NOTES. Reconsidering Leibniz s Analytic Solution of the. Catenary Problem:

Similar documents
The Leibniz Catenary Construction: Geometry vs Analysis in the 17 th Century

How did Leibniz Solve the Catenary Problem? A Mystery Story

Math F15 Rahman

Ordinary Differential Equations (ODEs)

then the substitution z = ax + by + c reduces this equation to the separable one.

Methods of Integration

7.3 Hyperbolic Functions Hyperbolic functions are similar to trigonometric functions, and have the following

In these notes we will outline a proof of Lobachevskiĭ s main equation for the angle of parallelism, namely

Integration by Parts

Weekly Activities Ma 110

Chapter 6. Techniques of Integration. 6.1 Differential notation

2.1 How Do We Measure Speed? Student Notes HH6ed. Time (sec) Position (m)

Descartes s Logarithm Machine

Core A-level mathematics reproduced from the QCA s Subject criteria for Mathematics document

CHAPTER 1. 1 FORMS. Rule DF1 (Linearity). d(αu + βv) = αdu + βdv where α, β R. Rule DF2 (Leibniz s Rule or Product Rule). d(uv) = udv + vdu.

Chapter 6. Techniques of Integration. 6.1 Differential notation

Leibniz and the Discovery of Calculus. The introduction of calculus to the world in the seventeenth century is often associated

6.7 Hyperbolic Functions

Math 200 University of Connecticut

JUST THE MATHS UNIT NUMBER DIFFERENTIATION 4 (Products and quotients) & (Logarithmic differentiation) A.J.Hobson

Practice Problems: Integration by Parts

O1 History of Mathematics Lecture VI Successes of and difficulties with the calculus: the 18th-century beginnings of rigour

MATH 18.01, FALL PROBLEM SET # 2

m(x) = f(x) + g(x) m (x) = f (x) + g (x) (The Sum Rule) n(x) = f(x) g(x) n (x) = f (x) g (x) (The Difference Rule)

AN INTRODUCTION TO CURVILINEAR ORTHOGONAL COORDINATES

EXAMPLES OF PROOFS BY INDUCTION

2009 A-level Maths Tutor All Rights Reserved

Integrals. D. DeTurck. January 1, University of Pennsylvania. D. DeTurck Math A: Integrals 1 / 61

Chapter 1. Complex Numbers. 1.1 Complex Numbers. Did it come from the equation x = 0 (1.1)

Review for Final Exam, MATH , Fall 2010

PURE MATHEMATICS AM 27

Math 201 Solutions to Assignment 1. 2ydy = x 2 dx. y = C 1 3 x3

Calculus II. Calculus II tends to be a very difficult course for many students. There are many reasons for this.

Definition: A vector is a directed line segment which represents a displacement from one point P to another point Q.

DIFFERENTIATION RULES

Be prepared to take a test covering the whole assignment in September. MATH REVIEW

Candidates are expected to have available a calculator. Only division by (x + a) or (x a) will be required.

MATH10000 Mathematical Workshop Project 2 Part 1 Conic Sections

AP-1 Physics. Summer 2016 Assignment Date Period. Name: What is due the first day of school? When is this assignment due? MATH REVIEW =

Chapter 2: Differentiation

1MA1 Introduction to the Maths Course

Essential Mathematics 2 Introduction to the calculus

Chapter 0.B.3. [More than Just] Lines.

I. Content Standard: Number, Number Sense and Operations Standard

The Integers. Peter J. Kahn

Module 3: Cartesian Coordinates and Vectors

Mathematics Notes for Class 12 chapter 7. Integrals

Time: 1 hour 30 minutes

Math RE - Calculus II Antiderivatives and the Indefinite Integral Page 1 of 5

1 Functions of many variables.

The Integers. Math 3040: Spring Contents 1. The Basic Construction 1 2. Adding integers 4 3. Ordering integers Multiplying integers 12

{ }. The dots mean they continue in that pattern to both

Week beginning Videos Page

INTEGRATING RADICALS

AP Physics 1 Summer Assignment 2016

Welcome to Math 104. D. DeTurck. January 16, University of Pennsylvania. D. DeTurck Math A: Welcome 1 / 44

Alabama Course of Study: Mathematics Precalculus

Prentice Hall Geometry (c) 2007 correlated to American Diploma Project, High School Math Benchmarks

In today s world, people with basic calculus knowledge take the subject for granted. As

Particles in Motion; Kepler s Laws

Assignment. Disguises with Trig Identities. Review Product Rule. Integration by Parts. Manipulating the Product Rule. Integration by Parts 12/13/2010

