores DC H(v; µ, ν, λ) and H-dominance pre-cores DC H (v; µ, ν, λ). The purpose of this paper is to establish the inclusion and equality relations between the cores and dominance core by referring to Theorems 1 3, and between the pre-cores and dominance pre-core by referring to Theorems 4 6. Funding: This research received no external funding. Acknowledgments: The author would like to thank the reviewers for providing the useful comments that definitely improve this paper. Conflicts of Interest: The author declares no conflict of interest. References 1. von Neumann, J.; Morgenstern, O. Theory of Games and Economic Behavior; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 1944. 2. Nash, J.F. Two-Person Cooperative Games. Econometrica 1953, 21, 128 140. [CrossRef] 3. Young, H.P. Monotonic Solutions of Cooperative Games. Int. J. Game Theory 1985, 14, 65 72. [CrossRef] 4. Fernández, F.R.; Puerto, J.; Zafra, M.J. Cores of Stochastic cooperative games. Int. Game Theory Rev. 2002, 4, 265 280. [CrossRef] 5. Granot, D. Cooperative games in stochastic characteristic function form. Manag. Sci. 1977, 23, 621 630. [CrossRef] 6. Suijs, J.P.; Borm, P.; De Waegenaere, A.; Tijs, S. Cooperative games with stochastic payoffs. Eur. J. Operat. Res. 1999, 13, 193 205. [CrossRef] 7. Chakrabarti, S.K. Pure Strategy Markov Equilibrium in Stochastic Games with a Continuum of Players. J. Math. Econ. 2003, 39, 693 724. [CrossRef] 8. Alvarez-Mena, J.; Hernández-Lerma, O. Existence of Nash Equilibria for Cosntrained Stochastic Games. Math. Methods Oper. Res. 2006, 63, 261 285. [CrossRef] 9. Dshalalow, J.H.; Huang, W. On Noncooperative Hybrid Stochastic Games. Nonlinear Anal. Hybrid Syst. 2008, 2, 803 811. [CrossRef] 10. Dekel, E.; Fudenberg, D.; Levine, D.K. Learning to Play Bayesian Games. Games Econ. Behav. 2004, 46, 282 303. [CrossRef] 11. Guo, X.; Yang, J. A New Condition and Approach for Zero-Sum Stochastic Games with Average Payoffs. Stoch. Anal. Appl. 2008, 26, 537 561. [CrossRef] 12. Puerto, J.; Fernandez, F.R.; Hinojosa, Y. Partially ordered cooperative games: extended core and Shapley value. Ann. Oper. Res. 2008, 158, 143 159. [CrossRef] 13. Moore, R. Methods and Applications of Interval Analysis; SIAM: Philadelphia, PA, USA, 1979.

Mathematics 2018, 6, 255 26 of 26 14. Branzei, R.; Branzei, O.; Alparslan Gok, S.Z.; Tijs, S. Cooperative Interval Games: A Survey. Cent. Eur. J. Oper. Res. 2010, 18, 397 411. [CrossRef] 15. Alparslan Gok, S.Z.; Branzei, R.; Tijs, S. The Interval Shapley Value: An Axiomatization. Cent. Eur. J. Oper. Res. 2010, 18, 131 140. [CrossRef] 16. Mallozzi, L.; Scalzo, V.; Tijs, S. Fuzzy Interval Cooperative Games. Fuzzy Sets Syst. 2011, 165, 98 105. [CrossRef] 17. Alparslan Gök, S.Z.; Branzei, O.; Branzei, R.; Tijs, S. Set-Valued Solution Concepts Using Interval-Type Payoffs for Interval Games. J. Math. Econ. 2011, 47, 621 626. [CrossRef] 18. Branzei, R.; Dimitrov, D.; Tijs, S. Shapley-like values for interval bankruptcy games. Econ. Bull. 2003, 3, 1 8. 19. Mares, M. Fuzzy Cooperative Games; Springer: Berlin, Germany, 2001. 20. Han, W.-B.; Sun, H.; Xu, G.-J. A New Approach of Cooperative Interval Games: The Interval Core and Shapley Value Revisited. Oper. Res. Lett. 2012, 40, 462 468. [CrossRef] 21. Alparslan Gok, S.Z.; Branzei, R.; Tijs, S. Convex Interval Games. J. Appl. Math. Decis. Sci. 2009, 2009. [CrossRef] 22. Branzei, R.; Alparslan Gok, S.Z.; Branzei, O. Cooperation Games Under Interval Uncertainty: On the Convexity of the Interval Undominated Cores. Cent. Eur. J. Oper. Res. 2011, 19, 523 532. [CrossRef] 23. Li, D.F. Models and Methods of Interval-Valued Cooperative Games In Economic Management; Springer: Berlin, Germany, 2016. 24. Hong, F.X.; Li, D.F. Nonlinear Programming Method for Interval-Valued N-Person Cooperative Games. Oper. Res. 2017, 17, 479 497. [CrossRef] 25. Li, D.F.; Ye, Y.F. Interval-valued least square prenucleolus of interval-valued cooperative games and a simplified method. Oper. Res. 2018, 18, 205 220. [CrossRef] 26. Meng, F.; Chen, X.; Tan, C. Cooperative Fuzzy Games with Interval Characteristic Functions. Oper. Res. 2016, 16, 1 24. [CrossRef] c 2018 by the authors. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).