Complexity of Ramsey null sets

Similar documents
SMALL SUBSETS OF THE REALS AND TREE FORCING NOTIONS

Decomposing Borel functions and structure at finite levels of the Baire hierarchy.

Uniquely Universal Sets

A BOREL SOLUTION TO THE HORN-TARSKI PROBLEM. MSC 2000: 03E05, 03E20, 06A10 Keywords: Chain Conditions, Boolean Algebras.

A NEW LINDELOF SPACE WITH POINTS G δ

Quasi-invariant measures for continuous group actions

IDEAL GAMES AND RAMSEY SETS

A collection of topological Ramsey spaces of trees and their application to profinite graph theory

CCC Forcing and Splitting Reals

Uncountable γ-sets under axiom CPA game

On the class of perfectly null sets and its transitive version

Definable Graphs and Dominating Reals

Playing with forcing

A product of γ-sets which is not Menger.

An introduction to OCA

Selective Ultrafilters on FIN

Ultrafilters with property (s)

Effective descriptive set theory

ON A QUESTION OF SIERPIŃSKI

The ideal of Sierpiński-Zygmund sets on the plane

Wojciech Stadnicki. On Laver extension. Uniwersytet Wrocławski. Praca semestralna nr 2 (semestr letni 2010/11) Opiekun pracy: Janusz Pawlikowski

Adam Kwela. Instytut Matematyczny PAN SELECTIVE PROPERTIES OF IDEALS ON COUNTABLE SETS. Praca semestralna nr 3 (semestr letni 2011/12)

ON THE LACZKOVICH-KOMJÁTH PROPERTY OF SIGMA-IDEALS. 1. Introduction

Borel cardinals and Ramsey ultrafilters (draft of Sections 1-3)

On the Length of Borel Hierarchies

A CLASSIFICATION OF SEPARABLE ROSENTHAL COMPACTA AND ITS APPLICATIONS

On the Length of Borel Hierarchies

SELF-DUAL UNIFORM MATROIDS ON INFINITE SETS

Higher dimensional Ellentuck spaces

ON THE COMPUTABILITY OF PERFECT SUBSETS OF SETS WITH POSITIVE MEASURE

Jónsson Properties for Non-Ordinal Sets Under the Axiom of Determinacy

1.A Topological spaces The initial topology is called topology generated by (f i ) i I.

Selective ultrafilters in N [ ], FIN [ ], and R α

Distributivity of Quotients of Countable Products of Boolean Algebras

Silver Measurability and its relation to other regularity properties

Convergence and submeasures in Boolean algebras

SMALL COMBINATORIAL CARDINAL CHARACTERISTICS AND THEOREMS OF EGOROV AND BLUMBERG

Eventually Different Functions and Inaccessible Cardinals

JUMP OPERATIONS FOR BOREL GRAPHS

Regularity and Definability

A G δ IDEAL OF COMPACT SETS STRICTLY ABOVE THE NOWHERE DENSE IDEAL IN THE TUKEY ORDER

MEASURABLE 3-COLORINGS OF ACYCLIC GRAPHS CLINTON T. CONLEY AND BENJAMIN D. MILLER

FORCING PROPERTIES OF IDEALS OF CLOSED SETS

Classical Theory of Cardinal Characteristics

ALGEBRAIC SUMS OF SETS IN MARCZEWSKI BURSTIN ALGEBRAS

PCF THEORY AND CARDINAL INVARIANTS OF THE REALS

Combinatorial proofs of Gowers FIN k and FIN ± k

Independence of Boolean algebras and forcing

Homogeneous spaces and Wadge theory

The Proper Forcing Axiom: a tutorial

BANACH SPACES FROM BARRIERS IN HIGH DIMENSIONAL ELLENTUCK SPACES

Annals of Pure and Applied Logic

EMBEDDING AN ANALYTIC EQUIVALENCE RELATION IN THE TRANSITIVE CLOSURE OF A BOREL RELATION

A NEW CLASS OF RAMSEY-CLASSIFICATION THEOREMS AND THEIR APPLICATION IN THE TUKEY THEORY OF ULTRAFILTERS, PART 1

arxiv: v1 [math.lo] 14 Jul 2017

Silver trees and Cohen reals

Banach Spaces from Barriers in High Dimensional Ellentuck Spaces

Free Subgroups of the Fundamental Group of the Hawaiian Earring

The length-ω 1 open game quantifier propagates scales

Maharam Algebras. Equipe de Logique, Université de Paris 7, 2 Place Jussieu, Paris, France

Irredundant Generators

MORE ABOUT SPACES WITH A SMALL DIAGONAL

4 Choice axioms and Baire category theorem

THE SMOOTH IDEAL JOHN D. CLEMENS, CLINTON T. CONLEY, AND BENJAMIN D. MILLER

The onto mapping property of Sierpinski

Tutorial 1.3: Combinatorial Set Theory. Jean A. Larson (University of Florida) ESSLLI in Ljubljana, Slovenia, August 4, 2011

