Quantum Measurements: some technical background

Similar documents
Quantum decoherence. Éric Oliver Paquette (U. Montréal) -Traces Worshop [Ottawa]- April 29 th, Quantum decoherence p. 1/2

Lecture 13B: Supplementary Notes on Advanced Topics. 1 Inner Products and Outer Products for Single Particle States

Hardy s Paradox. Chapter Introduction

Philosophy of QM Eighth lecture, 23 February 2005

Ensembles and incomplete information

1 Mach-Zehder Interferometer 1. 2 Elitzur-Vaidman Bombs 6

Decoherence and the Classical Limit

Quantum Information Types

Delayed Choice Paradox

C/CS/Phys C191 Amplitude Amplification, Quantum Zeno, Vaidman s bomb 11/10/09 Fall 2009 Lecture 22

PHY305: Notes on Entanglement and the Density Matrix

Coherent states, beam splitters and photons

Similarities and Differences Between Two-Particle and Three-Particle Interference

Introduction to Quantum Computing

Weak measurements: subensembles from tunneling to Let s Make a Quantum Deal to Hardy s Paradox

2 Quantum Mechanics. 2.1 The Strange Lives of Electrons

Introduction to Quantum Information Hermann Kampermann

A review on quantum teleportation based on: Teleporting an unknown quantum state via dual classical and Einstein- Podolsky-Rosen channels

Coins and Counterfactuals

Some Introductory Notes on Quantum Computing

Short Course in Quantum Information Lecture 2

1 Mathematical preliminaries

Intro to Quantum Physics

Problem Set: TT Quantum Information

Introduction to Quantum Information Processing QIC 710 / CS 768 / PH 767 / CO 681 / AM 871

b) (5 points) Give a simple quantum circuit that transforms the state

Detection of photonic Bell states

S.K. Saikin May 22, Lecture 13

The Stern-Gerlach experiment and spin

Quantum Mechanics C (130C) Winter 2014 Final exam

Quantum Mechanics: Interpretation and Philosophy

If quantum mechanics hasn t profoundly shocked you, you haven t understood it.

Identical Particles in Quantum Mechanics

Does Quantum Measurement Violate the Conservation of Angular Momentum? A Paradox Resolved Rick Bradford, 6/12/16

Quantum control of dissipative systems. 1 Density operators and mixed quantum states

Chapter 5. Density matrix formalism

Decoherence and The Collapse of Quantum Mechanics. A Modern View

3. Quantum Mechanics in 3D

Consistent Histories. Chapter Chain Operators and Weights

Ph 219/CS 219. Exercises Due: Friday 3 November 2006

Superposition - World of Color and Hardness

Lecture 14: Quantum information revisited

Density Matrices. Chapter Introduction

Introduction to Quantum Mechanics

1 Algebra of State Vectors

A Wheeler-Feynman Electromagnetic Transaction

Interference Between Distinguishable States. Thomas Alexander Meyer

AQI: Advanced Quantum Information Lecture 6 (Module 2): Distinguishing Quantum States January 28, 2013

Chemistry 271 Quantum Mechanics

Introduction to Quantum Cryptography

Qubits vs. bits: a naive account A bit: admits two values 0 and 1, admits arbitrary transformations. is freely readable,

The Particle in a Box

Contextuality and the Kochen-Specker Theorem. Interpretations of Quantum Mechanics

Time-Independent Perturbation Theory

Entanglement of projection and a new class of quantum erasers

The Weird World of Quantum Mechanics

Topic 2: The mathematical formalism and the standard way of thin

4. Two-level systems. 4.1 Generalities

Unitary evolution: this axiom governs how the state of the quantum system evolves in time.

Ph 219/CS 219. Exercises Due: Friday 20 October 2006

Singlet State Correlations

When Worlds Collide: Quantum Probability From Observer Selection?

Incompatibility Paradoxes

E = hν light = hc λ = ( J s)( m/s) m = ev J = ev

Modern Physics notes Spring 2007 Paul Fendley Lecture 27

OPERATORS AND MEASUREMENT

1. Basic rules of quantum mechanics

Lecture: Quantum Information

IDLER DCC SIGNAL SHUTTER

Lecture 4: Postulates of quantum mechanics

FIG. 16: A Mach Zehnder interferometer consists of two symmetric beam splitters BS1 and BS2

INTRODUCTORY NOTES ON QUANTUM COMPUTATION

Lecture 18: Quantum Information Theory and Holevo s Bound

Counterfactual quantum protocols

Logical AND. Logical XOR

II. The Machinery of Quantum Mechanics

Experimental quantum teleportation. Dirk Bouwmeester, Jian Wei Pan, Klaus Mattle, Manfred Eibl, Harald Weinfurter & Anton Zeilinger

De-coherence and transition from Quantum to Classical

Quantum Entanglement. Chapter Introduction. 8.2 Entangled Two-Particle States

2. Introduction to quantum mechanics

8.04: Quantum Mechanics Professor Allan Adams. Problem Set 7. Due Tuesday April 9 at 11.00AM

