From the microscopic to the macroscopic world. Kolloqium April 10, 2014 Ludwig-Maximilians-Universität München. Jean BRICMONT

Similar documents
UNDERSTANDING BOLTZMANN S ANALYSIS VIA. Contents SOLVABLE MODELS

MACROSCOPIC VARIABLES, THERMAL EQUILIBRIUM. Contents AND BOLTZMANN ENTROPY. 1 Macroscopic Variables 3. 2 Local quantities and Hydrodynamics fields 4

G : Statistical Mechanics Notes for Lecture 3 I. MICROCANONICAL ENSEMBLE: CONDITIONS FOR THERMAL EQUILIBRIUM Consider bringing two systems into

Classical Statistical Mechanics: Part 1

Statistical Mechanics

III. Kinetic Theory of Gases

Basic Concepts and Tools in Statistical Physics

Lecture 8. The Second Law of Thermodynamics; Energy Exchange

Physics 172H Modern Mechanics

Mathematical Structures of Statistical Mechanics: from equilibrium to nonequilibrium and beyond Hao Ge

Lecture 8. The Second Law of Thermodynamics; Energy Exchange

A Deeper Look into Phase Space: The Liouville and Boltzmann Equations

Boltzmann s dilemma an introduction to statistical mechanics via the Kac ring

Workshop on Heterogeneous Computing, 16-20, July No Monte Carlo is safe Monte Carlo - more so parallel Monte Carlo

Lecture 9 Examples and Problems

Boltzmann and the Interpretation of Entropy

213 Midterm coming up

Entropy and irreversibility in gas dynamics. Joint work with T. Bodineau, I. Gallagher and S. Simonella

Equilibrium. Chapter Introduction

From the universe to subsystems: Why quantum mechanics appears more stochastic than classical mechanics

Statistical thermodynamics for MD and MC simulations

Finite Ring Geometries and Role of Coupling in Molecular Dynamics and Chemistry

BOLTZMANN ENTROPY: PROBABILITY AND INFORMATION

Typicality, Irreversibility and the Status of Macroscopic Laws

G : Statistical Mechanics

Beyond the Second Law of Thermodynamics

CHAPTER 9. Microscopic Approach: from Boltzmann to Navier-Stokes. In the previous chapter we derived the closed Boltzmann equation:

Chapter 20 The Second Law of Thermodynamics

Lecture Notes Set 3b: Entropy and the 2 nd law

Emergent proper+es and singular limits: the case of +me- irreversibility. Sergio Chibbaro Institut d Alembert Université Pierre et Marie Curie

Deriving Thermodynamics from Linear Dissipativity Theory

Entropy for Mathematicians or... The final Blaubeuren chapters

On the role of Decoherence in Bohmian Mechanics

Lecture 25 Goals: Chapter 18 Understand the molecular basis for pressure and the idealgas

arxiv: v1 [cond-mat.stat-mech] 9 Oct 2014

Time in Bohmian Mechanics

Dr.Salwa Alsaleh fac.ksu.edu.sa/salwams

6.730 Physics for Solid State Applications

Statistical Physics. The Second Law. Most macroscopic processes are irreversible in everyday life.

Irreversibility. Have you ever seen this happen? (when you weren t asleep or on medication) Which stage never happens?

Macroscopic time evolution and MaxEnt inference for closed systems with Hamiltonian dynamics. Abstract

Chapter 1 Direct Modeling for Computational Fluid Dynamics

Non-equilibrium phenomena and fluctuation relations

Quantum Thermodynamics

PAPER No. 6: PHYSICAL CHEMISTRY-II (Statistical

Boltzmann s Dilemma: An Introduction to Statistical Mechanics via the Kac Ring

Physics, Time and Determinism

(# = %(& )(* +,(- Closed system, well-defined energy (or e.g. E± E/2): Microcanonical ensemble

B.2 Mechanical and thermal modes

Let s start by reviewing what we learned last time. Here is the basic line of reasoning for Einstein Solids

Introduction Statistical Thermodynamics. Monday, January 6, 14

The Search for a Fundamental Theory of the Universe

ON THE ARROW OF TIME. Y. Charles Li. Hong Yang

Derivation of the GENERIC form of nonequilibrium thermodynamics from a statistical optimization principle

Math 456: Mathematical Modeling. Tuesday, April 9th, 2018

Thermodynamics of feedback controlled systems. Francisco J. Cao

2017, James Sethna, all rights reserved. This exercise was developed in collaboration with Christopher Myers.

