Mind Association. Oxford University Press and Mind Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Mind.

Similar documents
Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Philosophy of Science Association

The American Mathematical Monthly, Vol. 100, No. 8. (Oct., 1993), pp

Baker. 1. Classical physics. 2. Determinism

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Sklar s Maneuver. Bradford Skow ABSTRACT

The Philosophy of Physics. Special Relativity and Minkowski Spacetime

Philosophy of Science, Vol. 43, No. 4. (Dec., 1976), pp

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

A New Conception of Science

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Avoiding the Block Universe: A Reply to Petkov Peter Bokulich Boston University Draft: 3 Feb. 2006

Scientific Examination of Relativistic Velocity and Acceleration Addition. Copyright 2010 Joseph A. Rybczyk

Accelerated Observers

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

PHILOSOPHY OF PHYSICS (Spring 2002) 1 Substantivalism vs. relationism. Lecture 17: Substantivalism vs. relationism

Biometrika Trust. Biometrika Trust is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Biometrika.

What s Observable in Special and General Relativity?

16. Einstein and General Relativistic Spacetimes

Notes de lecture 357 PROCESS PHYSICS: FROM INFORMATION THEORY TO QUANTUM SPACE AND MATTER

MATHEMATICAL EXPLANATION AND INDISPENSABILITY ARGUMENTS

The spacetime of special relativity

Review of Gordon Belot, Geometric Possibility Oxford: Oxford UP, 2011

Reinterpreting Newton s Law of Gravitation. Copyright 2012 Joseph A. Rybczyk

Biometrika Trust. Biometrika Trust is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Biometrika.

Brown and Janssen on the Arrow of. Explanation in Special Relativity

05 the development of a kinematics problem. February 07, Area under the curve

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Relativistic Constant Acceleration Distance Factor. Copyright 2010 Joseph A. Rybczyk

The Econometric Society is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Econometrica.

The nature of Reality: Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen Argument in QM

Hyperbolic Geometry of 2+1 Spacetime: Static Hypertext Version

Introduction to General Relativity

Einstein for Everyone Lecture 6: Introduction to General Relativity

Hestenes lectures, Part 5. Summer 1997 at ASU to 50 teachers in their 3 rd Modeling Workshop

LIGHT SPEED CANNOT BE A UNIVERSAL CONSTANT

Euler s Galilean Philosophy of Science

Lecture 12: Arguments for the absolutist and relationist views of space

The Problem of Slowing Clocks in Relativity Theory

Einstein for Everyone Lecture 3: Special Relativity

Causal Explanation and Ontological Commitment. Mark Colyvan University of Tasmania

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 3: Analysis, Analytically Basic Concepts, Direct Acquaintance, and Theoretical Terms. Part 2: Theoretical Terms

What metaphysics of mass and other quantitative properties accounts for the use of numbers in science to measure those properties?

COPENHAGEN INTERPRETATION:

A BRIEF INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICAL RELATIVITY PART 1: SPECIAL RELATIVITY ARICK SHAO

ACTIVITY 5. Figure 5-1: Simulated electron interference pattern with your prediction for the next electron s position.

Gravitational Effects on Light Propagation. Copyright 2009 Joseph A. Rybczyk

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

Curved Spacetime... A brief introduction

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

Absolute motion versus relative motion in Special Relativity is not dealt with properly

In defence of classical physics

Special Relativity Lecture

Leibniz s Ultimate Theory Soshichi Uchii

Biometrika Trust. Biometrika Trust is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Biometrika.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Relativity and the Dimensionality of the World

Philosophy of Mathematics Intuitionism

Chapter 2 The Structure of the Theories of Physics

The Twin Paradox, Once More

Fundamental Orbital to Escape Velocity Relationship. Copyright 2009 Joseph A. Rybczyk

The Philosophy of Physics. Is Space Absolute or Relational?

PROOF-THEORETIC REDUCTION AS A PHILOSOPHER S TOOL

ON THE FAITHFUL INTERPRETATION OF PURE WAVE MECHANICS

The Periodogram and its Optical Analogy.

Physicalism Feb , 2014

Relativity, Dimensionality, and Existence

Special Theory of Relativity. A Brief introduction

Motion Fundamentals. 1 Postulates. 2 Natural Progression. Thomas Kirk

Spacetime and Reality: Facing the Ultimate Judge

Mobolaji Williams Motifs in Physics April 26, Effective Theory

The College Mathematics Journal, Vol. 24, No. 4. (Sep., 1993), pp

Detection of Influential Observation in Linear Regression. R. Dennis Cook. Technometrics, Vol. 19, No. 1. (Feb., 1977), pp

Kepler problem and Lorentz transformations

Hidden Parameters in the Universal Gravitational Constant

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

Relativity as the quantum mechanics of space-time. measurements

07. Interpreting Special Relativity 1. Two Interpretations of Special Relativity

Critical Notice: Bas van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective Oxford University Press, 2008, xiv pages