Physics 202 Laboratory 5. Linear Algebra 1. Laboratory 5. Physics 202 Laboratory

HSSP Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics 08/07/11 Lecture Notes


A Simple Model of Quantum Trajectories. Todd A. Brun University of Southern California

This is the important completeness relation,

Solutions Final exam 633

ECE 487 Lecture 6 : Time-Dependent Quantum Mechanics I Class Outline:

Measurement: still a problem in standard quantum theory

Quantum Computing Lecture 3. Principles of Quantum Mechanics. Anuj Dawar

Quantum Mechanics- I Prof. Dr. S. Lakshmi Bala Department of Physics Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Erwin Schrödinger and his cat

How to use the simulator

Compression and entanglement, entanglement transformations

Wave function collapse

Physics 239/139 Spring 2018 Assignment 2 Solutions

Basics on quantum information

MP 472 Quantum Information and Computation

Density Operators and Ensembles

Ph 12b. Homework Assignment No. 3 Due: 5pm, Thursday, 28 January 2010

Transcription:

Quantum Measurements: some technical background [From the projection postulate to density matrices & (introduction to) von Neumann measurements] (AKA: the boring lecture) First: One more example I wanted to get to last time about odd sorts of measurements and the surprises in store... PHY 2206, lecture 2 (17.1.12)

" Quantum seeing in the dark " (AKA: The Elitzur-Vaidman bomb experiment) A. Elitzur, and L. Vaidman, Found. Phys. 23, 987 (1993) P.G. Kwiat, H. Weinfurter, and A. Zeilinger, Sci. Am. (Nov., 1996) Problem: Consider a collection of bombs so sensitive that a collision with any single particle (photon, electron, etc.) is guarranteed to trigger it. Suppose that certain of the bombs are defective, but differ in their behaviour in no way other than that they will not blow up when triggered. Is there any way to identify the working bombs (or some of them) without blowing them up?

" Quantum seeing in the dark " C (AKA: The Elitzur-Vaidman bomb experiment) A. Elitzur, and L. Vaidman, Found. Phys. 23, 987 (1993) P.G. Kwiat, H. Weinfurter, and A. Zeilinger, Sci. Am. (Nov., 1996) D BS2 Bomb absent: Only detector C fires BS1

" Quantum seeing in the dark " C (AKA: The Elitzur-Vaidman bomb experiment) A. Elitzur, and L. Vaidman, Found. Phys. 23, 987 (1993) P.G. Kwiat, H. Weinfurter, and A. Zeilinger, Sci. Am. (Nov., 1996) D BS2 BS1 Bomb absent: Only detector C fires Bomb present: "boom!" 1/2 C 1/4 D 1/4 The bomb must be there... yet my photon never interacted with it.

The measurement postulate

...measurement outcomes... Collapse of the wavefunction Future measurements of A will of course agree with this a i Measurement State preparation

What are the effects of measurement? Suppose we have two pawns, one black and one white, and I put one in each hand we can write this state as something like = + Obviously, if I open my left hand and measure the colour of its pawn, I find either black or white, not both from that point on, I describe the left pawn as one colour eigenstate, or. Is the other pawn still in a state of uncertain colour? No obviously, its state has also been affected by this measurement.

More refined version: the projection postulate When a i is found, the state Of course, this is not normalized, so the final state is actually Finding the left pawn to be black leaves the system in a state where the right pawn is known to be white (unsurprisingly).

Two effects of measurement 1. One thing happens, as opposed to all other possibilities 2. Interference between the different possibilities becomes impossible. 100% 50% 50% What s the state of the particles before the final beam-splitter? det. 2 A det. 1 B If no bomb was present, half the particles are in path A and half are in path B. If the bomb measures which path each is in... then still, half are in path A and half are in path B. The measurement didn t change the probabilistic description of the state... but without the bomb, interference caused all particles to interfere at the final beam splitter and go left; with the bomb, there is no such interference. Measurement destroyed phase information, but left the probabilities unchanged. A + e iϕ B A OR B.

How does the bomb cause the other detector to fire? The probability is given by the absolute square of this inner product, which is 1/4 + 1/4 = 1/2 (because the orthogonality of "peace" and "BOOM" cause the cross-terms to vanish).

Sneaky fact... No one knows why one thing happens instead of many simultaneous things... in fact, no one knows whether this is true (cf. relative-state, many-worlds, many-minds interpretations). No collapse process has ever been observed i.e., no case where we would make the wrong predictions if we didn t assume collapse. Yet to make sense of probabilities, one typically assumes that by the time you measure something, it s one thing or another. (But how do you know that when I measured it, I wasn t still in a probabilistic state? Wigner s friend. ) We can try (a) to understand what measurements do to coherence and/or (b) to search for a real collapse process, supplementary to quantum mechanics as we know it.

