Well Ordered Sets (continued)

Similar documents
Initial Ordinals. Proposition 57 For every ordinal α there is an initial ordinal κ such that κ α and α κ.

Math 455 Some notes on Cardinality and Transfinite Induction

Axioms for Set Theory

ADVANCED CALCULUS - MTH433 LECTURE 4 - FINITE AND INFINITE SETS

20 Ordinals. Definition A set α is an ordinal iff: (i) α is transitive; and. (ii) α is linearly ordered by. Example 20.2.

Cardinality and ordinal numbers

Appendix to Basic cardinal arithmetic

Notes on ordinals and cardinals

5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting

MATH 3300 Test 1. Name: Student Id:

SETS AND FUNCTIONS JOSHUA BALLEW

Short notes on Axioms of set theory, Well orderings and Ordinal Numbers

NOTES ON WELL ORDERING AND ORDINAL NUMBERS. 1. Logic and Notation Any formula in Mathematics can be stated using the symbols

Well-Ordered Sets, Ordinals and Cardinals Ali Nesin 1 July 2001

Notes. Functions. Introduction. Notes. Notes. Definition Function. Definition. Slides by Christopher M. Bourke Instructor: Berthe Y.

Axioms of separation

Topological properties

3. Abstract Boolean Algebras

MAGIC Set theory. lecture 6

Short Introduction to Admissible Recursion Theory

Seminaar Abstrakte Wiskunde Seminar in Abstract Mathematics Lecture notes in progress (27 March 2010)

Basic set-theoretic techniques in logic Part III, Transfinite recursion and induction

Part II Logic and Set Theory

Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras

A topological set theory implied by ZF and GPK +

Part II. Logic and Set Theory. Year

Outside ZF - Set Cardinality, the Axiom of Choice, and the Continuum Hypothesis

A BRIEF INTRODUCTION TO ZFC. Contents. 1. Motivation and Russel s Paradox

2. Two binary operations (addition, denoted + and multiplication, denoted

Equivalent Forms of the Axiom of Infinity

This paper is also taken by Combined Studies Students. Optional Subject (i): Set Theory and Further Logic

4 Countability axioms

Principles of Real Analysis I Fall I. The Real Number System

(D) Introduction to order types and ordinals

Linear Algebra. Chapter 5

CORES OF ALEXANDROFF SPACES

Math 280A Fall Axioms of Set Theory

Class Notes on Poset Theory Johan G. Belinfante Revised 1995 May 21

Topology. Xiaolong Han. Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA address:

MAT115A-21 COMPLETE LECTURE NOTES

MATH FINAL EXAM REVIEW HINTS

A NEW SET THEORY FOR ANALYSIS

Chapter 1 : The language of mathematics.

Meta-logic derivation rules

Section 31. The Separation Axioms

CITS2211 Discrete Structures (2017) Cardinality and Countability

1 Take-home exam and final exam study guide

Foundations of Mathematics MATH 220 FALL 2017 Lecture Notes

Contents. Index... 15

Functions as Relations

Sets, Structures, Numbers

MAT 570 REAL ANALYSIS LECTURE NOTES. Contents. 1. Sets Functions Countability Axiom of choice Equivalence relations 9

ALL NORMAL EXTENSIONS OF S5-SQUARED ARE FINITELY AXIOMATIZABLE

LECTURE 3 Matroids and geometric lattices

Faithful embedding on finite orders classes

Let us first solve the midterm problem 4 before we bring up the related issues.

Connectedness. Proposition 2.2. The following are equivalent for a topological space (X, T ).

Sets, Logic and Categories Solutions to Exercises: Chapter 2

A Logician s Toolbox

FORCING WITH SEQUENCES OF MODELS OF TWO TYPES

Logic and Mathematics:

Solutions to Homework Set 1

2. Prime and Maximal Ideals

Review of Linear Algebra

Course 212: Academic Year Section 1: Metric Spaces

Theory Combination. Clark Barrett. New York University. CS357, Stanford University, Nov 2, p. 1/24

DO FIVE OUT OF SIX ON EACH SET PROBLEM SET

AN EXPLORATION OF THE METRIZABILITY OF TOPOLOGICAL SPACES

SOLUTIONS TO ADDITIONAL EXERCISES FOR II.1 AND II.2

Chapter One. The Real Number System

3 COUNTABILITY AND CONNECTEDNESS AXIOMS

Introduction to Topology

4 Linear operators and linear functionals

Sets, Models and Proofs. I. Moerdijk and J. van Oosten Department of Mathematics Utrecht University