Measurability Problems for Boolean Algebras

ALMOST DISJOINT AND INDEPENDENT FAMILIES. 1. introduction. is infinite. Fichtenholz and Kantorovich showed that there is an independent family

Representing Scott Sets in Algebraic Settings

Axioms of separation

Isomorphism of free G-subflows (preliminary draft)

arxiv: v1 [math.lo] 11 Feb 2011

COMPACT SPACES WITH HEREDITARILY NORMAL SQUARES

EMBEDDING DISTRIBUTIVE LATTICES IN THE Σ 0 2 ENUMERATION DEGREES

Combinatorial Variants of Lebesgue s Density Theorem

Projective well-orderings of the reals and forcing axioms

VARIETIES OF ABELIAN TOPOLOGICAL GROUPS AND SCATTERED SPACES

Katětov and Katětov-Blass orders on F σ -ideals

Unsolvable problems, the Continuum Hypothesis, and the nature of infinity

TOPOLOGICAL RAMSEY SPACES DENSE IN FORCINGS

Wadge-like reducibilities on arbitrary quasi-polish spaces

arxiv: v1 [math.lo] 16 Jan 2010

PROBABILITY MEASURES AND EFFECTIVE RANDOMNESS

Gap Embedding for Well-Quasi-Orderings 1

The Metamathematics of Randomness

arxiv: v1 [math.fa] 14 May 2008

arxiv:math/ v1 [math.gn] 10 Apr 2002

COUNTABLY S-CLOSED SPACES

Social welfare relations and descriptive set theory

THE CANTOR GAME: WINNING STRATEGIES AND DETERMINACY. by arxiv: v1 [math.ca] 29 Jan 2017 MAGNUS D. LADUE

A Ramsey theorem for polyadic spaces

Representing Scott Sets in Algebraic Settings

Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras

Every Lusin set is undetermined in the point-open game

HECHLER'S THEOREM FOR TALL ANALYTIC P-IDEALS

Generic Absoluteness. Joan Bagaria and Sy D. Friedman. Abstract. However, this is not true for 1 3 predicates. Indeed, if we add a Cohen real

int cl int cl A = int cl A.

Stevo T o d o r č e v i ć (Toronto, Ont., and Beograd)

arxiv: v2 [math.lo] 29 Mar 2015

STEVO TODORCEVIC AND JUSTIN TATCH MOORE

Transcription:

Available online at www.sciencedirect.com Advances in Mathematics 230 (2012) 1184 1195 www.elsevier.com/locate/aim Complexity of Ramsey null sets Marcin Sabok Instytut Matematyczny Uniwersytetu Wrocławskiego, pl. Grunwaldzki 2/4, 50-384 Wrocław, Poland Instytut Matematyczny Polskiej Akademii Nauk, ul. Śniadeckich 8, 00-956 Warszawa, Poland Received 23 April 2010; accepted 13 March 2012 Available online 23 April 2012 Communicated by R.D. Mauldin Abstract We show that the set of codes for Ramsey positive analytic sets is 1 2-complete. This is an analogue of a theorem of Hurewicz saying that the set of uncountable compact subsets of an uncountable Polish space is 1 1-complete. As a corollary, we get that the σ -ideal of Ramsey null sets is not ZFC-correct, which answers a question of Ikegami, Pawlikowski and Zapletal. c 2012 Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved. MSC: 03E15; 28A05; 54H05 Keywords: Ramsey null sets; 1 2-complete sets 1. Introduction Ramsey measurability was introduced by Galvin and Prikry [5] to prove a Ramsey theorem for Borel colorings of the plane. Shortly after, their result was generalized by Silver [14] to those colorings of the plane which are in the σ -algebra generated by analytic sets. Ellentuck [4] pointed out that Ramsey measurable sets are precisely the sets with the Baire property in a certain topology on [ω] ω, called today the Ellentuck topology (see [9, Chapter 26]). The basic open sets in the Ellentuck topology are of the form [σ, s] = {x [ω] ω : x max(σ ) = σ x \ max(σ ) s} for σ [ω] <ω, s [ω] ω such that max σ < min s. Of crucial importance is the fact that Correspondence to: Instytut Matematyczny Polskiej Akademii Nauk, ul. Śniadeckich 8, 00-956 Warszawa, Poland. E-mail address: sabok@math.uni.wroc.pl. 0001-8708/$ - see front matter c 2012 Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved. doi:10.1016/j.aim.2012.03.001