Statistical Mixtures How should we describe a statistical mixture, i.e., half the time I ll send you state A and half the time I ll send you state B? Classically: P(x) = P(x B) P(B) + P(x A) P(A) +... QM: shall we say Ψ(x) = Ψ Β (x) P(B) + Ψ Α (x) P(A) +...? P(x A) P(x Ψ A + Ψ B ) P(x B)

We need a formalism for this... A simpler example: a spin-1/2. In +z >, <S x > = <S y > = 0. In z>, <S x > = <S y > = 0. So in a 50/50 mixture, we d have <S x > = <S y > = 0, but no { +z> + e iφ z> } / 2 satisfies this. (They are all spins in the xy plane, with angle φ.) Any QM wave function you write down which is half A and half B will exhibit some interference; no wave function can describe the state after a measurement of A & B, which we all know makes interference impossible... "Pure states" "Mixed states" individual QM wave functions probabilistic mixtures of QM states. (e.g., results of measurements) "Density Matrices"

Statistical mixtures... Conclusion: no superposition state (that is, no quantum state at all) correctly describes a statistical mixture. What s wrong? We need P(x) = { P(x A) + P(x B) } / 2, but P(x) = Ψ(x) 2, which isn t linear in Ψ. We would like a description of the state ρ such that probabilities were linear in ρ; then only could we naturally describe mixtures of such states. Well, remember that P(i) = <i Ψ><Ψ i>... this isn t linear in Ψ>, but it is linear in Ψ><Ψ ; perhaps that projector is a more desirable description of the quantum state than the wave function.

A linear description of the q. state So, let us define ρ = Ψ><Ψ

Was that clear? Who can define the trace for me in Dirac notation?

And what about mixed states? So instead of a wave function Ψ>, we describe a pure state by the density matrix ρ = Ψ><Ψ ; and we replace the formula <A> = <Ψ A Ψ> with the equivalent <A> = Tr ρ A. The essential property of a statistical mixture is that all expectation values are just the weighted averages of those for the individual pure states. Our expression for expectation values is linear in the density matrix i.e., we can keep using that expression with mixed states, if we define the mixed-state density matrix itself as a weighted average.

Density matrices

Interpretation of matrix elements pure Diagonal elements = probabilities Off-diagonal elements = "coherences" (provide info. about relative phase)

Density matrices for mixed states Note: probabilities still 50/50, but no coherence.

Purity Tr ρ = 1 is required for total probability = 1. (Or realize that Tr ρ = Tr ρi = <I> = 1 trivially.) As a Hermitian matrix, ρ can be diagonalized. For a pure state, ρ is a projector onto Ψ, so one eigenstate is Ψ (with eigenvalue 1) and all others have eigenvalue 0. ρ 2 is thus exactly the same. I.e., Ψ><Ψ Ψ><Ψ = Ψ> 1 <Ψ = Ψ><Ψ For a pure state, Tr ρ 2 = 1. For an impure state, no diagonalization into a single projector exists, so Tr ρ = Σ P i = 1 but Tr ρ 2 = Σ P i 2 < 1. This quantity Tr ρ 2 is sometimes called the linear purity. Any mixed state -- even one made by combining nonorthogonal states -- can be written as a mixture of orthogonal states. Decompositions are not unique.

What happens if you don't look at part of your system? When you calculate expectation values, you trace over the system. If your operators depend only on a subsystem, then it makes no difference whether you trace over other systems before or after:

Decoherence arises from throwing away information Taking this trace over the environment retains only terms diagonal in the environment variables i.e., no cross-terms (coherences) remain if they refer to different states of the environment. (If there is any way even in principle to tell which of two paths was followed, then no interference may occur.) ρ s when env is ρ s when env is

... coherence lost There is still coherence between and, but if the environment is not part of your interferometer, you may as well consider it to have "collapsed" to or. This means there is no effective coherence if you look only at the system.

It doesn t matter what the environment measures! We ve been talking as though sometimes the environment sees +z and sometimes it sees -z, and then we mix the two. But what if some evil experimenter in the environment decided to measure ±x instead of ±z? It wouldn t change a thing. The trace is basis-independent; when I sum over all possible states of the environment, this means it doesn t matter whether I m ignoring the outcome of an x- measurement or a z-measurement. This is important! It means nothing I do on the environment (no rotation, in this instance) changes the probability distribution observed on the system.

Decoherence: the party line When a particle interacts with a measurement device, the two subsystems become entangled (no separable description). Coherence is still present, but only in the entire system; if there is enough information in the measurement device to tell which path your subsystem followed, then it is impossible to observe interference without looking at both parts of the system. The effective density matrix of your system (traced over states of the measuring apparatus) is that of a mixed state. Coherence is never truly lost, as unitary evolution preserves the purity of states. In principle, this measurement interaction is reversible. In practice, once the system interacts with the "environment", i.e., anything with too many degrees of freedom for us to handle, we cannot reverse it. Just as in classical statistical mechanics, it is the approximation of an open system which leads to effective irreversibility, and loss of information (increase of entropy). Loss of Information = Loss of Coherence