Choosing Collectively Optimal Sets of Alternatives Based on the Condorcet Criterion

Similar documents
Multiwinner Elections Under Preferences that Are Single-Peaked on a Tree

Survey of Voting Procedures and Paradoxes

Volume 31, Issue 1. Manipulation of the Borda rule by introduction of a similar candidate. Jérôme Serais CREM UMR 6211 University of Caen

Dr. Y. İlker TOPCU. Dr. Özgür KABAK web.itu.edu.tr/kabak/

Possible Winners When New Alternatives Join: New Results Coming Up!

Voting Handout. Election from the text, p. 47 (for use during class)

Combining Voting Rules Together

CMU Social choice: Advanced manipulation. Teachers: Avrim Blum Ariel Procaccia (this time)

Efficient Algorithms for Hard Problems on Structured Electorates

Probabilistic Aspects of Voting

GROUP DECISION MAKING

An equity-efficiency trade-off in a geometric approach to committee selection Daniel Eckert and Christian Klamler

Exploring the No-Show Paradox for Condorcet Extensions Using Ehrhart Theory and Computer Simulations

Antipodality in committee selection. Abstract

Winning probabilities in a pairwise lottery system with three alternatives

Justified Representation in Approval-Based Committee Voting

Ties Matter: Complexity of Voting Manipulation Revisited

Single-peaked consistency and its complexity

Partial lecture notes THE PROBABILITY OF VIOLATING ARROW S CONDITIONS

MATH 19-02: HW 5 TUFTS UNIVERSITY DEPARTMENT OF MATHEMATICS SPRING 2018

Electing the Most Probable Without Eliminating the Irrational: Voting Over Intransitive Domains

An NTU Cooperative Game Theoretic View of Manipulating Elections

Electing the Most Probable Without Eliminating the Irrational: Voting Over Intransitive Domains

From Sentiment Analysis to Preference Aggregation

Aggregating Conditionally Lexicographic Preferences on Multi-Issue Domains

Condorcet Efficiency: A Preference for Indifference

Aggregating Conditionally Lexicographic Preferences on Multi-Issue Domains

Working Together: Committee Selection and the Supermodular Degree

The Complexity of Computing Minimal Unidirectional Covering Sets

A Maximum Likelihood Approach towards Aggregating Partial Orders

Recap Social Choice Fun Game Voting Paradoxes Properties. Social Choice. Lecture 11. Social Choice Lecture 11, Slide 1

Multivariate Complexity of Swap Bribery

Social Dichotomy Functions (extended abstract)

Justified Representation in Approval-Based Committee Voting

Dominating Manipulations in Voting with Partial Information

Manipulating Stochastically Generated Single-Elimination Tournaments for Nearly All Players

Mechanism Design for Bounded Agents

arxiv: v1 [cs.gt] 28 Feb 2016

CMU Social choice 2: Manipulation. Teacher: Ariel Procaccia

The Pairwise-Comparison Method

The Maximum Likelihood Approach to Voting on Social Networks 1

On the Chacteristic Numbers of Voting Games

Approximation algorithms and mechanism design for minimax approval voting

The Impact of Dependence among Voters Preferences with Partial Indifference. William V. Gehrlein, University of Delaware

Single-Peakedness and Total Unimodularity: Efficiently Solve Voting Problems Without Even Trying

MATH : FINAL EXAM INFO/LOGISTICS/ADVICE

Randomized Social Choice Functions Under Metric Preferences

Possible Winners when New Candidates Are Added: The Case of Scoring Rules

Voting with Partial Information: What Questions to Ask?

Complexity of Shift Bribery in Hare, Coombs, Baldwin, and Nanson Elections

Single-Peakedness and Total Unimodularity: New Polynomial-Time Algorithms for Multi-Winner Elections

Voting Theory: Pairwise Comparison

Multiwinner analogues of the plurality rule: axiomatic and algorithmic perspectives

Approval Voting for Committees: Threshold Approaches

Lower Bound Issues in Computational Social Choice

The Best Way to Choose a Winner

Who wins the election? Polarizing outranking relations with large performance differences. Condorcet s Approach. Condorcet s method

The Complexity of Computing Minimal Unidirectional Covering Sets

Generalizing the Single-Crossing Property on Lines and Trees to Intermediate Preferences on Median Graphs

Conference Program Design with Single-Peaked and Single-Crossing Preferences

Finding a Collective Set of Items: From Proportional Multirepresentation to Group Recommendation

How Credible is the Prediction of a Party-Based Election?