M. Sabok / Advances in Mathematics 230 (2012) 1184 1195 1185 all analytic subsets of [ω] ω have the Baire property in the Ellentuck topology. This leads to the Silver theorem, saying that every analytic set A [ω] ω is Ramsey measurable, i.e. for any basic open set [σ, s] as above there is an infinite set s s such that [σ, s ] is either disjoint from A or contained in A. If for any [σ, s] there is an infinite s s such that [σ, s] is disjoint from A, then we say that A is Ramsey null. A set is Ramsey positive if it is not Ramsey null. Note that, by the Silver theorem, an analytic set is Ramsey positive if and only if it contains some [σ, s] as above. It is worth noting here that the Silver theorem and the notion of Ramsey measurability found many applications outside of set theory, e.g. in the Banach space theory; cf [10, Section 19.E]. Ramsey null sets form a σ -ideal, i.e. they are closed under taking subsets and countable unions. On the other hand, many natural σ -ideals are definable in the following sense. Given two projective pointclasses and Ɣ, we say that a family A of subsets of a Polish space X is on Ɣ (cf. [10, Definition 35.9]) if for any Polish space Y and any Ɣ set A Y X we have that {y Y : A y A}. In fact, A is on Ɣ if and only if the above holds for one particular set A ω ω X, which is a good universal Ɣ set (for a definition see [13, Section 3.H.1]). If Ɣ is a pointclass, A is a family of sets in Ɣ, and A ω ω X is a fixed good universal Ɣ set, then we refer to {x ω ω : A x A} as the set of codes for Ɣ sets in A. We will be mostly interested in the projective complexity of the latter set. Note that if A ω ω X is any other good universal Ɣ set, then {x ω ω : A x A} has the same projective complexity as the set {x ω ω : A x A} and hence the complexity of the set of codes for Ɣ sets in A does not depend on the actual choice of the good universal Ɣ set. In most cases of commonly occurring σ -ideals I, the complexity of the set of codes of 1 1 sets in I is known. For example, the σ -ideal of countable sets is known to be 1 1 on 1 1 and this estimation is sharp, i.e. the set of codes for analytic countable sets is 1 1-complete. In fact, already the set of codes for closed countable subsets of 2 ω is 1 1-complete and the latter follows from a theorem of Hurewicz [10, Theorem 27.5], saying that for any uncountable Polish space X the set of countable compact subsets of X is 1 1-complete in K (X). The same complexity computation is true for the σ -ideal generated by compact subsets of any Polish space which is not σ -compact [10, Exercise 27.9]. In this paper, we prove the following result, which can be seen as an analogue of the Hurewicz theorem that is one projective step higher. Theorem 1. The set of codes for Ramsey positive 1 1 (or G δ) sets is 1 2 -complete. It should be mentioned that not very many natural examples of 1 2-complete sets are known. One of the few sources is the paper of Becker, Kahane and Louveau [2] with some examples appearing in harmonic analysis. More recently, new 1 2-complete sets appeared in the work of Adams and Kechris [1], where the authors show [1, Theorem 2] that the problems of reducibility and bireducibility of countable Borel equivalence relations are 1 2-complete. On the other hand, one level below in the projective hierarchy the situation is quite different and there are plenty of natural examples of 1 1-complete sets (see [10, Section 27]). The proof of Theorem 1 is divided into two parts. In the first we show that the set of codes for Ramsey positive sets is ( 1 2, 1 1 1 1 )-complete, which means that any 1 2 set can be reduced to it via a ( 1 1 1 1 )-submeasurable reduction (for definitions see Section 2). The second part is more technical and shows that this reduction can be improved to a continuous one on abstract grounds.

1186 M. Sabok / Advances in Mathematics 230 (2012) 1184 1195 Theorem 2. Any ( 1 2, 1 1 1 1 )-complete subset of a Polish zero-dimensional space is 1 2 - complete. This result seems to be of independent interest and should be compared to a theorem of Kechris [11], saying that any set which is 1 1 -complete with respect to Borel reductions is 1 1 - complete. Recently, Zapletal [16] developed a general theory of iteration for idealized forcing. One of the necessary conditions for a σ -ideal to be iterable (see [16, Definition 5.1.3]) is its ZFCcorrectness (for a definition see Section 5). Shortly after, Ikegami [8] presented a general framework for generic absoluteness and transcendence principles (cf. Judah and Shelah [7]) for strongly arboreal [8, Definition 2.4] forcing notions P. The latter was recently developed by Brendle and Khomskii [3] who obtained new characterizations of transcendence principles for some strongly arboreal forcing notions (including the E 0 -forcing). An important assumption in Ikegami s approach (cf. [8, Theorem 4.3], [8, Theorem 4.4]) is that the Borel codes for sets in the σ -ideals considered (see [8, Definition 2.11]) are 1 2. Ikegami and, independently, Pawlikowski and Zapletal asked whether the σ -ideal of Ramsey null sets is ZFC-correct and the theory of [8,16] can be applied to the forcing associated with Ramsey null sets (the Mathias forcing). As a corollary of Theorem 1, we obtain a negative answer to this question and get the following. Corollary 3. The σ -ideal of Ramsey null sets is not ZFC-correct. This paper is organized as follows. In Section 2 we gather some notation and standard facts used later in the proofs. In Section 3 we show that for a certain universal G δ set G 2 ω [ω] ω the set {x 2 ω : G x is Ramsey positive} is 1 2 -complete with respect to 1 1 1 1 -submeasurable maps. In Section 4 we prove Theorem 2. Together with the results of Section 3, Theorem 2 implies that {x 2 ω : G x is Ramsey positive} is 1 2-complete and therefore the same is true for any good G δ -universal (or good 1 1-universal) set in place of G. That proves Theorem 1. Finally, in Section 5 we show how Theorem 1 implies Corollary 3. 2. Preliminaries Given a tree T ω <ω we write lim T for {x ω ω : n ω x n T }. If τ ω <ω, then we denote by [τ] the set {x ω ω : τ x}. Similarly, for τ [ω] <ω we write [τ] for {x [ω] ω : x max(τ) = τ}. For each n < ω and i 2 we write [(n, i)] for {x 2 ω : x(n) = i}. For a tree T ω <ω we write P(T ) (resp. R(T )) for the set of all perfect (resp. pruned) subtrees of T. P(T ) and R(T ) are endowed with Polish topologies induced via the natural embeddings into 2 ω. In particular, P(2 <ω ) stands for the space of all perfect binary trees. If D ω ω ω ω and F ω ω are closed, then we write f : F c D to denote that f is a continuous function from F to Y whose graph is contained in D. Recall [10, Proposition 2.5] that if T and S are trees such that F = lim T and D = lim S, then we can code f by a monotone map from T to S, and any monotone map from T to S gives rise to a continuous function defined on a comeager subset of F. By the standard topology on [ω] ω we mean the one induced from the Baire space ω ω via the standard embedding of [ω] ω into ω ω. Unless stated otherwise, [ω] ω is always considered as a topological space with the standard topology. In special cases we will indicate when we refer to the Ellentuck topology on [ω] ω.