The Pound-Rebka Experiment as Disproof of Einstein s General Relativity Gravity Theory.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Universalism Entails Extensionalism

Relativistic Orbital Velocity. Copyright 2009 Joseph A. Rybczyk

Chapter One BASIC QUESTIONS

Mathematical Olympiad for Girls

Annals of Mathematics

ALBERT EINSTEIN AND THE FABRIC OF TIME by Gevin Giorbran

Boscovich s theory: strict Newtonian physics, by Roger J. Anderton

EXERCISES IN QUATERNIONS. William Rowan Hamilton. (The Cambridge and Dublin Mathematical Journal, 4 (1849), pp ) Edited by David R.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Scientific Explanation- Causation and Unification

THE SYDNEY SCHOOL AN ARISTOTELIAN REALIST PHILOSOPHY OF MATHEMATICS

Against Option 1, Healey notes that in non-abelian Yang-Mills theories, two distinct gauge potential fields may give rise to the same gauge

Relativity, Dimensionality, and Existence

Mathematical versus physical meaning of classical mechanics quantities

Transcription:

Mind Association Response to Colyvan Author(s): Joseph Melia Source: Mind, New Series, Vol. 111, No. 441 (Jan., 2002), pp. 75-79 Published by: Oxford University Press on behalf of the Mind Association Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/3093789 Accessed: 16/06/2010 14:54 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showpublisher?publishercode=oup. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. Oxford University Press and Mind Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Mind. http://www.jstor.org

Response to Colyvan JOSEPH MELIA In 'Weaseling Away the Indispensability Argument' (Melia 2000) I argued that although quantification over mathematical objects may indeed be indispensable to our scientific theories, it is not always intellectually dishonest to deny the existence of some of the objects over which we quantify. I argued also that, though the postulation of mathematical objects may increase the attractiveness or utility of our scientific theories, the way in which they do so is unlike the way in which the postulation of theoretical physical entities increases the utility of our scientific theories. Because of this, we can be justified in adopting different attitudes to the different entities postulated by our best scientific theories. In particular, we can have good reason for accepting the existence of theoretical physical entities, but little reason for accepting mathematical ones. Accordingly, I urged that the mere fact that we may have to quantify over mathematical objects in our best physical theory is not enough to establish that we ought to believe that there are such things as mathematical objects. Colyvan claims that, even if we accept my distinction between the different kinds of utility the postulation of physical and mathematical entities may afford, the indispensability argument still works (Colyvan 2002). For there are clear cases in which postulating mathematical entities has exactly the right kind of theoretical virtues. For instance, unificatory power is a clear virtue of a physical theory and postulating complex numbers can increase the unificatory power of a theory. Similarly, explanatory power of a theory is also a virtue of a theory and the Minkowski geometric explanation of certain relativistic effects gives us a clear example of an explanation that employs mathematical entities. In my view, Colyvan's strategy is the best way for those who want to defend the indispensability argument. Were there clear examples where the postulation of mathematical objects results in an increase in the same kind of utility as that provided by the postulation of theoretical entities, then it would seem that the same kind of considerations that Mind, Vol. 111. 441. January 2002? Oxford University Press 2002

76 Joseph Melia support the existence of atoms, electrons and space-time equally supports the existence of numbers, functions and sets. Colyvan is right that only by a careful analysis of the uses to which mathematics is put will we be able to judge whether or not the indispensability argument supports Platonism. However, the two particular examples cited by Colyvan fail to convince me that my beloved nominalism should be rejected. Colyvan writes 'the Minkowski geometric explanation of the Lorentz contraction is, arguably, a non-causal explanation (indispensably) employing mathematical entities such as the Minkowski metric'. I agree. The Minkowski explanation is a geometric explanation of relativistic effects-not a mathematical one. For Minkowski, it is the structure and properties of space-time which account for the fact that moving bodies appear to suffer a contraction, which accounts for the fact that moving clocks run slowly, which grounds the difference between an inertial frame and a non-inertial one. Minkowski's insight was that, by dropping our old and familiar geometric explanations in terms of spatial and temporal separation and replacing them with a new notion of spatio-temporal separation, we could give a simple geometric explanation of relativistic effects. True, when we come to give the geometric explanation of a certain relativistic fact, we may find ourselves indispensably using mathematical objects. But it doesn't follow from this that mathematical objects play a part in the explanation itself, or add to the explanatory power of the theory-for it may be that it is only by using mathematical objects that we are able to pick out a particular geometric property. This much is familiar even in the non-relativistic case: it may be the case that the explanation for some physical fact F is that a certain path P has a certain length. It may be the case that the only or the simplest or the most elegant way of picking out this length is to use a real number: the length is 12 as long as some standard metre. Accordingly, when we come to explain F, our best theory may offer as an explanation 'F occurred because P is 2 metres long'. But we all recognize that, though the number 42 is cited in our explanation, it is the length of P that is responsible for F, not the fact that the length is picked out by a real number. As with this simple example, so with Minkowski. In each case, it is the geometric properties and the geometric properties alone that do the explaining in Minkowski space-time. The second example that Colyvan gives is in the use of complex numbers to solve differential equations. Colyvan points out that, towards the end of my paper, I focus on the theoretical virtue of simplicity. I urge that, although the introduction of numbers may indeed increase the simplicity of a theory, they do not increase the simplicity in