Winner Determination in Sequential Majority Voting

Inequality of Representation

Introduction to Game Theory Lecture Note 2: Strategic-Form Games and Nash Equilibrium (2)

Computing Spanning Trees in a Social Choice Context

Possible and necessary winners in voting trees: majority graphs vs. profiles

Complexity of Unweighted Coalitional Manipulation Under Some Common Voting Rules

Algorithmic Game Theory Introduction to Mechanism Design

Approval Voting: Three Examples

Geometry of distance-rationalization

Incremental Approval Voting for Multi-agent Knapsack Problems

Theoretical and Empirical Evaluation of Data Reduction for Exact Kemeny Rank Aggregation

Voting on Multiattribute Domains with Cyclic Preferential Dependencies

Thema Working Paper n Université de Cergy Pontoise, France

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 24: Decisions in Groups

Consistent Approval-Based Multi-Winner Rules

Mechanism Design for Multiagent Systems

Stackelberg Voting Games: Computational Aspects and Paradoxes

Analysis of Boolean Functions

Complexity of unweighted coalitional manipulation under some common voting rules

The Complexity of Computing Minimal Unidirectional Covering Sets

Positively responsive collective choice rules and majority rule: a generalization of May s theorem to many alternatives

AUTHOR QUERY FORM. Article Number:

Volume 37, Issue 3. On the Likelihood of the Coincidence of Condorcet Committees

Computational Aspects of Strategic Behaviour in Elections with Top-Truncated Ballots

Multiwinner Voting with Fairness Constraints

Voting: foundations and computational issues. LAMSADE, CNRS & Université Paris-Dauphine EASSS 2014

Points-based rules respecting a pairwise-change-symmetric ordering

2013 IEEE International Symposium on Information Theory

On the probabilistic modeling of consistency for iterated positional election procedures

A Failure of Representative Democracy

arxiv: v1 [cs.gt] 28 Feb 2017

SYSU Lectures on the Theory of Aggregation Lecture 2: Binary Aggregation with Integrity Constraints

Judgment Aggregation Rules Based on Minimization

Social Choice and Social Networks. Aggregation of General Biased Signals (DRAFT)

Proportional Representation as Resource Allocation: Approximability Results

Complexity of Shift Bribery in Iterative Elections

Winner Determination in Sequential Majority Voting with Incomplete Preferences

On the Approximability of Dodgson and Young Elections

Transcription:

1 / 24 Choosing Collectively Optimal Sets of Alternatives Based on the Condorcet Criterion Edith Elkind 1 Jérôme Lang 2 Abdallah Saffidine 2 1 Nanyang Technological University, Singapore 2 LAMSADE, Université Paris-Dauphine, France

2 / 24 Motivation Holding weekly research seminars in a department. A B C D E Tue. Tue. Thu. Thu. Tue. Mon. Wed. Wed. Fri. Mon. Wed. Thu. Fri. Mon. Fri. Thu. Fri. Mon. Tue. Thu. Fri. Mon. Tue. Wed. Wed.

2 / 24 Motivation Holding weekly research seminars in a department. A B C D E Tue. Tue. Thu. Thu. Tue. Mon. Wed. Wed. Fri. Mon. Wed. Thu. Fri. Mon. Fri. Thu. Fri. Mon. Tue. Thu. Fri. Mon. Tue. Wed. Wed. no single day will suit everybody.

2 / 24 Motivation Holding weekly research seminars in a department. A B C D E Tue. Tue. Thu. Thu. Tue. Mon. Wed. Wed. Fri. Mon. Wed. Thu. Fri. Mon. Fri. Thu. Fri. Mon. Tue. Thu. Fri. Mon. Tue. Wed. Wed. no single day will suit everybody.