M. Sabok / Advances in Mathematics 230 (2012) 1184 1195 1187 For a sequence of Polish spaces X i : i I (I countable) we write i I X i for the disjoint union of the spaces X i with the natural Polish topology. For a Polish space X we write K (X) for the space of compact subsets of X with the Vietoris topology (cf. [10, Section 4.F]) and F(X) for the Polish space of all closed subsets of X (usually F(X) is considered only as a standard Borel space, but we make use of the fact that there is an appropriate Polish topology on it; cf. [10, Theorem 12.3]). Note that if X is the Baire space ω ω (or [ω] ω ), then the natural coding of closed sets by pruned trees gives a homeomorphism of F(ω ω ) and R(ω <ω ) (see also [10, Exercise 12.10]). All Polish spaces considered in this paper are assumed to be endowed with a fixed topology subbase. For the Cantor space 2 ω we fix the subbase consisting of the sets [(n, 0)] and [(n, 1)] for n < ω. For zero-dimensional Polish spaces we assume that the fixed subbase is the one inherited from 2 ω via a fixed embedding into 2 ω. In particular, the space of all pruned subtrees of ω <ω inherits its subbase from 2 ω and this subbase consists of the sets {T R(ω <ω ) : σ T } and {T R(ω <ω ) : σ T }. Similarly, the subbase for F([ω] ω ) consists of the sets {D F([ω] ω ) : D [σ ] } and {D F([ω] ω ) : D [σ ] = } for σ ω <ω. Note that this topology is strictly weaker than the natural analogue of the Vietoris topology, since the sets {D F([ω] ω ) : D U} are in general not open for any open U [ω] ω (cf. [10, Remark 12.12]). By a pointclass we mean one of the classes 0 α, 0 α for α < ω 1 and 1 n, 1 n for n < ω (the latter are also referred to as projective pointclasses). If is a Boolean combination of pointclasses, X and Y are Polish spaces, U is the fixed subbase for Y, and f : X Y is a function, then we say that f is -submeasurable if f 1 (U) for each U U. If Ɣ is a pointclass, A X is in Ɣ and f : A Y is a function, then we say that f is Ɣ-measurable if for each open set V Y there is B Ɣ such that f 1 (V ) = A B. If Y is zero-dimensional and A Y is in Ɣ, then we say that A is (Ɣ, )-complete if for any zero-dimensional Polish space Z and A Z in Ɣ there is a -submeasurable function f : Z Y such that f 1 (A) = A. Note that the notion of (Ɣ, 0 1 )-completeness coincides with the usual notion of Ɣ-completeness. 3. Completeness with respect to submeasurable maps We begin with some simple estimations on the complexity of codes for Ramsey null sets. The first claim shows that Theorem 1 is optimal, i.e. the analytic (or G δ ) sets cannot be replaced by closed sets as in the Hurewicz theorem. Claim 4. The set of codes for 0 1 (or F σ ) Ramsey positive sets is 1 1. Proof. A closed set C [ω] ω is Ramsey positive if and only if there is a basic open set [σ, s] in the Ellentuck topology such that [σ, s] C. The latter condition is arithmetical, since both sets [σ, s] and C are closed in the standard topology on [ω] ω. If an F σ set F is written as n<ω C n with C n closed, then F is Ramsey positive if and only if C n is Ramsey positive for some n ω. On the other hand, the complexity of any higher pointclass sets grows by at most one projective level. Lemma 5. The set of codes for 1 1 (or G δ) Ramsey positive sets is 1 2.