MATH 102 INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICAL ANALYSIS. 1. Some Fundamentals

Multivalued functions in digital topology

Math 3140 Fall 2012 Assignment #3

Connectivity and tree structure in finite graphs arxiv: v5 [math.co] 1 Sep 2014

1.2 Functions What is a Function? 1.2. FUNCTIONS 11

Chapter 1. Sets and Numbers

Lecture 2. (1) Every P L A (M) has a maximal element, (2) Every ascending chain of submodules stabilizes (ACC).

Filters in Analysis and Topology

Countability. 1 Motivation. 2 Counting

(1) Which of the following are propositions? If it is a proposition, determine its truth value: A propositional function, but not a proposition.

Two sets X, Y have the same cardinality (cardinal number, cardinal),

Metric spaces and metrizability

Solutions to Homework Problems

Introduction to Set Theory

Math 4606, Summer 2004: Inductive sets, N, the Peano Axioms, Recursive Sequences Page 1 of 10

Isomorphisms between pattern classes

Chapter 1. Logic and Proof

arxiv:cs/ v1 [cs.cc] 9 Feb 2007

Introduction to Metalogic 1

TOPOLOGY HW 2. x x ± y

Properties of the Integers

Discrete Mathematics: Lectures 6 and 7 Sets, Relations, Functions and Counting Instructor: Arijit Bishnu Date: August 4 and 6, 2009

SOME TRANSFINITE INDUCTION DEDUCTIONS

a + b = b + a and a b = b a. (a + b) + c = a + (b + c) and (a b) c = a (b c). a (b + c) = a b + a c and (a + b) c = a c + b c.

Math 203A - Solution Set 4

Math 4603: Advanced Calculus I, Summer 2016 University of Minnesota Notes on Cardinality of Sets

Transcription:

Well Ordered Sets (continued) Theorem 8 Given any two well-ordered sets, either they are isomorphic, or one is isomorphic to an initial segment of the other. Proof Let a,< and b, be well-ordered sets. Let d be such that d / b (take e.g. d = b). Define f : a b {d} to satisfy { the least element in b\rng(f ax ) if b\rng(f a f(x) = x ) d otherwise (12) The existence of such f is guaranteed by the previous theorem 1 since for each x from the well ordered set a, f(x) is uniquely determined in terms of x and f a x. Observe that if x 1, x 2 a and x 1 < x 2 then a x1 a x2 so and hence we have b\rng(f a x2 ) b\rng(f a x1 ) either both f(x 1 ) and f(x 2 ) are in b and f(x 1 ) f(x 2 ), (f(x 2 ) b\rng(f a x2 ) and f(x 1 ) Rng(f a x2 ) so f(x 1 ) f(x 2 )) or only f(x 1 ) is in b and f(x 2 ) = d, or f(x 1 ) = f(x 2 ) = d. Define g = f (a b), i.e. g(x) = f(x) except when f(x) = d in which case x / Dom(g). Let s = Dom(g), t = Rng(g). If x 1,x 2 a, x 2 s and x 1 < x 2 then x 1 s by the above observation. Also, if y 1, y 2 b, y 2 t and y 1 y 2 then y 1 t since if y 2 = f(x) for some x in a then y 1 must be in Rng(f a x ). It follows by Example 6.2 that s = a or s = a x for some x a, and t = b or t = b y for some y b. Note that s is well ordered by the restriction of < to s and t is well ordered by the restriction of to t. g : s t is a bijection since it is surjective by definition of t and if x 1,x 2 s, x 1 x 2 then assuming without loss of generality that x 1 < x 2 we have f(x 1 ) f(x 2 ) by the above observation, so g an order preserving bijection and as such an isomorphism between s and t by Corollary 3. 1 For θ(x, u, y) we can take e.g. the formula [x a & Fn(u)&Dom(u) = a x & b\rng(u) &y = Lst(b\Rng(u))] [ (x a & Fn(u)&Dom(u) = a x & b\rng(u) )&y = d] where y = Lst(w) stands for y w &( z w) y z. It is easy to check that x u!yθ(x, u, y), and that for x a, (12) corresponds to θ(x, f a x, f(x)). 48

