ADJUNCTION AND INVERSION OF ADJUNCTION

Similar documents
The Cone Theorem. Stefano Filipazzi. February 10, 2016

On a connectedness principle of Shokurov-Kollár type

Finite generation of pluricanonical rings

NOTES ON THE LOG MINIMAL MODEL PROGRAM

ON MAXIMAL ALBANESE DIMENSIONAL VARIETIES. Contents 1. Introduction 1 2. Preliminaries 1 3. Main results 3 References 6

Flops connect minimal models

SHOKUROV S REDUCTION THEOREM TO PRE LIMITING FLIPS

ON THE ADJUNCTION FORMULA ON 3-FOLDS IN CHARACTERISTIC p

arxiv: v1 [math.ag] 30 Apr 2018

FUNDAMENTAL THEOREMS FOR THE LOG MINIMAL MODEL PROGRAM

arxiv:math/ v3 [math.ag] 1 Mar 2006

arxiv: v1 [math.ag] 2 Apr 2015

Minimal Model Theory for Log Surfaces

arxiv: v1 [math.ag] 30 Sep 2013

Birational geometry of algebraic varieties

LOG-CANONICAL MODELS OF SINGULAR PAIRS AND ITS APPLICATIONS. Yuji Odaka and Chenyang Xu

Some Remarks on the Minimal Model Program

FACTORING 3-FOLD FLIPS AND DIVISORIAL CONTRACTIONS TO CURVES

BOUNDEDNESS OF MODULI OF VARIETIES OF GENERAL TYPE

THE MINIMAL MODEL PROGRAM FOR VARIETIES OF LOG GENERAL TYPE

ON THE NUMBER AND BOUNDEDNESS OF LOG MINIMAL MODELS OF GENERAL TYPE

ON THE NUMBER AND BOUNDEDNESS OF LOG MINIMAL MODELS OF GENERAL TYPE

FUNDAMENTAL THEOREMS FOR THE LOG MINIMAL MODEL PROGRAM

A CONE THEOREM FOR NEF CURVES

ON SHOKUROV S RATIONAL CONNECTEDNESS CONJECTURE

ON THE MODULI B-DIVISORS OF LC-TRIVIAL FIBRATIONS

arxiv: v1 [math.ag] 15 Apr 2013

ON SUBADDITIVITY OF THE LOGARITHMIC KODAIRA DIMENSION

ACC FOR LOG CANONICAL THRESHOLDS

locus such that Γ + F = 0. Then (Y, Γ = Γ + F ) is kawamata log terminal, and K Y + Γ = π (K X + ) + E + F. Pick H ample such that K Y + Γ + H is nef

Fundamental theorems for semi log canonical pairs

LOG MINIMAL MODELS ACCORDING TO SHOKUROV

EXISTENCE OF LOG CANONICAL FLIPS AND A SPECIAL LMMP

Singularities of linear systems and boundedness of Fano varieties. Caucher Birkar

ON SUBADDITIVITY OF THE LOGARITHMIC KODAIRA DIMENSION

arxiv: v2 [math.ag] 5 May 2015

BASE POINT FREE THEOREMS SATURATION, B-DIVISORS, AND CANONICAL BUNDLE FORMULA

arxiv:math/ v1 [math.ag] 11 Apr 2003 James McKernan and Yuri Prokhorov

arxiv:math/ v1 [math.ag] 6 Sep 1999

SINGULARITIES OF LOW DEGREE COMPLETE INTERSECTIONS

FINITE GENERATION OF THE LOG CANONICAL RING IN DIMENSION FOUR

Linear systems and Fano varieties: introduction

ON WEAK FANO VARIETIES WITH LOG CANONICAL SINGULARITIES

arxiv: v1 [math.ag] 7 Nov 2012

INVERSION OF ADJUNCTION IN HIGH CODIMENSION

AN INFORMAL INTRODUCTION TO THE MINIMAL MODEL PROGRAM

CANONICAL BUNDLE FORMULA AND VANISHING THEOREM

ON ECKL S PSEUDO-EFFECTIVE REDUCTION MAP

The sectional genus of quasi-polarised varieties

The Grothendieck Ring of Varieties

HYPERBOLICITY FOR LOG CANONICAL PAIRS AND THE CONE THEOREM

FANO MANIFOLDS AND BLOW-UPS OF LOW-DIMENSIONAL SUBVARIETIES. 1. Introduction

Minimal model program and moduli spaces

LOG MINIMAL MODELS FOR ARITHMETIC THREEFOLDS

EXISTENCE OF MINIMAL MODELS FOR VARIETIES OF LOG GENERAL TYPE

INTERSECTION THEORY CLASS 12

On singular Fano varieties with a divisor of Picard number one

EXTENSION OF SECTIONS VIA ADJOINT IDEALS. 1. Introduction

mult V f, where the sum ranges over prime divisor V X. We say that two divisors D 1 and D 2 are linearly equivalent, denoted by sending

