What is the right type-space? Humboldt University. July 5, John T. Baldwin. Which Stone Space? July 5, Tameness.

Similar documents
June 28, 2007, Warsaw

Morley s Proof. Winnipeg June 3, 2007

Disjoint n-amalgamation

March 3, The large and small in model theory: What are the amalgamation spectra of. infinitary classes? John T. Baldwin

AMS regional meeting Bloomington, IN April 1, 2017

Non-Elementary Classes 2007

The Vaught Conjecture Do uncountable models count?

Examples of Non-locality

Examples of Non-locality

October 12, Complexity and Absoluteness in L ω1,ω. John T. Baldwin. Measuring complexity. Complexity of. concepts. to first order.

Independence in tame abstract elementary classes

Does set theoretic pluralism entail model theoretic pluralism? III. The entanglement of infinitary logic and set theory Aberdeen

Amalgamation, Absoluteness, and Categoricity

The Rocky Romance of Model Theory and Set Theory

Generalized Quantifiers, Infinitary Logics, and Abstract Elementary Classes

Introduction to Model Theory

The Vaught Conjecture Do uncountable models count?

N AS AN ABSTRACT ELEMENTARY CLASS

Notes on Quasiminimality and Excellence

The Rocky Romance of Model Theory and Set Theory University of Helsinki

SHELAH S EVENTUAL CATEGORICITY CONJECTURE IN UNIVERSAL CLASSES

Almost Galois ω-stable classes

CHAINS OF SATURATED MODELS IN AECS

Disjoint amalgamation in locally finite AEC

Foundations. September 4, Foundations. A Model Theoretic Perspective. John T. Baldwin. sociology. Thesis I. Thesis II. A Concept Analysis

The Vaught Conjecture Do uncountable models count?

CATEGORICITY FROM ONE SUCCESSOR CARDINAL IN TAME ABSTRACT ELEMENTARY CLASSES

TAMENESS FROM TWO SUCCESSIVE GOOD FRAMES

More Model Theory Notes

Generalizing abstract model theory. an eye toward applications

MATHEMATICS: CONCEPTS, AND FOUNDATIONS Vol. II - Model Theory - H. Jerome Keisler

Löwenheim-Skolem Theorems, Countable Approximations, and L ω. David W. Kueker (Lecture Notes, Fall 2007)

Measures in model theory

ON THE STRUCTURE OF CATEGORICAL ABSTRACT ELEMENTARY CLASSES WITH AMALGAMATION

Amalgamation, Absoluteness, and Categoricity

Automorphism Groups of Homogeneous Structures

Tame definable topological dynamics

AN INTRODUCTION TO EXCELLENT CLASSES INTRODUCTION

A Hanf number for saturation and omission: the superstable case

SUPERSTABILITY IN ABSTRACT ELEMENTARY CLASSES

Abstract Elementary Classes: Some Answers, More Questions

GOOD FRAMES IN THE HART-SHELAH EXAMPLE

arxiv: v2 [math.lo] 16 Oct 2015

SUPERSTABILITY IN ABSTRACT ELEMENTARY CLASSES

2.2 Lowenheim-Skolem-Tarski theorems

TOWARD A STABILITY THEORY OF TAME ABSTRACT ELEMENTARY CLASSES

A SURVEY ON TAME ABSTRACT ELEMENTARY CLASSES. Contents

FORKING IN SHORT AND TAME ABSTRACT ELEMENTARY CLASSES

SOME USES OF SET THEORY IN ALGEBRA. Stanford Logic Seminar February 10, 2009

GOOD FRAMES IN THE HART-SHELAH EXAMPLE

ω-stable Theories: Introduction

Part II. Logic and Set Theory. Year

Applications of model theory in extremal graph combinatorics

Classifying classes of structures in model theory

Model Theory MARIA MANZANO. University of Salamanca, Spain. Translated by RUY J. G. B. DE QUEIROZ

VC-dimension in model theory and other subjects

Computability theory and uncountable structures

Continuum Harvard. April 11, Constructing Borel Models in the. Continuum Harvard. John T. Baldwin. University of Illinois at Chicago