Since s = a or s = a x for some x a, and t = b or t = b y for some y b, and since the case of both s = a x and y = b y cannot occur (it would mean f(x) = d but b\rng(f a x ) ), the theorem follows. Corollary 4 If sets a and b can be well ordered then either a b or b a. Consequently, if all sets can be well ordered then for any two sets a, b we have a b or b a. Later, we will show the converse: if a b or b a for any two sets a, b, then every set can be well ordered! The statement that all sets can be well ordered is usually referred to as the Well Ordering Theorem (WOT) and the statement that for any two sets a, b we have a b or b a is referred to as the Law of Trichotomy (LOT). Hence we have shown that it follows from out axioms that WOT implies LOT and we will soon show that is also follows that LOT implies WOT. (However, neither can be proved in ZF. We will return to this later.) Proposition 45 (i) Let a be a set well-ordered by and let f : a a be order-preserving. Then x f(x) for each x a. (ii) There can be no order-preserving injective function from a well ordered set to an initial segment of it. Proof (i) Assume that the statement does not hold and let c = {x a f(x) x}. Note that c is non-empty since for some x a, x f(x) does not hold, and is total. Let x 0 be the least element of c. We have f(x 0 ) x 0 so since f is injective and order preserving also f(f(x 0 )) f(x 0 ) but that means f(x 0 ) c and f(x 0 ) x 0, contradicting the choice of x 0 as the least element in c. (ii) Let a be well ordered by, x a. If f was an order preserving injective function from a to a x then f(x) x which contradicts (i). Corollary 5 The isomorphism in Theorem 8 is unique. Proof See Example 6.4. Ordinals Well-ordered sets generalize the notion of counting as represented by natural numbers, when counting is understood as arranging elements in order, starting from a first one and proceeding in discrete steps. Assuming again we have N for the moment, note that for any finite set there is (up to isomorphism) only one way to count it: if n N and a set a has n elements and a, is well ordered then a, is isomorphic to N n < bytheorem 8, and because finite sets can only be equinumerous if they have the same number 49

of elements. However, we have seen that on N there can be essentially different well-orderings (cf. Example 5.4(ii)). Non-isomorphic well-orderings correspond to essentially different outcomes we may get when counting sets. Isomorphic well orderings share an important feature, similarly to equinumerous sets having the same cardinality. We say that isomorphic well ordered sets have the same order type. We could proceed similarly as before and talk about an order type being that which is shared by isomorphic well-ordered sets. However, we are now in a position to say exactly what we mean, and define a unique set representing each such class of isomorphic well orderings. When we have done it, we will proceed to use it to define what we mean by cardinal numbers, too. Definition 20 Let a be a set. Then a is the relation on a defined by a = { x,y x,y a &x y}. a is irreflexive on a by virtue of the Axiom of Foundation, but in general it is not transitive nor total. We shall be interested in special sets which are totally ordered by a. First we point out some properties of sets a totally ordered by a. Lemma 9 Let a be a set such that a totally orders a, and let b a and w b. Then w is the least element of b (with respect to a ) if and only if w b =. Proof w is the least element of b just when ( y b) (y = w w a y) which, by virtue of a being total, is equivalent to any of the following ( y b) y a w ( y b) y w w b =. Corollary 6 A set a is totally ordered by a if and only if it is well ordered by it. Proof This follows by the above Lemma and the Axiom of Foundation. Corollary 7 A set a is totally ordered by a if and only if For all x,y a, exactly one of x = y, x y, y x holds. (OT) Proof By the previous Corollary and Proposition 42 (since (OT) implies the existence of a least elements for any non-empty set subset of a, as in the proof of Lemma 9). Definition 21 A set a is transitive if it contains all elements of its elements, that is, ( x a) x a. 50