Irreversibility and the Second Law in Thermodynamics and Statistical Mechanics

IV. Classical Statistical Mechanics

Hydrodynamics, Thermodynamics, and Mathematics

Physics 9 Wednesday, February 29, 2012

Entropy. Physics 1425 Lecture 36. Michael Fowler, UVa

Derivation of the Boltzmann Distribution

Boltzmann, Gibbs, and the Concept of Equilibrium

Chapter 9: Statistical Mechanics

Before you begin read these instructions carefully.

84 My God, He Plays Dice! Chapter 12. Irreversibility. This chapter on the web informationphilosopher.com/problems/reversibility

Heat Machines (Chapters 18.6, 19)

2m + U( q i), (IV.26) i=1

The need for something else: Entropy

Physics 207 Lecture 25. Lecture 25, Nov. 26 Goals: Chapter 18 Understand the molecular basis for pressure and the idealgas

Statistical Mechanics

Physics 106b: Lecture 7 25 January, 2018

Where is quantum theory headed?

Time-Dependent Statistical Mechanics 5. The classical atomic fluid, classical mechanics, and classical equilibrium statistical mechanics

Grand Canonical Formalism

Contact Geometry of Mesoscopic Thermodynamics and Dynamics

Khinchin s approach to statistical mechanics

Chemistry 2000 Lecture 9: Entropy and the second law of thermodynamics

Biology as Information Dynamics

2 Equations of Motion

CHEM-UA 652: Thermodynamics and Kinetics

Thermodynamics. Energy is driving life. Energy of sun ultimately drives most of life on Earth

arxiv: v2 [cond-mat.stat-mech] 30 Jun 2011

Time asymmetry in nonequilibrium statistical mechanics

Groups, entropies and Einstein s likelihood functions

ChE 503 A. Z. Panagiotopoulos 1

1 Phase Spaces and the Liouville Equation

Irreversible Processes

Definite Integral and the Gibbs Paradox

Biology as Information Dynamics

The general reason for approach to thermal equilibrium of macroscopic quantu

Thermodynamics: Entropy

Introduction to the Renormalization Group

H-Theorems from Autonomous Equations. Wojciech De Roeck 1, Christian Maes 2 Instituut voor Theoretische Fysica, K.U.

Thermodynamics: More Entropy

Guided Inquiry Worksheet 2: Interacting Einstein Solids & Entropy

Thermodynamics: More Entropy

25.1 Ergodicity and Metric Transitivity

Rubber elasticity. Marc R. Roussel Department of Chemistry and Biochemistry University of Lethbridge. February 21, 2009

Transcription:

From the microscopic to the macroscopic world Kolloqium April 10, 2014 Ludwig-Maximilians-Universität München Jean BRICMONT Université Catholique de Louvain

Can Irreversible macroscopic laws be deduced from or reduced to Reversible microscopic laws? (definitions later)

Brief answer (goal of this talk) : Yes, but in a certain sense, to be made precise. The basic idea goes back to Boltzmann, but there are also many pseudo-solutions, confused answers etc. Very little is on firm mathematical grounds

Consider classical mechanics. Given x(t) = (q(t), p(t)) for a (closed) mechanical system, q = the positions of the particles p = the momenta of the particles, then everything follows. In particular, macroscopic quantities, like the density or the energy density, are functions of x.

Simple example of macroscopic equation : diffusion d dt u = u u = u(x, t), x R 3. Let u = density (or energy density). u = example of macroscopic variable. Same idea with Navier-Stokes, Boltzmann... u(x, t) constant as t

Ω Ω = PHASE SPACE R 6N N AVOGADRO n << N Ex : F n CELLS F (x) = (F 1 (x),...; F n (x)) R n = fraction of particles in each cell U(x) in diffusion equation is a continuous approximation to F.

Simple example Coin tossing x (H, T, T, H...) 2 N possible values F (x) = Number of heads or tails = N possible values N << 2 N.

x(0) x(t) = T t x(0) F 0 F t Is the evolution of F Hamilton AUTONOMOUS, i.e. independent of the x mapped onto F? x(0) x(t) Reversible : IT t I x(t) = x(0) I(q, p) = (q, p) But F 0 F t often irreversible, as in the example of diffusion. F t UNIFORM DISTRIBUTION (in R 3!) There is no I operation that leaves the diffusion equation invariant.