2 / 24 Motivation Holding weekly research seminars in a department. A B C D E Tue. Tue. Thu. Thu. Tue. Mon. Wed. Wed. Fri. Mon. Wed. Thu. Fri. Mon. Fri. Thu. Fri. Mon. Tue. Thu. Fri. Mon. Tue. Wed. Wed. no single day will suit everybody.

2 / 24 Motivation Holding weekly research seminars in a department. A B C D E Tue. Tue. Thu. Thu. Tue. Mon. Wed. Wed. Fri. Mon. Wed. Thu. Fri. Mon. Fri. Thu. Fri. Mon. Tue. Thu. Fri. Mon. Tue. Wed. Wed. no single day will suit everybody.

2 / 24 Motivation Holding weekly research seminars in a department. A B C D E Tue. Tue. Thu. Thu. Tue. Mon. Wed. Wed. Fri. Mon. Wed. Thu. Fri. Mon. Fri. Thu. Fri. Mon. Tue. Thu. Fri. Mon. Tue. Wed. Wed. no single day will suit everybody.

2 / 24 Motivation Holding weekly research seminars in a department. A B C D E Tue. Tue. Thu. Thu. Tue. Mon. Wed. Wed. Fri. Mon. Wed. Thu. Fri. Mon. Fri. Thu. Fri. Mon. Tue. Thu. Fri. Mon. Tue. Wed. Wed. no single day will suit everybody. select 2 seminar days, for even weeks and odd weeks

2 / 24 Motivation Holding weekly research seminars in a department. A B C D E Tue. Tue. Thu. Thu. Tue. Mon. Wed. Wed. Fri. Mon. Wed. Thu. Fri. Mon. Fri. Thu. Fri. Mon. Tue. Thu. Fri. Mon. Tue. Wed. Wed. no single day will suit everybody. select 2 seminar days, for even weeks and odd weeks

2 / 24 Motivation Holding weekly research seminars in a department. A B C D E Tue. Tue. Thu. Thu. Tue. Mon. Wed. Wed. Fri. Mon. Wed. Thu. Fri. Mon. Fri. Thu. Fri. Mon. Tue. Thu. Fri. Mon. Tue. Wed. Wed. no single day will suit everybody. select 2 seminar days, for even weeks and odd weeks

3 / 24 Related Work Proportional Representation Condorcet Committees

4 / 24 Notations n voters a set of p candidates X preference profile P = 1,..., n

5 / 24 θ-winning Sets Definition For Y X, z X \ Y, and 0 < θ 1 Y θ-covers z if #{i N y Y such that y i z} > θn. (A proportion at least θ of the voters prefers some alternative of Y to z).

5 / 24 θ-winning Sets Definition For Y X, z X \ Y, and 0 < θ 1 Y θ-covers z if #{i N y Y such that y i z} > θn. (A proportion at least θ of the voters prefers some alternative of Y to z). Y is a θ-winning set if z X \ Y, Y θ-covers z.

6 / 24 Given P, θ, and k D(P, θ, k) = {Y, Y is a θ-winning set, Y k}

6 / 24 Given P, θ, and k D(P, θ, k) = {Y, Y is a θ-winning set, Y k} We may fix θ and minimize k fix k and maximize θ

7 / 24 Example P 1 1 2 3 a b d c c a d d b b a c

7 / 24 Example P 1 1 2 3 a b d c c a d d b b a c {c} 1 2 -covers d {c} does not 1 2-cover a or b

7 / 24 Example P 1 1 2 3 a b d c c a d d b b a c {c} 1 2 -covers d {c} does not 1 2-cover a or b {a, b} 1 2 -covers c {a, b} 1 2 -covers d {a, b} is a 1 2-winning set

7 / 24 Example P 1 1 2 3 a b d c c a d d b b a c {c} 1 2 -covers d {c} does not 1 2-cover a or b {a, b} 1 2 -covers c {a, b} 1 2 -covers d {a, b} is a 1 2-winning set D(P 1, 1 2, 1) = D(P 1, 1 2, 2) = {{a, b}, {a, c}, {a, d}, {b, d}, {c, d}}

8 / 24 Particular Cases θ = 1 2, k = 1 If P has a Condorcet winner c then D(P, 1 2, 1) = {{c}} else D(P, 1 2, 1) =