Statue of Aristotle at the Aristotle University of Thessaloniki, Greece

Pseudo-finite model theory

Introduction. Itaï Ben-Yaacov C. Ward Henson. September American Institute of Mathematics Workshop. Continuous logic Continuous model theory

SATURATION AND SOLVABILITY IN ABSTRACT ELEMENTARY CLASSES WITH AMALGAMATION

Definably amenable groups in NIP

Categoricity. John T. Baldwin, Department of Mathematics, Statistics and Computer Science, University of Illinois at Chicago

Model Theory and Forking Independence

On Kim-independence in NSOP 1 theories

Harmonious Logic: Craig s Interpolation Theorem and its Descendants. Solomon Feferman Stanford University

INTRODUCTION TO GEOMETRIC STABILITY

GENERALIZED AMALGAMATION IN SIMPLE THEORIES AND CHARACTERIZATION OF DEPENDENCE IN NON-ELEMENTARY CLASSES

Model Theory of Differential Fields

Three Red Herrings around Vaught s Conjecture

Scott Sentences in Uncountable Structures

SHELAH S CATEGORICITY CONJECTURE FROM A SUCCESSOR FOR TAME ABSTRACT ELEMENTARY CLASSES

A stability transfer theorem in d-tame Metric Abstract Elementary Classes

Three Red Herrings around Vaught s Conjecture

DOWNWARD CATEGORICITY FROM A SUCCESSOR INSIDE A GOOD FRAME

Disjoint amalgamation in locally finite AEC

Mekler s construction and generalized stability

Advances in Classification Theory for Abstract Elementary Classes

tp(c/a) tp(c/ab) T h(m M ) is assumed in the background.

Part II Logic and Set Theory

Introduction to Model Theory

MORLEY S CATEGORICITY THEOREM

SOME PROJECTIVE PLANES OF LENZ-BARLOTTI CLASS I

THE METAMATHEMATICS OF RANDOM GRAPHS

Citation 数理解析研究所講究録 (2012), 1794:

Algebras with finite descriptions

MODEL THEORY OF GROUPS (MATH 223M, UCLA, SPRING 2018)

MODEL THEORY FOR ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY

arxiv: v4 [math.lo] 23 Jul 2016

Categoricity in homogeneous complete metric spaces

MULTIPLE CARDINALITIES

The rise and fall of uncountable models

Basics of Model Theory

TRANSFERING SATURATION, THE FINITE COVER PROPERTY, AND STABILITY

PRESERVATION THEOREMS IN LUKASIEWICZ MODEL THEORY

FINITE MODEL THEORY (MATH 285D, UCLA, WINTER 2017) LECTURE NOTES IN PROGRESS

TEST GROUPS FOR WHITEHEAD GROUPS

SHELAH S SINGULAR COMPACTNESS THEOREM

Transcription:

Goals The fundamental notion of a Stone space is delicate for infinitary logic. I will describe several possibilities. There will be a quiz.

Infinitary Logic and Omitting Types Key Insight (Chang, Lopez-Escobar) Any sentence φ of L ω1,ω can be coded by omitting a set of types in a countable first order theory.

Reduction (Shelah) Any κ-categorical sentence of L ω1,ω can be replaced (for categoricity purposes) by considering the atomic models of a first order theory, T. A model A M = T is atomic if every finite sequence from A realizes a principal (isolated) type over the empty set.

Our Context T is a countable first order theory that admits quantifier elimination. K is the class of atomic models of T. K is elementary submodel.

AMALGAMATION PROPERTY The class K satisfies the amalgamation property if for any situation with A, M, N K: N A M there exists an N 1 such that N A M N 1

ZILBER S PROGRAM FOR (C, +,, exp) Goal: Realize (C, +,, exp) as a model of an L ω1,ω-sentence discovered by the Hrushovski construction. Objective A Expand (C, +, ) by a unary function f which behaves like exponentiation using a Hrushovski-like dimension function. Prove some L ω1,ω-sentence Σ satisfied by (C, +,, f ) is categorical and has quantifier elimination. Objective B Prove (C, +,, exp) is a model of the sentence Σ found in Objective A.