Besides, the evolution of F is NOT autonomous! Time evolution of a system of 900 particles all interacting via the same potential. Half of the particles are colored white, the other half black. All velocities are reversed at t = 20, 000. The system then retraces its path and the initial state is fully recovered. But at t = 20, 000, the density is uniform both for the configuration obtained at that time and for the one with the reversed velocities.

So, the evolution of the macroscopic variable CANNOT be autonomous. PARADOX? Basis of the Solution The map F is many to one in a way that depends on value taken by F. Think of coin tossing F = N one configuration F = N 2 2N N configurations

A coarse-graining of phase space into regions corresponding to states that are macroscopically indistinguishable from one another.

As time evolves, the phase-space point enters compartments of larger and larger volume.

CONSIDER A CONCRETE EXAMPLE THE KAC RING MODEL ( ( ( i 1 ( i i + 1 i + 2 N points 1 particle at each point SIGN η i (t) = +1 η i (t) = 1 M CROSSES ε i = +1 = scatterers ε i 1 = 1

( i 1 ( ( ( i i + 1 i + 2 Dynamics TURN CHANGE SIGN when particle goes through a cross. So, e.g. η i (t + 1) = η i 1 (t) η i+1 (t + 2) = η i (t + 1) η i (t) = η i 1 (t 1)ε i 1 = NEWTON S EQUATION

DETERMINISTIC ISOLATED REVERSIBLE : IF, AFTER TIME t, PARTICLES START TO MOVE BACKWARD, THEY GO BACK TO THE INITIAL STATE IN TIME t. EVERY CONFIGURATION IS PERIODIC OF PERIOD 2N << 2 N = # STATES (THIS IS MUCH STRONGER THAN POINCARE S RECURRENCES OR LACK OF ERGODICITY).

CONVERGENCE TO EQUILIBRIUM? N + = N N MACROSCOPIC VARIABLES N + = N = N 2 = EQUILIBRIUM START WITH N + (0) = N

( CONFIGURATION OF PERIOD 4 ( ( ( NO CONVERGENCE TO EQUILIBRIUM Convergence to equilibrium CANNOT hold for all initial conditions, i.e. for all distributions of crosses.

1. BOLTZMANN N + (t + 1) = N + (t) N + (S, t) + N (S, t) N (t + 1) = N (t) N (S, t) + N + (S, t) WHERE N + (S, t) DENOTES THE NUMBER OF + SIGNS THAT HAVE A CROSS (OR SCATTERER) AHEAD OF THEM (AND, THUS WILL CHANGE SIGN AT THE NEXT TIME STEP). N (S, t) IS SIMILAR. ASSUME N + (S, t) = M N N +(t) N (S, t) = M N N (t) MOLECULAR CHAOS : SIGN UNCORRELATED WITH CROSSES

1 ( ) N + (t + 1) N (t + 1) N ( = 1 2M ) ( N + (t) N (t)) N 1 ( ) ( N + (t) N (t) = 1 2M ) t N N ( ) N + (0) = N N (0) = 0 We may assume M N < 1/2. EQUILIBRIUM!

BOLTZMANN S ENTROPY ( N S B (t) = ln N (t) ) ( ) N! = ln N (t)!n + (t)! MAXIMUM for N = N + = N 2 = EQUILIBRIUM

MICROSCOPIC THEORY 1. Eq. of MOTION η i (t) = η i 1 (t 1)ε i 1 i-1 ( i

i-1 ( i SOLUTION η i (t) = η i t (0)ε i 1 ε i 2... ε i t MOD N BUT MACROSCOPIC VARIABLES = FUNCTIONS OF THE MICROSCOPIC ONES

1 N (N +(t) N (t)) = 1 N = 1 N N η i (t) i=1 N η i t (0)ε i 1 ε i 2... ε i t i=1 IF we look at t = 2N : PROBLEM (PERIODICITY) TAKE t << N, e.g. t = 10 6. N 10 23.

Then, one can show, by the law of large numbers, that, for the overwhelming majority of microscopic initial configurations, i.e. of distributions of crosses, 1 ( ) ( N + (t) N (t) 1 2M N N ) t, i.e. the macrostate follows the solution of the Boltzmann approximation. So, the microstate does, in the overwhelming majority of cases, move towards larger regions of phase space.