1188 M. Sabok / Advances in Mathematics 230 (2012) 1184 1195 Proof. Let A [ω] ω be 1 1 (or G δ) and let D [ω] ω ω ω be a closed set projecting to A. Again, A is Ramsey positive if and only if there is a basic open set [σ, s] in the Ellentuck topology such that [σ, s] A. By the Ramsey uniformization [15, Theorem 1.59], the above is equivalent to [τ, b] f : [τ, b] c D f is total. Since both sets [τ, b] and D are closed, we can code any partial continuous function whose graph is contained in D and whose domain is contained in [τ, b] with a monotone map, as remarked in Section 2. Saying that f is total is a 1 1 statement and hence the above condition is 1 2. Construct now a universal G δ set G 2 ω [ω] ω in such a way that if x 2 ω codes a sequence of closed subsets D n : n < ω of [ω] ω, then G x = [ω] ω \ n<ω D n. More precisely, realize this using n<ω F([ω]ω ) as the set of codes for sequences of closed subsets of [ω] ω. The space n<ω F([ω]ω ) is embedded (as a G δ set) into 2 ω using the pruned trees. We will show that the set {x 2 ω : G x is Ramsey positive} is ( 1 2, 1 1 1 1 )-complete. Together with Theorem 2, this implies that {x 2 ω : G x is Ramsey positive} is 1 2 -complete. The same is true for any good universal G δ (or 1 1 ) set in place of G and this proves Theorem 1. Theorem 6. The set {x 2 ω : G x is Ramsey positive} is ( 1 2, 1 1 1 1 )-complete. Proof. The fact that {x 2 ω : G x is Ramsey positive} follows directly from Lemma 5. Consider now the following set: Z = {C K (2 ω ) : a [ω] ω x C lim x(n) = 0}. n a By a result of Becker, Kahane and Louveau [2, Theorem 3.1], Z is 1 2-complete. We will find a 1 1 1 1 -submeasurable reduction from Z to {x 2ω : G x is Ramsey positive}. For C K (2 ω ) and τ [ω] <ω we define U τ (C) [ω] ω as follows. Put U τ (C) = {a [ω] ω : ( x C n a \ max(τ) x(n) = 1) a [τ]}. Lemma 7. For each C K (2 ω ) and τ 2 <ω the set U τ (C) is open in the standard topology on [ω] ω. Proof. Write C = {(a, x) [ω] ω 2 ω : x C x (a \ max(τ)) = 1} and let π be the projection to [ω] ω from [ω] ω 2 ω. Since C is closed in [ω] ω 2 ω, the set π ( C) is closed in [ω] ω. We have [ω] ω \ U τ (C) = [τ] π ( C), which proves the lemma.

Lemma 8. For each τ 2 <ω the function M. Sabok / Advances in Mathematics 230 (2012) 1184 1195 1189 K (2 ω ) C [ω] ω \ U τ (C) F([ω] ω ) is 1 1 1 1 -submeasurable. Proof. Recall (see Section 2) that the subbase for the space F([ω] ω ) (embedded in 2 ω ) consists of the sets {D F([ω] ω ) : D [σ ] }, {D F([ω] ω ) : D [σ ] = } for σ ω <ω. It is enough to prove that for each σ ω <ω the preimage A σ of the set {D F([ω] ω ) : D [σ ] } is 1 1 in K (2ω ). Moreover, it is enough to show this for σ τ. Indeed, [ω] ω \ U τ (C) is always contained in [τ], so for σ τ we have A σ = A τ if σ τ and A σ = otherwise. But if σ τ, then A σ is equal to {C K (2 ω ) : π ( C) [σ ] }, which is the same as {C K (2 ω ) : x C a [σ ] x (a \ max(τ)) = 1}. The latter set is easily seen to be 1 1. Now we define r : K (2 ω ) n<ω F([ω]ω ) so that r(c) = [ω] ω \ U τ (C) : τ [ω] <ω (we use a fixed recursive bijection from ω to [ω] <ω ). In other words, r(c) is the code for the G δ set G r(c) = U τ (C). τ 2 <ω Note that, by Lemma 8, the function r is 1 1 1 1-submeasurable. We will be done once we prove the following lemma. Lemma 9. For C K (2 ω ) we have C Z if and only if G r(c) is Ramsey null. Proof. ( ) Suppose first that r(c) is a code for a Ramsey null set. We must show that C Z. Take any a [ω] ω. We shall find x C such that lim x(n) 0. n a Since G r(c) is Ramsey null, there is b a, b [ω] ω such that [b] ω G r(c) =. In particular, there is τ [ω] <ω such that b U τ (C). This means that b [τ] x C n b \ max(τ) x(n) = 1. Thus, there is x C which is constant 1 on b \ max(τ), so in particular lim n a x(n) 0 and C Z, as needed. ( ) Suppose now that C Z. We must show that r(c) is a code for a Ramsey null set. Take any τ [ω] <ω and a [ω] ω such that max(τ) < min(a). We shall find b [a] ω such that [τ, b] G r(c) =.