Assumption K has the amalgamation property over models and the joint embeddding property. This is a highly nontrivial assumption; it follows from categoricity up to ℵ ω and the WGCH. Amalgamation over arbitrary subsets is a still stronger hypothesis which misses mathematically important examples.

The Monster Model If K has the amalgamation property and the joint embedding property then we can work inside a monster model (universal domain) M that is M -model homegeneous. That is, If N K M and N K M K and M < M there is embedding of M into M over N.

Stone Space I Ordinary S(A) Let A M K. A syntactic 1-type is an ultrafilter in the Boolean algebra of 1-ary formulas with parameters from A. S(A) is the set of types over A. Since T eliminates quantifiers there is no dependence on the choice of M.

Stone Space II S (A) Let p S(A) where A is atomic. Definition p S (A) means there is an atomic model M of T with A M such that p is realized in M.

Stone Space III S at (A) Let p S(A) where A is atomic. Definition p S at (A) means Aa is atomic if a realizes p.

Simple Example Wake up! T is the theory of an infinite set under equality. M = T. p asserts x m for every m M. Then p S at (M).

Complicated Example Fact (Marcus): There is a model M which is atomic, minimal and contains an infinite indiscernible set.

Complicated Example Fact (Marcus): There is a model M which is atomic, minimal and contains an infinite indiscernible set. Consequences monster model for K?

Complicated Example Fact (Marcus): There is a model M which is atomic, minimal and contains an infinite indiscernible set. Consequences monster model for K? Every p S at (M) is realized in M.

Complicated Example Fact (Marcus): There is a model M which is atomic, minimal and contains an infinite indiscernible set. Consequences monster model for K? Every p S at (M) is realized in M. This does not mean: For any A M, every p S at (A) is realized in M.

Stone Space IV S M (A) Fix a monster model M of K. Let p S(A) where A M. Definition p S M (A) means that p is realized in M.

Question S M (A) Fix a monster model M of K. What are the relations among S M (A), S (A), S at (A), S(A)? Does the cardinality of A matter?

Observations means proper subset. Always S M (A) S (A) S at (A) S(A)

Observations means proper subset. Always S M (A) S (A) S at (A) S(A) Usually S at (A) S(A)

Observations means proper subset. Always S M (A) S (A) S at (A) S(A) Usually S at (A) S(A) Marcus S M (A) S (A)

Observations means proper subset. Always S M (A) S (A) S at (A) S(A) Usually S at (A) S(A) Marcus S M (A) S (A) A-countable S (A) = S at (A)

Stone Space V: Galois Types S(A) Fix a monster model M of K. Definition Let A M K M and a M. The Galois type of a over M ( M) is the orbit of a under the automorphisms of M which fix A. The set of Galois types over A is denoted S(A).

Stone Space V: Galois Types: Subtleties Over sets Clearly, for fixed M, there exists π : S(A) S M (A). But there is a choice of M. In general the relation between S(A) and S at (A) is unclear. Over models But for models: π : S(M) S at (M). There is only one monster model. And Shelah s notion corresponds to the monster model version.

GALOIS TYPES: General Form Define: (M, a, N) = (M, a, N ) if there exists N and strong embeddings f, f taking N, N into N which agree on M and with f (a) = f (a ).

GALOIS TYPES: General Form Define: (M, a, N) = (M, a, N ) if there exists N and strong embeddings f, f taking N, N into N which agree on M and with f (a) = f (a ). The Galois type of a over M in N is the same as the Galois type of a over M in N if (M, a, N) and (M, a, N ) are in the same class of the equivalence relation generated by =.

GALOIS TYPES: Algebraic Form Suppose K has the amalgamation property. Definition Let M K, M K M and a M. The Galois type of a over M is the orbit of a under the automorphisms of M which fix M. We say a Galois type p over M is realized in N with M K N K M if p N.

Galois vrs Syntactic Types Syntactic types have certain natural locality properties. locality Any increasing chain of types has at most one upper bound; tameness two distinct types differ on a finite set; compactness an increasing chain of types has a realization. The translations of these conditions to Galois types do not hold in general.