7.1 Indefinite Integrals Calculus

2602 Mark Scheme June Mark Scheme 2602 June 2005

MATHEMATICAL METHODS (CAS) Written examination 1

2 Recollection of elementary functions. II

5.2 Proving Trigonometric Identities

3. On the grid below, sketch and label graphs of the following functions: y = sin x, y = cos x, and y = sin(x π/2). π/2 π 3π/2 2π 5π/2

Vectors and Fields. Vectors versus scalars

Time: 1 hour 30 minutes

CHAPTER 1: Functions

Correlation of 2012 Texas Essential Knowledge and Skills (TEKS) for Algebra I and Geometry to Moving with Math SUMS Moving with Math SUMS Algebra 1

(1) Recap of Differential Calculus and Integral Calculus (2) Preview of Calculus in three dimensional space (3) Tools for Calculus 3

1.4 Techniques of Integration

LIMITS, AND WHAT THEY HAVE TO DO WITH CONTINUOUS FUNCTIONS

Mathematics 102 Fall 1999 The formal rules of calculus The three basic rules The sum rule. The product rule. The composition rule.

this cover and their final version of the extended essay to are not

Limits and Continuity

Week 2 Techniques of Integration

THE LOGIC OF COMPOUND STATEMENTS

x 1 x 2. x 1, x 2,..., x n R. x n

To Be (a Circle) or Not to Be?

1. Introduction to commutative rings and fields

The Continuing Story of Zeta

Chapter 2: Differentiation

MA 460 Supplement: Analytic geometry

DIFFERENTIATION RULES

APPENDIX 2.1 LINE AND SURFACE INTEGRALS

Solving Equations by Adding and Subtracting

6x 2 8x + 5 ) = 12x 8. f (x) ) = d (12x 8) = 12

UNDETERMINED COEFFICIENTS SUPERPOSITION APPROACH *

Series Solutions of ODEs. Special Functions

Further mathematics. AS and A level content

Spring Homework Part B Packet. MAT Calculus I

The Not-Formula Book for C2 Everything you need to know for Core 2 that won t be in the formula book Examination Board: AQA

7 TRIGONOMETRIC IDENTITIES AND EQUATIONS

Final Examination Solutions

AP Physics 1 Summer Assignment 2017

Geometry beyond Euclid

BHASVIC MαTHS. Skills 1

Solving Algebraic Equations in one variable

Transcription:

NOTES Reconsidering Leibniz s Analytic Solution of the Catenary Problem: The Letter to Rudolph von Bodenhausen of August 1691 Mike Raugh January 3, 017

Leibniz published his solution of the catenary problem as a classical ruler-and-compass construction in the June 1691 issue of Acta Eruditorum, without comment about the analysis used to derive it. 1 However, in a private letter to Rudolph Christian von Bodenhausen later in the same year he explained his analysis. Here I take up Leibniz s argument at a crucial point in the letter to show that a simple observation leads easily and much more quickly to the solution than the path followed by Leibniz. The argument up to the crucial point affords a showcase in the techniques of Leibniz s calculus, so I take advantage of the opportunity to discuss it in the Appendix. Leibniz begins by deriving a differential equation for the catenary, which in our modern orientation of an x y coordinate system would be written as, dy dx = n a (n = dx + dy ), (1) where (x, z) represents cartesian coordinates for a point on the catenary, n is the arc length from that point to the lowest point, the fraction on the left is a ratio of differentials, and a is a constant representing unity used throughout the derivation to maintain homogeneity. 3 The equation characterizes the catenary, but to solve it n must be eliminated. 1 Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm, De linea in quam flexile se pondere curvat in Die Mathematischen Zeitschriftenartikel, Chap 15, pp 115 14, (German translation and comments by Hess und Babin), Georg Olms Verlag, 011. I thank Professor Eberhard Knobloch for citing this work and discussing it with me at his office in Berlin. Professor Knobloch is director of the Alexander von Humboldt Research Centre of the Berlin-Brandenburg Academy of Sciences, and head of the math and technical-scientific sections of the Academy edition of the works of Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz. Letter in German to Rudolf Christan von Bodenhausen, Wolfenbutel, 10/0 August 1691, and in the attached Latin text Analysis problemas catenari, both printed in G. W. Leibniz, Sämtliche Schriften und Briefe, series III, volume 5 (003), p. 143-155; http://www.gwlb.de/leibniz/leibnizarchiv/veroeffentlichungen/iii5a.pdf. I thank Dr. Siegmund Probst of the Leibniz Archive at the Göttingen Academy of Science for bringing this letter to my attention, for a rush translation into English of the Latin text and for a helpful exchange of emails. 3 The same equation was found by Johann Bernoulli in his solution of the catenary problem. See the translation by William A. Ferguson, Jr. at, http://www.1stcenturysciencetech.com/translations/bernoulli.pdf. The equation is a consequence of the parallelogram law of statics and the fact that tension must act in the direction of the tangent. 1