1190 M. Sabok / Advances in Mathematics 230 (2012) 1184 1195 It is enough to find b [a] ω such that [τ, b] U τ (C) =. Since it is not the case that x C lim n a x(n) = 0, there are x 0 C and b [a] ω such that x 0 b = 1. We claim that [τ, b] U τ (C) =. Suppose not. Take any y [τ, b] U τ (C). Then y [τ], y \ max(τ) b and y U τ (C). So, by the definition of U τ, we have ( x C n y \ max(τ) x(n) = 1). But on the other hand, x 0 C and x 0 b = 1, so we have x 0 (y \ max(τ)) = 1. This gives a contradiction and shows that [τ, b] U τ (C) =, as needed. This concludes the proof of the theorem. 4. Completeness In this section we prove Theorem 2. The proof will be based on some ideas of Harrington and Kechris from [6] and of Kechris from [11]. We will need the following definition. Definition. Let A be a pointclass and B be a Boolean combinations of pointclasses. An (A, B)- expansion of a Polish space Y is an A-subset E(Y ) of a Polish space Y together with an A-measurable map r : E(Y ) Y satisfying the following. For every zero-dimensional Polish space X and B-submeasurable map f : Y X there is a closed (in Y ) set F E(Y ) and a continuous map g : Y X such that r (F) = Y and the following diagram commutes: r F F Y f F g X Note that in this definition we may assume that X = 2 ω. The above notion is relevant in view of the following. Proposition 10. Let X and Y be zero-dimensional Polish spaces, A X be (A, B)-complete and C Y be A-complete. If Y has an (A, B)-expansion, then A is A-complete. Proof. Let Y, E(Y ) and r : E(Y ) Y be an (A, B)-expansion of Y. Put C = r 1 (C) and note that C Y is also in A. Let f : Y X be B-submeasurable such that f 1 (A) = C. Take F E(Y ) and g : X Y as in the definition of expansion. Note that g 1 (A) = C. In view of Proposition 10 and the fact that there exists a 1 2-complete subset of the Cantor space [2, Theorem 3.1], Theorem 2 will follow once we prove the following. Theorem 11. There exists a ( 1 2, 1 1 1 1 )-expansion of the Cantor space.

M. Sabok / Advances in Mathematics 230 (2012) 1184 1195 1191 We will need the following technical result (cf. [6, Sublemma 1.4.2]). Proposition 12. There exists a 1 2 set R 2ω and a 1 2 -measurable function T : R P(2<ω ) such that for each partition of 2 ω 2 ω into A 1 1 and C 1 1 there exists x R such that lim T (x) A x or lim T (x) C x. Proof. We begin with a lemma. Lemma 13. Given x 2 ω, for any partition of ω 2 ω into A Σ1 1(x) and C Π 1 1 (x) there is a 1 2 (x)-recursive function T : ω P(2<ω ) such that for each n ω we have lim T (n) A n or lim T (n) C n. Proof. Pick a sufficiently large fragment ZFC of ZFC and consider the set H = {c 2 ω : M a countable transitive model of ZFC containing x and c is a Cohen real over M}. Since H is Σ 1 2 (x), it contains a 1 2 (x) element c. For each n < ω both A n and C n have the Baire property and are coded in any model containing x. Hence, if c A n, then A n is nonmeager and if c C n, then C n is nonmeager. Put S = {n ω : c A n }, P = {n ω : c C n } and note that both sets S and P are 1 2 (x). We shall define the function T on S and P separately. For each n P the set C n is nonmeager, and so in particular contains a perfect set. Consider the set P = {(n, T ) ω P(2 <ω ) : n P lim T C n } and note that P is Σ2 1(x). Pick any Σ 2 1(x) uniformization T P of P and note that T P is in 1 2 (x). For each n S the set A n is nonmeager. Let D ω 2 ω ω ω be a Π1 0 (x) set projecting to A. Since for n S the set A n is nonmeager, we can use the Jankov von Neumann uniformization and the fact that any Baire measurable function can be restricted to a continuous one on a comeager set (which contains a perfect set) to get for n S a perfect tree T n together with a c continuous map h : {n} lim T n Dn. Note that, by compactness of lim T n, we can code a total continuous function on {n} lim T n using a monotone map. Consider the set S = {(n, T ) ω P(2 <ω ) : n S f : {n} lim T c D n } and note that S is Σ 1 2 (x). Pick any Σ 1 2 (x) uniformization T S of S and note that T s is 1 2 (x). The function T = T P T S is as required. Now we finish the proof of the proposition. Fix a good Σ2 1-universal set U ω 2ω ω ω such that for each A ω ω and x 2 ω if A Σ2 1 (x), then there is n < ω such that A = U (n,x). Let U U be a Σ 1 2 -uniformization of U treated as a subset of (ω 2ω ω) ω and write R = {(n, x) ω 2 ω : m < ω k < ω (m, k) U (n,x) and U (n,x) codes a characteristic function of a perfect tree}, where the coding is done via a fixed recursive bijection from ω to 2 <ω. Note that R Σ 1 2.