Grossberg and VanDieren focused on the idea of studying tame abstract elementary classes: Definition We say K is (χ, µ)-tame if for any N K with N = µ if p, q, S(N) and for every N 0 N with N 0 χ, p N 0 = q N 0 then q = p.

-Algebraic form Suppose K has the amalgamation property. K is (χ, µ)-tame if for any model M of cardinality µ and any a, b M:

-Algebraic form Suppose K has the amalgamation property. K is (χ, µ)-tame if for any model M of cardinality µ and any a, b M: If for every N K M with N χ there exists α aut N (M) with α(a) = b, then there exists α aut M (M) with α(a) = b.

Consequences of Suppose K has arbitrarily large models and amalgamation. Theorem (Grossberg-Vandieren) If λ > LS(K), K is λ + -categorical and (λ, < )-tame then K is categorical in all θ λ +. Theorem (Lessmann) If K with LS(K) = ℵ 0 is ℵ 1 -categorical and (ℵ 0, )-tame then K is categorical in all uncountable cardinals

Two Examples that are not tame 1 Hiding the zero For each k < ω a class which is (ℵ 0, ℵ k 3 )-tame but not (ℵ k 3, ℵ k 2 )-tame. -Kolesnikov (building on Hart-Shelah) 2 Coding EXT A class that is not (ℵ 0, ℵ 1 )-tame. A class that is not (ℵ 0, ℵ 1 )-tame but is (2 ℵ 0, )-tame. (-Shelah)

Very Complicated Example Theorem. [Hart-Shelah / -Kolesnikov] For each 3 k < ω there is an L ω1,ω sentence φ k such that: 1 φ k has the disjoint amalgamation property; 2 Syntactic types determine Galois types over models of cardinality at most ℵ k 3 ; 3 But there are syntactic types over models of size ℵ k 3 that split into 2 ℵ k 3-Galois types.

Very Complicated Example Theorem. [Hart-Shelah / -Kolesnikov] For each 3 k < ω there is an L ω1,ω sentence φ k such that: 1 φ k has the disjoint amalgamation property; 2 Syntactic types determine Galois types over models of cardinality at most ℵ k 3 ; 3 But there are syntactic types over models of size ℵ k 3 that split into 2 ℵ k 3-Galois types. 4 φ k is categorical in µ if µ ℵ k 2 ; 5 φ k is not ℵ k 2 -Galois stable; 6 But for m k 3, φ k is ℵ m -Galois stable; 7 φ k is not categorical in any µ with µ > ℵ k 2.

Some further consequences In this example: 1 π : S(M) S M (A) is not 1-1. 2 There exists an independent pair of countable models M 1, M 2 over M 2 so that S at (M 1 M 2 ) = 2 ℵ 0 The last example exhibits the failure of automorphism stationarity. If M 1 M 1 over M 0 and both are independent from M 2 over M 0 then they are isomorphic over M 0. But in 2) they need not be automorphic over M 0.

One more inequality The Marcus example gives an uncountable atomic set A which cannot be embedded in an atomic model. In fact, S (A) S at (A). From the -Kolesnikov analysis there is a model M with S (M) S at (M).

Locality and Definition K has (κ, λ)-local galois types if for every continuous increasing chain M = i<κ M i of members of K with M = λ and for any p, q S(M): if p M i = q M i for every i then p = q. Lemma If λ κ and cf(κ) > χ, then (χ, λ)-tame implies (κ, λ)-local. If particular, (ℵ 0, ℵ 1 )-tame implies (ℵ 1, ℵ 1 )-local.

Whitehead Groups Definition We say A is a Whitehead group if Ext(A, Z) = 0. That is, every short exact sequence 0 Z H A 0, splits or in still another formulation, H is the direct sum of A and Z.

Key Example Shelah constructed (page 228 of Eklof-Mekler, first edition) of a group with the following properties. Fact There is an ℵ 1 -free group G of cardinality ℵ 1 which is not Whitehead. Moreover, there is a countable subgroup R of G such that G/R is p-divisible for each prime p.

THE AEC EXAMPLE Let K be the class of structures M = G, Z, I, H, where each of the listed sets is the solution set of one of the unary predicates (G, Z, I, H). G is a torsion-free Abelian Group. Z is a copy of (Z, +). I is an index set and H is a family of infinite groups.