With some algebraic manipulation of Equation 1 using second differentials and integration that Leibniz assumed his reader would understand, he showed that, dx = a dy ay + y () then, comparing this with Equation 1 and substituting z = y + a, concluded that n = z a. 4 The reader might think that this equation for n has allowed us to determine an arc length without the use of integration, but the derivation of Equation demonstrated in the Appendix does in fact require integration. My departure from Leibniz and simplification of the argument begins here, where Leibniz makes use of the product of z + n and z n: (z + n)(z n) = a. I assume, without essential loss of generality, that a = 1 and that for some yet unknown n we have, (z + n)(z n) = 1. (3) The product expressed by Equation 3 hints at a role for the exponential function z = e x, since, if we have p q = 1, we will have logarithms for p and q that are bilaterally symmetric about the origin. In our case, we would have, ln(z + n) = ln(z n). But the curve for z = e x is not bilaterally symmetric, so it cannot by itself represent a catenary. Let s try the next simplest thing: symmetrize the exponential by letting: 5 4 Leibniz s derivation of Equation from Equation 1 is a good example of his algebraic use of differentials. For this, and verification that Equation follows from Equation 1, see Appendix. 5 Testing simple guesses is a good technique for exploring groundwork in a difficult problem; by good luck the simplest guess for this problem yields the solution straight away. We recognize this from familiarity with the problem, but for full verification it is necessary to proceed with the argument.

z = ex + e x, This formula for z is bilaterally symmetric, so let us find an n such that Equation 3 is satisfied. The result is immediate and decisive, since, by Equation 3, n = z 1: ( ) e n x + e x ( ) e x e x = 1 =. We choose n = ex e x and conclude that dz = dy = n dx. This is the differential equation that Leibniz derived to characterize the catenary, where his n = arc length. But is the n we derived arc length too? Yes, it is, as can be shown easily from the above with these definitions and results: cosh x ex + e x, sinh x ex e x, dc = ds, cosh x sinh x = 1 So, for z = cosh x as above, Arc length = 1 + ( dz dx) = sinh x = n We have shown that dz = n, and now we know that our derived n = arc length. dx Therefore, this equation is equivalent to Equation 1, proving that z = cosh x is in fact a catenary. The identity cosh x sinh x = 1 validates Leibniz s claims about the right triangle laid out in his construction, with sides labeled in his figure as OA and AR, wherein OA = a, AR = n = arc length, and the length of the hypotenuse is z. 6 The triangle also contains the information needed to construct a tangent line to the catenary at the point (x, z), as explained by Leibniz in Acta Eruditorum. The argument used above to derive z = cosh x can be reworked with minor changes to 6 Leibniz, De linea in quam flexile se pondere curvat, cited above. 3

yield the formula for a general catenary: z = a cosh x a I conclude with these comments: The catenary presented by Leibniz in his construction stands out clearly as being based on the exponential function e x, labeled as his logarithmic curve. and his catenary is obviously the hyperbolic cosine not yet named as such. Some properties specified by Leibniz could not have been known without the use of calculus, e.g., the segment constructed equal in length to an arc. Before knowing about the von Bodenhausen letter, I had wondered what methods of analysis Leibniz used to discover his curve and its properties. It was a mystery for me until I hit upon a simple solution proceding from Equation 1 that reveals the role of the hyperbolic functions explicity, convincing me that the logarithm and exponential function were lying close enough to the surface to be found easily by Leibniz. 7 This note helps to make that more evident. Leibniz s construction reveals one of the ways he stood out in the late 17 th Century in which the Cartesian rules for defining curves in strict geometric terms were giving way to a newer conception that analytic definitions were also valid, more general and better suited to a wider range of problems in physics. 8 The dichotomy between geometry vs analysis stands out in the Leibniz construction because it is an impossiblity in the strict sense of a Euclidean ruler-and-compass construction. The fundamental reason is that e is not constructable because it is a transcendetal number; this is the same reason that it is impossible to square the circle, i.e., construct a square of 7 See http://www.mikeraugh.com/talks/rips-016-leibnizcatenary.pdf. 8 Bos, Henk J. M., Redefining Geomterical Exactness: Descarts Transformation of the Early Modern Concept of Construction, Springer, 001. 4

equal area, since π is transcendental. Nevertheless, the Leibniz construction is theoretically possible because it is based on two given line segments (D and K in one of the representations of his figure). Given segments D and K of the right ratio, his construction can proceed by strict use of a straightedge-andcompass, and in fact Leibniz made the necessary deus ex machina assumption equivalent to d/k = e. This could trouble geometers of the Descartes school, but not an analyst like Leibniz who accepted the tools of calculus as valid instruments for defining curves. Leibniz had found his catenary using analysis then presented it geometrically. 5