1192 M. Sabok / Advances in Mathematics 230 (2012) 1184 1195 For (n, x) R we write {n}(x) for the perfect tree coded by U(n,x). Note that (n, x) {n}(x) is a partial Σ2 1-recursive function from ω 2ω to P(2 <ω ). Now pick a recursive homeomorphism h : 2 ω ω 2 ω and write h(x) = (n x, x ). Put R = h 1 (R ) and T (x) = {n x }(x ) for x R. We claim that R and T are as required. To see this, pick a partition of 2 ω 2 ω into A 1 1 and C 1 1. Let z 2ω be such that A Σ1 1(z) and C Π 1 1(z). Let T : ω P(2<ω ) be a 1 2 (z)-recursive function as in Lemma 13. For each n ω we have that T (n) is a total Σ2 1 (z)-recursive function from ω to ω coding a perfect tree. Therefore, by the Kleene Recursion Theorem for Σ2 1 (z)-recursive functions [13, Theorem 7A.2] there is n ω such that T (n) = U (n,z) = {n}(z). Now x = h 1 (n, z) has the desired property. Now we are ready to prove Theorem 11. Proof of Theorem 11. Pick a 1 2 set R 2ω and a 1 2 -measurable function T : R P(2<ω ) as in Proposition 12. For each x R let t(x) T (x) be the first splitting node of T (x) and let T 0, T 1 : R P(2 <ω ) be defined as T i (x) = T (x) t(x) i for i 2. Note that T 0 and T 1 are also 1 2 -measurable. For x R let s 0 x, s1 x : 2ω lim T i (x) be induced by the canonical isomorphism of 2 <ω and T i (x). It is not difficult to see that for each i 2 the map (x, y) (x, s i x (y)) is a 1 2 -measurable function from R 2ω to R 2 ω. For each n ω let R n (2 ω ) n+1 be defined as R n = {(x 0,..., x n ) (2 ω ) n+1 : x 0 R x n 1 R}. For each τ 2 <ω put X τ = (2 ω ) τ +2 and write R τ for a copy of R τ inside X τ. Pick a homeomorphism q : 2 ω 2 ω 2 ω. For each n ω let p n+1 : X τ X τ τ 2 n+1 τ 2 n be a partial function such that dom(p n+1 ) = τ 2 n+1 R τ and if τ 2 n+1, τ = σ i, then p n+1 maps R τ into R σ as follows: p n+1 (x 0,..., x n 1, x n, x n+1 ) = (x 0,..., x n 1, s i x n (q(x n, x n+1 ))) ( ) for (x 0,..., x n+1 ) R τ (the value is treated as a point in R σ ). Note that each p n+1 is 1 2 - measurable and 1 1. We get the following sequence of spaces and partial 1 2-measurable maps: 2 ω 2 ω = X p 1 X 0 X 1 p 2 p n τ 2 n X τ p n+1 τ 2 n+1 X τ p n+2 and we write t n for p 1 p n for n > 0 and t 0 for the identity function on 2 ω 2 ω

M. Sabok / Advances in Mathematics 230 (2012) 1184 1195 1193 Now, let E(2 ω ) 2 ω 2 ω be defined as E(2 ω ) = rng(t n ). n<ω Notice that E(2 ω ) 1 2. The map r : E(2ω ) 2 ω is defined as follows. For n ω and τ 2 n we put r(x) n = τ iff (t n ) 1 (x) X τ. Note that r is 1 2 -measurable. We need to check that E(2 ω ) and r satisfy the properties of expansion. Let f : 2 ω Y be 1 1 1 1-submeasurable, where Y is a zero-dimensional Polish space. Since Y is embedded into 2 ω and inherits its subbase from 2 ω via this embedding, we can assume that Y = 2 ω and the subbase consists of the sets [(n, i)] for n ω, i 2. We shall define two trees x τ : τ 2 <ω and u τ : τ 2 <ω such that for each τ 2 <ω and i 2 we have x τ (2 ω ) τ +1 and u τ 2 τ +1 u τ u τ i and x τ x τ i, and ( f t n ) (X τ x τ ) [u τ ] where X τ x τ = {y X τ : y ( τ + 1) = x τ y n+1 T (y n )}. Suppose this has been done. Note that then for each n ω and τ 2 n the sets F τ = t n (X τ x τ ) are closed since, by ( ), t n is a continuous function of the last variable when the remaining ones are fixed. The sets F τ form a Luzin scheme of closed sets. Put F = F τ. n<ω τ 2 n We define g : 2 ω 2 ω so that g(y) n<ω[u y n ]. Note that g is continuous. From ( ) we get that g (r F) = f F. Now we build the trees x τ : τ 2 <ω and u τ : τ 2 <ω. We construct them by induction as follows. The two sets f 1 ([(0, 0)]) and f 1 ([(0, 1)]) form a partition 2 ω 2 ω into two sets, one of which is 1 1 and the other 1 1, by the assumption that f is 1 1 1 1-submeasurable. By Proposition 12 there are x R and i 2 such that T (x) f 1 [[(0, i)]]. Put x = x, u = i and note that ( ) is satisfied. Suppose that n > 0, and x σ and u σ are constructed for all σ 2 n 1. Fix τ 2 n and let τ = σ i for some σ 2 n 1 and i 2. We must find x τ (2 ω ) n+1 and u τ 2 n+1. Note that the set {y X τ : y n = x σ } is homeomorphic to 2 ω 2 ω. Let w : 2 ω 2 ω {y X τ : y n = x σ } denote the canonical homeomorphism y x σ y. Consider the partition of 2 ω 2 ω into ( f i n+1 w) 1 ([(n 1, 0)]) and ( f i n+1 w) 1 ([(n 1, 1)]). ( )