N - N + - N 1 period 4 Vast majority of trajectories 1 2 3 4 t Solution of Boltzmann s equation 2N

As time evolves, the phase-space point enters compartments of larger and larger volume.

Solution to the reversibility paradox, in general Ω 0 = F 1 (F 0 ), given F 0 Ω 0 Ω 0 good configurations, meaning that x Ω 0 F 0 = F(x) F t ACCORDING TO THE MACROSCOPIC LAW

In Kac s model : Ω 0 = all signs are + and all configurations of scatterers. Ω 0 = all signs are + and the scatterers belong to that overwhelming majority of configurations of scatterers, discussed above. Ω t with time S t = k ln Ω t BOLTZMANN S ENTROPY ( ) N In Kac s model : S t = k ln Ω t = ln N (t) ( N = ln N + (t) ).

Ω 0 Ω 0 Ω 0 T t Ω 0 I T t Ω 0 Ω t I T t Ω 0 Ω t But I T t Ω 0 = Ω 0 << Ω t

T t Ω 0 Ω t for t not too large (BECAUSE OF POINCARE S RECURRENCE, OR PERIODICITY IN THE KAC MODEL) I T t Ω 0 Ω t I T t Ω 0 Ω t BECAUSE T t I T t Ω 0 Ω 0 Since IT t I T t Ω 0 = Ω 0, by reversibility. Not a paradox, because I T t Ω 0 = Ω 0, by Liouville, and Ω 0 Ω 0 << Ω t, so that Ω t \Ω t MAY still be small. Real mathematical problem : need to show that Ω t \Ω t small for all times (not too large). Easy for the Kac s model, hard for a real dynamical system, but no difference in principle, from a physical point of view.

Often misunderstood Irreversibility is either true on all levels or on none : It cannot emerge as out of nothing, on going from one level to another I. PRIGOGINE and I. STENGERS Irreversibility is therefore a consequence of the explicit introduction of ignorance into the fundamental laws M. BORN Gibbs was the first to introduce a physical concept which can only be applied to an object when our knowledge of the object is incomplete. W. HEISENBERG

It is somewhat offensive to our thought to suggest that, if we know a system in detail, then we cannot tell which way time is going, but if we take a blurred view, a statistical view of it, that is to say throw away some information, then we can. H. BONDI In the classical picture, irreversibility was due to our approximations, to our ignorance. I. PRIGOGINE

Misleading solution Appeal to ergodicity (Almost) every trajectory in the big phase space Ω will spend in each region of that space a fraction of time proportional to its size (i.e. Lebesgue volume). Shows too much and too little!

Too much : we are not interested in the time spent in every tiny region of the phase space Ω! Too little : ergodicity, by itself says nothing about time scales. We want the macroscopic quantities (and only them!) to reach equilibrium reasonably fast.

DOES THIS EXPLAIN IRREVERSIBILITY AND THE SECOND LAW? WHAT DO YOU MEAN BY EXPLAIN?

IN A DETERMINISTIC FRAMEWORK : IF THE LAWS IMPLY THAT A STATE A AT TIME ZERO YIELDS A STATE B AT TIME t, THEN B AT TIME t IS EXPLAINED BY THE LAWS AND BY A AT TIME ZERO. OF COURSE, IT REMAINS TO EXPLAIN A.

IN A PROBABILISTIC FRAMEWORK : IF F 0 IS A MACROSTATE AT TIME ZERO, THEN THERE IS A NATURAL MEASURE (THE ONE WITH MAXIMAL ENTROPY) ON THE CORRESPONDING SET F 1 (F 0 ) OF MICROSTATES x 0. IF, WITH LARGE PROBABILITY WITH RESPECT TO THAT MEASURE, THE MACROSTATE F(x t ) OBTAINED FROM THE EVOLUTION OF THE MICROSTATE x t EQUALS F t, THEN F 0 AND THE LAWS EXPLAIN F t. ANOTHER WAY TO SAY THIS, IS THAT ONE EXPLAINS F t, IF, BY A BAYESIAN REASONING, ONE WOULD HAVE PREDICTED F t, KNOWING ONLY F 0 AT TIME 0.

WHY DOESN T THIS ARGUMENT APPLY TO THE PAST?

REAL PROBLEM ORIGIN of the LOW ENTROPY STATES

The sun and the cycle of life

God choosing the initial conditions of the universe, in a volume of size 10 10123 of the total volume (according to R. Penrose). There is no good answer to that problem.