8 / 24 Particular Cases θ = 1 2, k = 1 If P has a Condorcet winner c then D(P, 1 2, 1) = {{c}} else D(P, 1 2, 1) = θ = max{θ D(P, θ, 1) } {x} is a θ -winning set iff x is

8 / 24 Particular Cases θ = 1 2, k = 1 If P has a Condorcet winner c then D(P, 1 2, 1) = {{c}} else D(P, 1 2, 1) = θ = max{θ D(P, θ, 1) } {x} is a θ -winning set iff x is a winner for the maximin voting rule

8 / 24 Particular Cases θ = 1 2, k = 1 If P has a Condorcet winner c then D(P, 1 2, 1) = {{c}} else D(P, 1 2, 1) = θ = max{θ D(P, θ, 1) } {x} is a θ -winning set iff x is a winner for the maximin voting rule Y D(P, 1, k) Y contains every candidate ranked first by some voter

9 / 24 CWS: not a tournament solution 1 2 3 a b d c c a d d b b a c a c b d 1 2 3 a c d b d a c a b d b c {a, b} is a CWS {a, b} is not a CWS

10 / 24 Condorcet Dimension Definition Condorcet dimension of a profile P: dim C (P) = smallest k s.t. D(P, 1 2, k)

10 / 24 Condorcet Dimension Definition Condorcet dimension of a profile P: dim C (P) = smallest k s.t. D(P, 1 2, k) P 1 If P has a Condorcet winner then dim C (P) = 1. We have seen that dim C (P 1 ) = 2 1 2 3 a b d c c a d d b b a c

11 / 24 A profile of dimension 3 v 1 v 2 v 3 v 4 v 5 v 6 v 7 v 8 v 9 v 10 v 11 v 12 v 13 v 14 v 15 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 2 3 4 5 1 7 8 9 10 6 12 13 14 15 11 3 4 5 1 2 8 9 10 6 7 13 14 15 11 12 4 5 1 2 3 9 10 6 7 8 14 15 11 12 13 5 1 2 3 4 10 6 7 8 9 15 11 12 13 14 Not CWS: 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 1 2 3 4 5 7 8 9 10 6 12 13 14 15 11 2 3 4 5 1 8 9 10 6 7 13 14 15 11 12 3 4 5 1 2 9 10 6 7 8 14 15 11 12 13 4 5 1 2 3 10 6 7 8 9 15 11 12 13 14 5 1 2 3 4 11 12 13 14 15 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 12 13 14 15 11 2 3 4 5 1 7 8 9 10 6 13 14 15 11 12 3 4 5 1 2 8 9 10 6 7 14 15 11 12 13 4 5 1 2 3 9 10 6 7 8 15 11 12 13 14 5 1 2 3 4 10 6 7 8 9

11 / 24 A profile of dimension 3 v 1 v 2 v 3 v 4 v 5 v 6 v 7 v 8 v 9 v 10 v 11 v 12 v 13 v 14 v 15 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 2 3 4 5 1 7 8 9 10 6 12 13 14 15 11 3 4 5 1 2 8 9 10 6 7 13 14 15 11 12 4 5 1 2 3 9 10 6 7 8 14 15 11 12 13 5 1 2 3 4 10 6 7 8 9 15 11 12 13 14 Not CWS: {1, 2} 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 1 2 3 4 5 7 8 9 10 6 12 13 14 15 11 2 3 4 5 1 8 9 10 6 7 13 14 15 11 12 3 4 5 1 2 9 10 6 7 8 14 15 11 12 13 4 5 1 2 3 10 6 7 8 9 15 11 12 13 14 5 1 2 3 4 11 12 13 14 15 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 12 13 14 15 11 2 3 4 5 1 7 8 9 10 6 13 14 15 11 12 3 4 5 1 2 8 9 10 6 7 14 15 11 12 13 4 5 1 2 3 9 10 6 7 8 15 11 12 13 14 5 1 2 3 4 10 6 7 8 9