Each model in K consists of 1 a torsion free group G, 2 a copy of Z 3 and a family of extensions of Z by G. Each of those extensions is coded by single element of the model so the Galois type of a point of this kind represents a specific extension. The projection and embedding maps from the short exact sequence are also there.

M 0 K M 1 if M 0 is a substructure of M, but Z M 0 = Z M and G M 0 is a pure subgroup of G M 1.

NOT LOCAL Lemma (K, K ) is not (ℵ 1, ℵ 1 )-local. That is, there is an M 0 K of cardinality ℵ 1 and a continuous increasing chain of models M 0 i for i < ℵ 1 and two distinct types p, q S(M 0 ) with p M 0 i = q M i for each i. Let G be an Abelian group of cardinality ℵ 1 which is ℵ 1 -free but not a Whitehead group. There is an H such that, is exact but does not split. 0 Z H G 0

WHY? Let M 0 = G, Z, a, G Z

WHY? Let M 0 = G, Z, a, G Z M 1 = G, Z, {a, t 1 }, {G Z, H}

WHY? Let M 0 = G, Z, a, G Z M 1 = G, Z, {a, t 1 }, {G Z, H} M 2 = G, Z, {a, t 2 }, {G Z, G Z}

WHY? Let M 0 = G, Z, a, G Z M 1 = G, Z, {a, t 1 }, {G Z, H} M 2 = G, Z, {a, t 2 }, {G Z, G Z} Let p = tp(t 1 /M 0, M 1 ) and q = tp(t 2 /M 0, M 2 ). Since the exact sequence for H M2 splits and that for H M1 does not, p q.

NOT ℵ 1 -LOCAL But for any countable M 0 K M 0, p M 0 = q M 0, as 0 Z H i G 0. (1) splits. G = G(M 0 ), H = π 1 (t i, G ).

NOT ℵ 0 -TAME It is easy to see that if (K, K ) is (ℵ 0, ℵ 0 )-tame then it is (ℵ 1, ℵ 1 )-local, so (K, K ) is not (ℵ 0, ℵ 0 )-tame. So in fact, (K, K ) is not (ℵ 0, χ)-tame for any χ.

Question Could this example be formulated more naturally as {Ext(G, Z) : G is torsion-free } (with projection and injection maps?

Incompactness Theorem Assume 2 ℵ 0 = ℵ 1, and ℵ1, S 2 where 1 S1 2 = {δ < ℵ 2 : cf(δ) = ℵ 1 }. Then, the last example fails either (ℵ 1, ℵ 1 ) or (ℵ 2, ℵ 2 )-compactness.

BECOMING TAME?? Grossberg and Van Dieren asked for (K, K ), and µ 1 < µ 2 so that (K, K ) is not (µ 1, )-tame but is (µ 2, )-tame.

Admits intersection We say the AEC (K, K ) admits intersections if for every X M K, there is a minimal closure of X in M. That is, M {N : X N K M} = cl M (X ) K M.

gained Theorem There is an AEC in a countable language that admits intersections with Löwenheim-Skolem number ℵ 0 which is not (ℵ 0, ℵ 1 )-tame but is (2 ℵ 0, )-tame. Proof Sketch: Repeat the previous example but instead of letting the quotient be any torsion free group 1 insist that the quotient is an ℵ 1 -free group; 2 add a predicate R for the group R G/R is divisible by every prime p where G is Shelah s example of a non-whitehead group. This forces G 2 ℵ 0 and then we get (2 ℵ 0, )-tame. But ℵ 1 -free groups fail amalgamation??

Lemma For any AEC (K, K ) which admits intersections there is an associated AEC (K, K ) with the same (non) locality properties that has the amalgamation property. Theorem There is an AEC with the amalgamation property in a countable language with Löwenheim-Skolem number ℵ 0 which is not (ℵ 0, ℵ 1 )-tame but is (2 ℵ 0, )-tame.

Conclusion S(M) is the natural tool for Abstract elementary classes. S at (M) is Shelah s tool for L ω1,ω. Excellence implies they agree. But Hytinnen and Kesala have interesting results with S M (A) for finitary AEC.