Warning The terminology is established but potentially confusing: to say that a relation is transitive is not the same thing as saying that a set is transitive (even though any relation is also a set!). It is always clear from the context what is meant. Definition 22 A set a is an ordinal if it is transitive and totally ordered by a = { x,y x,y a&x y} Proposition 46 If a is an ordinal then a is well ordered by a. Proof From Corollary 6. We remark that when Axiom of Foundation is not assumed, an ordinal is usually defined as a transitive set a which is well ordered by a. As Proposition 46 shows, in ZF this is equivalent to our definition. Proposition 47 A set a is an ordinal if and only if it is transitive and For all x,y a, exactly one of x = y, x y, y x holds. Proof From Corollary 7. (OT) For example,, { }, {, { }}, {, { }, {, { }}} are ordinals. We will use lower case Greek letters α, β, γ,δ,... for ordinals. Let Ord stand for the class of all ordinals. We will write Ord(x) to mean x is an ordinal. We will need the following properties of ordinals. Recall that x y stands for x y and x y. Proposition 48 Let α,β be ordinals, d a set. (i) If d α then d α. (ii) If d α then d Ord. (iii) β α β α. (iv) Exactly one of α β, α = β, β α holds. Proof (i) By transitivity of α, if d α then d α. Equality would mean d d, which cannot be by the Axiom of Foundation. (ii) Suppose that d α, and y d and z y. By transitivity of α we know that z,y, d α, so by transitivity of α, z d and hence d is a transitive set. Suppose that z, y d. By transitivity of α we also have z, y α and consequently, (OT) holds for d because it holds for α. The result follows by Proposition 47. 51

(iii) The implication = follows from (i). Suppose β α. Then α\β so let δ α\β be such that δ (α\β) =. (Note that δ is an ordinal by (ii).) We shall show that β = δ (and hence since δ α, also β α.) If λ δ then λ α (by transitivity of α). Also, λ / α\β because δ (α\β) =, so we must have λ β. If λ β then since β α, we have λ α. Hence by (OT) for α, exactly one of λ δ, λ = δ, δ λ holds. It cannot be λ = δ since λ β α so λ / (α\β) but δ (α\β) and it cannot be δ λ since that would mean δ β by transitivity of β but δ (α\β). Hence λ δ, as required. (iv) It is impossible to have two of them holding by the Axiom of Foundation. Hence it suffices to prove that it cannot be the case that none of them holds. Assume α / β and α β. Then by (iii) α β so α\β is a non-empty subset of α. Let δ α\β be such that δ (α\β) =. If γ δ then γ α by transitivity of α, so γ β since δ (α\β) =. Consequently, δ β and hence by part (iii), δ = β or δ β. The latter is impossible since δ α\β, so δ = β and hence β α, as required. Theorem 9 The class of all ordinals Ord is a proper class. Proof Assume that Ord is a set. Then Ord is an ordinal by Propositions 47 and 48(ii),(iv) so Ord Ord which cannot be by the Axiom of Foundation. Like for a set, define Ord to be { β, α α,β Ord & β α}. Ord is a proper class (exercise). For α Ord let Ord α = {β β Ord & β Ord α}. By Proposition 48 (ii), Ord α = {x x α} = α, that is, the predecessors of α in Ord are just the elements of α. If γ Ord then for α, β γ we have α,β Ord and It follows that β γ α β α β Ord α. α = Ord α = γ α. Ord is usually replaced by <. So for α,β Ord, α Ord β, α β, α < β all stand for the same thing. As usual, α β stands for α < β α = β. Proposition 49 (i) Let α be an ordinal. Then α {α} is an ordinal, denoted α + 1. (ii) Let b be a set of ordinals. Then b is an ordinal. (iii) Let b be a non-empty set of ordinals. Then b is an ordinal and it is equal to the least element of b. 52

Proof Example 6.5. Theorem 10 Let b be a set well ordered by. Then there exists a unique ordinal α such that b, is isomorphic to α, α. Proof Let f be the unique function with domain b guaranteed by Theorem 7 satisfying f(x) = Rng(f b x ) for all x b. First note that f is a bijection between b and Rng(f): it is obviously surjective. If x, y b, x y then x b y so f(x) Rng(f b y ) = f(y) and hence f is injective (since x y means x y or y x so f(x) f(y) or f(y) f(x), either of which incompatible with f(x) = f(y) by virtue of the Axiom of Foundation). Also, as above, for x,y b, x y = f(x) f(y). Conversely, if f(x) f(y) then since f(y) = Rng(f b y ) = {f(z) z b & z y}, and f is injective, we have x y. Hence f is an isomorphism between b, and Rng(f), Rng(f). Consequently, Rng(f) satisfies (OT) because is total. It is clearly a transitive set so by Proposition 47 it is an ordinal. The uniqueness of α follows from the fact that there can be no isomorphism between two distinct ordinals (given two distinct ordinals, one must be an initial segment of the other and by Proposition 45(ii) no well-ordered set is isomorphic to an initial segment of itself). If b, was isomorphic to ordinals α and β then α and β would be isomorphic. Definition 23 If b, is a well ordered set then the unique ordinal α isomorphic to b, is called the order type of b,. Proposition 50 If b is a set, γ an ordinal and b γ then b can be well ordered (so that the order type of this ordering is less or equal to γ). Proof We can obtain a well ordering for b from f : b γ as in the Proposition 44. Note that f is then order preserving. Let α be the order type of b, and let g be an isomorphism between α, < and b,. Then we have α γ, since if not then α > γ, so γ = α γ and f g is an order preserving injection from α to an initial segment of itself which cannot be by Lemma 45(ii). Theorem 11 (Hartogs Theorem) Given any set b there is an ordinal α such that not α b. Proof First notice that d = { x, x b & is a well ordering of x } 53