11 / 24 A profile of dimension 3 v 1 v 2 v 3 v 4 v 5 v 6 v 7 v 8 v 9 v 10 v 11 v 12 v 13 v 14 v 15 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 2 3 4 5 1 7 8 9 10 6 12 13 14 15 11 3 4 5 1 2 8 9 10 6 7 13 14 15 11 12 4 5 1 2 3 9 10 6 7 8 14 15 11 12 13 5 1 2 3 4 10 6 7 8 9 15 11 12 13 14 Not CWS: {1, 2} 5 {1, 3} 11 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 1 2 3 4 5 7 8 9 10 6 12 13 14 15 11 2 3 4 5 1 8 9 10 6 7 13 14 15 11 12 3 4 5 1 2 9 10 6 7 8 14 15 11 12 13 4 5 1 2 3 10 6 7 8 9 15 11 12 13 14 5 1 2 3 4 11 12 13 14 15 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 12 13 14 15 11 2 3 4 5 1 7 8 9 10 6 13 14 15 11 12 3 4 5 1 2 8 9 10 6 7 14 15 11 12 13 4 5 1 2 3 9 10 6 7 8 15 11 12 13 14 5 1 2 3 4 10 6 7 8 9

11 / 24 A profile of dimension 3 v 1 v 2 v 3 v 4 v 5 v 6 v 7 v 8 v 9 v 10 v 11 v 12 v 13 v 14 v 15 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 2 3 4 5 1 7 8 9 10 6 12 13 14 15 11 3 4 5 1 2 8 9 10 6 7 13 14 15 11 12 4 5 1 2 3 9 10 6 7 8 14 15 11 12 13 5 1 2 3 4 10 6 7 8 9 15 11 12 13 14 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 1 2 3 4 5 7 8 9 10 6 12 13 14 15 11 2 3 4 5 1 8 9 10 6 7 13 14 15 11 12 3 4 5 1 2 9 10 6 7 8 14 15 11 12 13 4 5 1 2 3 10 6 7 8 9 15 11 12 13 14 5 1 2 3 4 Not CWS: {1, 2} 5 {1, 3} 11 {1, 6} 5 etc. 11 12 13 14 15 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 12 13 14 15 11 2 3 4 5 1 7 8 9 10 6 13 14 15 11 12 3 4 5 1 2 8 9 10 6 7 14 15 11 12 13 4 5 1 2 3 9 10 6 7 8 15 11 12 13 14 5 1 2 3 4 10 6 7 8 9

11 / 24 A profile of dimension 3 v 1 v 2 v 3 v 4 v 5 v 6 v 7 v 8 v 9 v 10 v 11 v 12 v 13 v 14 v 15 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 2 3 4 5 1 7 8 9 10 6 12 13 14 15 11 3 4 5 1 2 8 9 10 6 7 13 14 15 11 12 4 5 1 2 3 9 10 6 7 8 14 15 11 12 13 5 1 2 3 4 10 6 7 8 9 15 11 12 13 14 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 1 2 3 4 5 7 8 9 10 6 12 13 14 15 11 2 3 4 5 1 8 9 10 6 7 13 14 15 11 12 3 4 5 1 2 9 10 6 7 8 14 15 11 12 13 4 5 1 2 3 10 6 7 8 9 15 11 12 13 14 5 1 2 3 4 11 12 13 14 15 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 12 13 14 15 11 2 3 4 5 1 7 8 9 10 6 13 14 15 11 12 3 4 5 1 2 8 9 10 6 7 14 15 11 12 13 4 5 1 2 3 9 10 6 7 8 15 11 12 13 14 5 1 2 3 4 10 6 7 8 9 Not CWS: {1, 2} 5 {1, 3} 11 {1, 6} 5 etc. CWS: {1, 6, 11} {1, 3, 6} etc.

12 / 24 High dimension profiles? finding P such that dim C (P) = 1 or dim C (P) = 2 is trivial. dim C (P) = 3 needs more work(previous slide). we could not find a profile of dimension 4 or more

12 / 24 High dimension profiles? finding P such that dim C (P) = 1 or dim C (P) = 2 is trivial. dim C (P) = 3 needs more work(previous slide). we could not find a profile of dimension 4 or more Question Does there exist a profile of dimension k for any k?