Response to Colyvan 77 the right kind of way. However, Colyvan is quite right that simplicity is not the only theoretical virtue that theories may possess. Unificatory power must also be considered a theoretical virtue. I believe that, just as there are distinctions in the way in which the postulation of abstract entities may increase the overall simplicity of a theory, so there are distinctions in the way in which the postulation of such entities may increase the overall unificatory power of a theory. As an example of the unificatory power of a theory, Colyvan has cited Newtonian gravitational theory (Colyvan 1999), which is capable of unifying such apparently diverse phenomena as tides, planetary orbits and projectile motion. I accept that the fact that Newtonian gravitational theory is capable of giving a unified account of such diverse phenomena is indeed a virtue of his theory. For by postulating just a few properties, force and mass, and postulating that a certain relationship holds between these properties (although, admittedly, a relationship which may be only expressible using mathematical machinery) different phenomena can be understood as nothing more than manifestations of a unified, underlying reality. What is so attractive about this theory is that it gives us a unified account of the world. But the kind of unification that the complex numbers provides is quite different. Colyvan introduces two differential equations: (1) y - y" = o and (2) y + y" = o. He points out that the real algebra which can be used to solve (1) cannot be used to solve (2) and that complex methods must be employed. Without complex methods Colyvan writes 'we would have no unified approach to solving the respective equations'. But having a unified approach to solving equations seems quite a different matter from having a unified account of apparently disparate phenomena. I do not deny that having such a unified approach may be a useful matter, and I'm sure that physicists are grateful to mathematicians for finding unified approaches to such different equations. Mine is not an eliminativist strategy and I have no desire to eliminate mathematics from scientific theory. But the kind of unification that Newton succeeded in carrying out seems quite different from the kind of unification we get when we find a unified approach to solving different equations. On Newton's account, the tides, the planetary orbits, the trajectory of projectiles are all nothing more than examples of massive bodies evolving according to his gravitational and kinematic laws. The introduction of complex numbers does nothing to unify different phenomena in this way. Nobody thinks that, just because (1) and (2) turn out to be solvable by the same methods that systems obeying these laws have been shown to be manifesta-

78 Joseph Melia tions of the same unified underlying reality. And why should we? There's no obvious route from the fact that different equations can be solved using the same methods to the fact that physical bodies that obey the same equations are therefore manifestations of the same underlying reality. Colyvan also says that, without complex methods, we would be forced to consider phenomena described by (1) and (2) as completely disparate. I'm not entirely sure why this should be so. If complex numbers are simply introduced to enable us to solve the two equations in an analogous manner, then those who believe only in real numbers can still see that any two physical systems which satisfy the respective equa- tions are similar-after all, they are both described by similar differential equations. But even granting this, I do not deny that there are cases where embedding simple systems into a more complicated one may enable us to see connections and similarities between the systems that we could not notice before. Again, mine is not an eliminativist strategy. Embedding a couple of non-euclidean two-dimensional geometries into one Euclidean three dimensional geometry may enable us to see all sorts of connections between the two that might not have been noticed before. Indeed, sometimes, it is not until a system has been embedded into one with extra structure that the properties of the simpler system become transparent. As Shapiro has written, 'when one realises that the complex plane... contains an "isomorphic copy" of the natural numbers, then one can use complex analysis to shed light on the natural numbers'. (Shapiro 1991. See also Kreisel 1967). But the fact that such an embedding is possible does not mean that the existence of the embedding accounts for or unifies the intrinsic structures of the embedded systems. The embedding just enables us to see clearly that there is such a shared structure. I do not wish to deny the practising philosopher, mathematician or scientist his right to do this, or to deny that doing such things affords us theoretical utility. What I do deny is that this kind of utility is similar to the kind of utility that Newtonian gravitational theory affords. School of Philosophy University of Leeds Leeds LS2 9JT UK j. w. melia@leeds. ac. uk JOSEPH MELIA

Response to Colyvan 79 References Colyvan, Mark 1999: 'Confirmation Theory and Indispensability'. Phil- osophical Studies, 96, pp. 1-19. Colyvan, Mark 2002: 'Mathematics and Aesthetic Considerations in Science'. Mind, 111 pp. 69-74. Melia, Joseph 2000: 'Weaseling Away the Indispensability Argument'. Mind, 109, pp. 455-79. Kreisel, G. 1967: 'Informal Rigour and Completeness Proofs' in Lakatos 1967, pp. 138-86. Lakatos, I (ed.) 1967: Problems in the Philosophy of Mathematics. Amsterdam: North-Holland. Shapiro, Stuart 1991: Foundations Without Foundationalism. Clarendon Press, Oxford.