is a set (please check it as an exercise, using the Separation and other Axioms), and by Theorem 10 for every x, d there is a unique ordinal α isomorphic to it. By the Replacement Axiom, the collection of such ordinals is a set, call it c. Now assume that for every ordinal α we have α b, so for every ordinal α there is a subset x of b such that x α. As in Proposition 44, we can define a well ordering on x so that x, is isomorphic to α. But that means that every ordinal is in c, which contradicts Theorem 9. As a consequence, we get the promised result about the Law of Trichotomy implying the Well Ordering Theorem: Assume LOT holds. Let b be a set and α is an ordinal such that α b does not hold, then b α and hence b can be well ordered by Proposition 50. Definition 24 Let α be an ordinal, α. If there is an ordinal β such that α = β {β} then we say that α is a successor ordinal and we write α = β + 1. Otherwise α is a limit ordinal. Note that if α = β {β} then β α, i.e β < α and there is no γ such that β < γ < α (otherwise β γ and γ β {β} which by β γ gives β γ, γ β, contradicting the Axiom of Foundation). It follows that β + 1 is the immediate successor of β. Proposition 51 If γ,β are ordinals such that γ + 1 = β + 1 then γ = β. Proof Assume γ + 1 = β + 1 and γ β. Then γ < β or β < γ so assume without loss of generality that γ < β. It follows that γ < β < β + 1 = γ + 1 which contradicts γ + 1 being the immediate successor of γ. If α = β {β} then β is denoted α 1 and referred to as the immediate predecessor of α. Each successor ordinal has an immediate predecessor but limit ordinals do not. Proposition 52 If α is a limit ordinal then α = α = {β β < α}. Proof By Proposition 49(ii), γ = {β β < α} is an ordinal, and since α is transitive, γ α If δ α then δ {δ} α since α is not a successor so δ α = γ, that is α γ. It follows that γ = α as required. We have seen examples of successor ordinals (, { }, {, { }}) {, { }, {, { }}}...). Now we will use the Axiom of Infinity to prove that there is a limit ordinal. Definition 25 A set x is called an inductive set if x and y (y x = y {y} x). 54

Let ω = {x x is an inductive set} = {z x (x is an inductive set = z x)}. Then ω is a set by the Separation Axiom since if a is an inductive set (which is guaranteed to exist by the Axiom of infinity) then Clearly, ω is an inductive set. ω = {z a x(x is an inductive set = z x)}. Proposition 53 ω is an ordinal. Proof Since is an ordinal, we can see from Proposition 49(i) that ω Ord is an inductive set, so since ω is the intersection of all inductive sets, we must have ω Ord. Hence by Proposition 48(iv) ω satisfies (OT). The set c = {α ω α ω} is an inductive set since clearly c and if α c then α ω, α ω so α {α} ω and α {α} ω (as ω is inductive) and hence α {α} c. It follows that c = ω, so ω is transitive. Note that ω is not a successor ordinal since if it was equal to γ {γ} for some γ then γ would be an element of ω so since ω is inductive, we would have ω = γ {γ} ω. Every element of ω other than is a successor ordinal, since otherwise the predecessors of a limit ordinal α ω would form an inductive set strictly included in ω, which cannot be. We will now postpone further study of larger ordinals and concentrate on ω showing that it provides the promised representation of N in ZF and using it to obtain Z, Q and R, too. 55