1194 M. Sabok / Advances in Mathematics 230 (2012) 1184 1195 One of them is 1 1 and the other 1 1, so by Proposition 12, there exist x R and i 2 such that T (x) ( f i n+1 w) 1 ([(n 1, i)]). Put x τ = x σ x and u τ = u σ i. To see that ( ) holds note that p n+1 (X τ x τ ) X σ x σ by the definition ( ). Therefore, by the inductive assumption we have that ( f t n+1 ) (X τ x τ ) [u σ ] [(n 1, i)] = [u τ ]. This ends the construction and the whole proof. 5. An application to forcing Given a (real-definable) family Φ of analytic sets we say that Φ is ZFC-correct [16, Definition 2.1.16] if there is a finite fragment ZFC of ZFC such that for any A 1 1 and any transitive model M of ZFC containing a code for A and Φ, we have that M = A Φ if and only if V = A Φ. Now we prove Corollary 3. Proof of Corollary 3. Let A ω ω [ω] ω be a good universal 1 1 set. We have to show that the σ -ideal of Ramsey null sets is not ZFC-correct. Suppose otherwise. Then we can express the fact that A x is Ramsey null as M a countable transitive model of ZFC x M M = A x is Ramsey null or, equivalently, as M a countable transitive model of ZFC x M M = A x is Ramsey null, where ZFC is a fragment of ZFC recognizing the correctness of the σ -ideal of Ramsey null sets. Using the standard way of coding countable transitive models with reals (see [9, Chapter 25] or [12]), we get that the first statement is 1 2 and the second one is 1 2. This gives that {x 2 ω : A x is Ramsey positive} is 1 2, which contradicts Theorem 1. Acknowledgments Part of this work was done during the author s stay at the Institut Mittag-Leffler in autumn 2009 and at the Kurt Gödel Research Center in winter 2010. He would like to thank Joan Bagaria, Daisuke Ikegami and Stevo Todorčević for stimulating discussions. The author is also grateful to Janusz Pawlikowski and Jindřich Zapletal for valuable comments. This research was supported by the Mittag-Leffler Institute (Djursholm, Sweden), by the ESF INFTY program, by the MNiSW (Polish Ministry of Science and Higher Education) grant N N201 418939 and by the Foundation for Polish Science. References [1] S. Adams, A. Kechris, Linear algebraic groups and countable Borel equivalence relations, J. Amer. Math. Soc. 13 (2000) 909 943. [2] H. Becker, S. Kahane, A. Louveau, Some complete 1 2 sets in harmonic analysis, Trans. Amer. Math. Soc. 339 (1993) 323 336. [3] J. Brendle, Y. Khomskii, Polarized partitions on the second level of the projective hierarchy, Annals of Pure and Applied Logic (in press). [4] E. Ellentuck, A new proof that analytic sets are Ramsey, J. Symbolic Logic 39 (1974) 163 165. [5] F. Galvin, K. Prikry, Borel sets and Ramsey s theorem, J. Symbolic Logic 38 (1973) 193 198.

M. Sabok / Advances in Mathematics 230 (2012) 1184 1195 1195 [6] L.A. Harrington, A.S. Kechris, On the determinacy of games on ordinals, Ann. Math. Log. 20 (2) (1981) 109 154. [7] J.I. Ihoda, S. Shelah, 1 2-sets of reals, Ann. Pure Appl. Logic 42 (3) (1989) 207 223. [8] D. Ikegami, Forcing absoluteness and regularity properties, Ann. Pure Appl. Logic 161 (2010) 879 894. [9] T. Jech, Set Theory, in: Springer Monographs in Mathematics, Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 2003, The third millennium edition, revised and expanded. [10] A.S. Kechris, Classical Descriptive Set Theory, Springer-Verlag, New York, 1994. [11] A.S. Kechris, On the concept of 1 1-completeness, Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. 125 (6) (1997) 1811 1814. [12] R. Mansfield, G. Weitkamp, Recursive Aspects of Descriptive Set Theory, in: Oxford Logic Guides, vol. 11, The Clarendon Press Oxford University Press, New York, 1985. [13] Y.N. Moschovakis, Descriptive Set Theory, second ed., in: Mathematical Surveys and Monographs, vol. 155, American Mathematical Society, Providence, RI, 2009. [14] J. Silver, Every analytic set is Ramsey, J. Symbolic Logic 35 (1970) 60 64. [15] S. Todorcevic, Introduction to Ramsey Spaces, in: Annals of Mathematics Studies, vol. 174, Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ, 2010. [16] J. Zapletal, Forcing Idealized, vol. 174, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2008.