Probabilistic approach n voters m = X candidates generate profiles randomly with a uniform distribution (impartial culture) Proposition {a, b} X is CWS with probability 1 me n/24 Hint: with probability 2 in any given vote, either a or b is ranked 3 above c, therefore the expected number of votes where a or b beats c is 2n. By Chernoff bound, the probability that a or b is 3 ranked above c in at least n votes is at most 2 e n/24. Therefore the probability that {a, b} is not a CWS is at most me n/24. 13 / 24

14 / 24 Experimental results (1) k = 1 k = 2 k = 3 k = 4 0 20 40 60 80 100 Figure: probability that a fixed set of size k is a Condorcet winning set as a function of n, for a 30-candidate election

Important remark: dominating sets are CWS 15 / 24 1 2 3 a b d c c a d d b b a c {a, b}, {a, c}, {a, d}, {b, d}, {c, d} a c b d {a, c}, {a, d}, {b, d}, {c, d}

16 / 24 An upper bound on the dimension Proposition For any profile P with n voters (n odd) we have dim C (P) log 2 m.

16 / 24 An upper bound on the dimension Proposition For any profile P with n voters (n odd) we have dim C (P) log 2 m. Proof. n odd the majority graph is a tournament dominating sets of the majority graph are CWS. Megiddo and Vishkin (1988): a tournament has a dominating set of size log 2 m.

Complexity CONDORCET DIMENSION: compute dim C (P). 17 / 24

Complexity CONDORCET DIMENSION: compute dim C (P). Is there a K such that for all P, dim C (P) K? Yes enumerate all subsets of size K poly(n, m)m K polynomial ( P) 17 / 24

Complexity CONDORCET DIMENSION: compute dim C (P). Is there a K such that for all P, dim C (P) K? Yes enumerate all subsets of size K poly(n, m)m K polynomial ( P) No enumerate all subsets of size log 2 m poly(n, m)m log m quasi-polynomial ( QP) 17 / 24

18 / 24 θ-winning Sets for θ 1 2 θ = 1 2, k 2, every pair is with high probability a CWS. fixing θ = 1 2 and minimizing k is not interesting. fix k and use θ = k k+1

19 / 24 Experimental Results (2) n = 5 n = 8 n = 20 n = 500 n = 2000 0 1 2 3 4 5 6 Figure: Empirical distribution of the number of 2 -winning sets of 3 size 2 for 20 candidates

20 / 24 Experimental Results (3) k = 1 k = 2 k = 3 k = 4 0 1 2 2 3 3 4 4 1 5 Figure: Empirical distribution of θ(k) for m = 30 and n = 100

Related Work (1) 21 / 24

21 / 24 Related Work (1) Proportional representation Chamberlin and Courant (1983): choose the highest-ranking alternative from the given set in each vote, but use the Borda score as a basis. A set Y receives max y Y s B (y; i) points from a voter i and the winning committee of size k is the k-element set of candidates with the highest score.

21 / 24 Related Work (1) Proportional representation Chamberlin and Courant (1983): choose the highest-ranking alternative from the given set in each vote, but use the Borda score as a basis. A set Y receives max y Y s B (y; i) points from a voter i and the winning committee of size k is the k-element set of candidates with the highest score. Procaccia et al. (2008): computing a winning committee of size k is NP-hard. Lu and Boutilier (2011): trade-off between committee size and quality of representation; computation of optimal sets.

22 / 24 Related Work (2) Condorcet committees: conjunctive sets Gehrlein (1985): Y X is a Condorcet committee if for every alternative y in Y and every alternative x in X \ Y, a majority of voters prefers y to x. CWS: disjunctive interpretation of sets

23 / 24 Related Work (2) Condorcet committees, continued Ratliff (2003): generalizes Dodgson and Kemeny to sets of alternatives. Fishburn (1981): defines preference relations on sets of alternatives and looks for a subset that beats any subset in a pairwise election. Kaymak and Sanver (2003): under which conditions on the extension function can a Condorcet committee in the sense of Fishburn be derived from preferences over single alternatives? Can Condorcet committees be also CWSs? Depends on the extension function. For standard extension functions: no.

24 / 24 Conclusion Reconciliating both approaches disjunctive interpretation (as in proportional representation) satisfies the Condorcet criterion (like Condorcet committees) Question Are there profiles of Condorcet dimension 4 or more?