Appendix A Leibniz s derivation of Equation from Equation 1 is a good example of the use of differentials in his calculus. Before summarizing Leibniz, we will use the modern idiom of calculus to show that Equation is a consequence of Equation 1. Modern derivation. Taking into account that Equation 1 assumes that the lowpoint of the catenary is tangent to the x-axis, begin with: dy dx = y = n a. (y(0) = y (0) = 0) (A.1) Differentiation yields, y = n a = 1 a 1 + y. (A.) Squaring, differentiating and cancelling the redundant y, y = y a (A.3) Then integrating, y = y a + C (A.4) and comparing with Equation A. with simplifying algebra, arrive at, 6

( y a + C) = 1 a (1 + y ) (A.5) The initital conditions of Equation A. imply that C = 1. Feeding this back into Equation a A.5, we wind up with a result equivalent to Equation : y = y + ax (A.6) You will see next that the preceding derivation is essentially what Leibniz does in his own idiom. Leibniz s derivation. Before proceeding with the derivation of Equation from Equation 1 in his own idiom, it will be useful to illustrate some of the basic techniques Leibniz used. Liebniz postulated that differentials could be manipulated algebraically like actual numerical variables, although he understood them as a useful fiction. 1 Suppose that a curve is represented at points by an abscissa x and an ordinate y, in which the two are coordinated by analytic expressions, say f(x) and g(y), such that g(y) = f(x). If the respective differentials are, say, d g(y) = g (y) dy and d f(x) = f (x) dx where g and f are supposed known then the latter equality fixes the relationship between dy and dx at each point (x, y) of the curve but does not determine an absolute value for either dx or dy. This allowed Leibniz to specify one or the other for convenience, as will be illustrated below. For example, suppose y = x 3. Then dy = 3x dx. This equation itself can be differentiated using the product rule: ddy = 6x(dx) dx + 3x ddx. We could choose dx to be constant while still supposing that the equation dy = 3x dx holds and get the simpler result that 1 For a discussion in detail, see H. J. M. Bos, Differentials, Higher-Order Differentials and the derivative in the Leibnizian Calculus, in particular Sec..19, Archive for History of Exact Sciences, Vol. 14, Springer. The product rule: d (uv) = u dv+v du. Since dy is a legitimate variable, it has a differential: d du = dd u. The symbol dd indicates the differential of a differential, and so on for more-often repeated differentials, e.g., ddd u = d (ddu ). 7

ddy = 6x (dx). The process can be reversed by taking the anti-differential of both sides, recognizing that an undeternined constant must be restored after having been eliminated by the differentiation: dy = x 3 dx + Cdx, where a constant factor of the form Cdx (in which C is an ordinary number) was presumed present in the original expression and needed to be restored. 3 Here s another application that yields the differential of a quotient. Let w = u v. Multiply by v and differentiate: du = d wv = w dv + v dw = u v dv + vdw. The first and last members of the preceding equations imply that. dw = d u v = vdu udv v. Now we return to the problem of deriving Equation from Equation 1 using Leibniz s own idiom. Without loss of generality, simplify Equation 1 by letting a = 1 so that we may begin with dy dx = n and, by definition, n = (dx) + (dy). Leibniz chose dx to be a constant. We treat these two equations as follows. 1) Differentiate the first equation (regarding dx as constant), to get: ddy = dn dx. ) Differentiate the second equation, square it, and differentiate again (holding dx constant), to get: dn ddn = dy ddy. 3 So why not some higher power of dx, for example C(dx) 3? This appears to be heuristic in Leibniz in consideration of experience differentiating expressions of various types in which each separate act of differentiation adds just one d to each term of the resulting expression. For the case in point, only one d appears in dy = 3x dx, and so only one d should appear in the constant term Cdx. This idea works out in practice to produce correct results, and so the finer points of logic can be postponed for another generation of mathematicians. 8

Combine these two results to eliminate dn, arriving at: ddn = dy dx. Here Leibniz takes the anti-differential of both sides to get: dn = y dx+cdx, where C is a constant real number to be determined by initial conditions. By squaring both sides and using the definition of n again deduce that, (dx) + (dy) = (y + y + C ) (dx) = y = dy dx = y + y + C 1 The initial conditions y(0) = y (0) = 0 give us C = 1 and a result equivalent to Equation without the scaling factor a: dy dx = y + y. The reader may re-introduce a at the beginning of the derivation and derive Equation exactly. The fact that the square-root can be taken in either sense positive or negative reflects the fact that the catenary is bilaterally symmetric. 9