PURELY LOG TERMINAL THREEFOLDS WITH NON-NORMAL CENTRES IN CHARACTERISTIC TWO

arxiv: v1 [math.ag] 4 Nov 2018

7. Classification of Surfaces The key to the classification of surfaces is the behaviour of the canonical

Varieties fibred over abelian varieties with fibres of log general type. Caucher Birkar and Jungkai Alfred Chen

Dedicated to Mel Hochster on his 65th birthday. 1. Introduction

The Noether Inequality for Algebraic Threefolds

the complete linear series of D. Notice that D = PH 0 (X; O X (D)). Given any subvectorspace V H 0 (X; O X (D)) there is a rational map given by V : X

Singularities of (L)MMP and applications. Massimiliano Mella. Dipartimento di Matematica, Università di Ferrara, Italia address:

ON EXISTENCE OF LOG MINIMAL MODELS

CAUCHER BIRKAR. Abstract. We prove that the Iitaka conjecture C n,m for algebraic fibre spaces holds up to dimension 6, that is, when n 6.

ON THE MINIMAL MODEL THEORY FOR DLT PAIRS OF NUMERICAL LOG KODAIRA DIMENSION ZERO

arxiv:math/ v1 [math.ag] 6 Aug 2002

LECTURES ON SINGULARITIES AND ADJOINT LINEAR SYSTEMS

arxiv: v1 [math.ag] 4 Jun 2007

ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY I, FALL 2016.

Journal of Algebra 369 (2012) Contents lists available at SciVerse ScienceDirect. Journal of Algebra.

EXISTENCE OF MINIMAL MODELS FOR VARIETIES OF LOG GENERAL TYPE

IMAGES OF MANIFOLDS WITH SEMI-AMPLE ANTI-CANONICAL DIVISOR

arxiv: v4 [math.ag] 16 Mar 2019

ACC for log canonical thresholds and termination of log flips. Caucher Birkar. May 28, 2006

Porteous s Formula for Maps between Coherent Sheaves

Introduction to the log minimal model program for log canonical pairs

arxiv: v1 [math.ag] 3 Mar 2009

Effective birationality

Index. Cambridge University Press Singularities of the Minimal Model Program János Kollár. Index.

Logarithmic geometry and rational curves

Smoothable del Pezzo surfaces with quotient singularities

Linear systems and Fano varieties: BAB, and related topics

Birational geometry for d-critical loci and wall-crossing in Calabi-Yau 3-folds

arxiv: v1 [math.ag] 25 Jan 2013

INTERSECTION THEORY CLASS 6

KAWAMATA VIEHWEG VANISHING THEOREM

Letters of a Bi-rationalist. VII Ordered Termination

EXISTENCE OF MINIMAL MODELS FOR VARIETIES OF LOG GENERAL TYPE II

COMPLEX ALGEBRAIC SURFACES CLASS 9

CHARACTERIZATION OF VARIETIES OF FANO TYPE VIA SINGULARITIES OF COX RINGS

Some questions on minimal log discrepancies

MA 206 notes: introduction to resolution of singularities

EXAMPLES OF CALABI-YAU 3-MANIFOLDS WITH COMPLEX MULTIPLICATION

APPENDIX 3: AN OVERVIEW OF CHOW GROUPS

arxiv:math/ v3 [math.ag] 17 Feb 2011

Transcription:

ADJUNCTION AND INVERSION OF ADJUNCTION STEFANO FILIPAZZI Abstract. These notes are meant to be a handout for the student seminar in algebraic geometry at the University of Utah. They are a short introduction to the notions of adjunction and inversion of adjunction for pairs. Contents. Introduction 2. Adjunction on singular varieties: the different 2 3. A quick review of singularities of pairs 3 4. Adjunction and singularities 4 5. Log canonical inversion of adjunction 5 References 7. Introduction Among the techniques in birational geometry, adjunction theory is one of the most powerful tools. It allows to relate the geometry, and in particular the singularities, of the ambient variety with the one of appropriate subvarieites. We call adjunction the process of inferring statements about a subvariety from some knowledge of the ambient variety, while the inverse and usually more complicated process is called inversion of adjunction. The most satisfactory formulation of this theory in the case of pairs is the following, due to Hacon [Hac4]. Theorem. ([Hac4, Theorem 0.]). Let V be a log canonical center of a pair (X, = δ i i ) where 0 δ i. Then (X, ) is log canonical in a neighborhood of V if and only if (V, B(V ; X, )) is log canonical. In the case V has codimension, the statement takes the following and simpler form, originally due to Kawakita [Kaw07]. Theorem.2 ([Kaw07]). Let (X, S + B) be a log pair such that S is a reduced divisor which has no common component with the support of B, let S ν denote the normalization of S, and let B ν denote the different of B on S ν. Then (X, S + B) is log canonical near S if and only if (S ν, B ν ) is log canonical. The purpose of this note is to give an overview of the ideas behind these results, and to present a slightly simplified version of Theorem.2. Date: August 4, 207.

2. Adjunction on singular varieties: the different Consider a smooth projective variety X, and let D be a smooth prime divisor on it. Then, the classic literature gives an explicit relation between the line bundles ω X = O X (K X ) and ω D = O D (K D ) [Har77, Proposition II.8.20]. The adjunction formula tells us that ω X (D) D = ωd. The above can be rephrased as (K X + D) D = K D in the language of divisors. A natural question is how much such a relation can be generalized in the case of singular varieties. We will explore this through an example. Let X be the cone over a projectively normal rational curve of degree n, and let L be a line through the vertex V. If we blow up V, we obtain a morphism π : X X, where X is smooth. Denote by L the strict transform of L, and by E the π-exceptional divisor. A direct computation shows that K X and L are a Q-Cartier divisor with the latter having Cartier index exactly n [Har77, cf. Example II.6.5.2]. Also, one can show that E 2 = n. What happens in the smooth case suggests to consider the divisor (K X +L) L. As K X +L is just a Q-Cartier divisor, the direct computation is not the most convenient approach. Instead, we notice that the morphism π L : L L obtained restricting π is an isomorphism. Under the identification given by π L, we have (K X + L) L = (π (K X + L)) L. As π is birational, we have K Y = π K X + ae for some a. The adjunction formula for smooth varieties gives us As E is a rational curve, this gives K E = (K Y + E) E = (π K X + (a + )E) E. 2 = deg(π K X + (a + )E) E = (π K X + (a + )E) E = n(a + ). Thus, we have a = + 2 n. By construction, nl H, where H is a very ample divisor with H 2 = n. In particular, this implies L 2 = n. Now, consider π L = L + be. Then, we have n = L2 = (π L) 2 = L 2 + 2b L E + E 2. As L 2 = 0 and L E =, we conclude that b =. n Putting all the above together, we get ( ( (K X + L) L = K Y + L + ) E) n L = K L + ( ) O, n where {0} := L E is identified with V via π L. We will call the correction term appearing in the formula different, and we will write ( Diff(0) := ) V. n 2

Such a term appears because of the singularities of X, and the fact that L is not a Cartier divisor. This example illustrates how in birational geometry it is natural to consider the notion of pair (X, ), where X is a normal projective variety, and is an effective Q-divisor such that K X + is Q-Cartier. Indeed, on a mildly singular variety as the cone over a rational curve, the natural operation of adjunction produces a pair with non-zero boundary. This is a common phenomenon, as many proofs in higher dimensional geometry rely on induction on dimension and adjunction. Therefore, even if we are interested in statement A for varieties, the inductive step would require having knowledge of statement A for pairs in lower dimension. Now, assume that (X, ) is a pair, where = S + B, with S normal prime divisor. Let π : Y X a log resolution of (X, ), i.e. a birational morphism with Y smooth, and Supp(π ) + Ex(π) is a simple normal crossing divisor. Denote by S the strict transform of S. Then, we can write and then define K Y + Y = π (K X + ), Diff(B) := π S, (( Y S) S), where π S : S S is the restriction of π. One can show that the definition does not depend on Y, and that Diff(B) is effective [Hac4]. Thus, this procedure provides us with a new pair (S, Diff(B)). 3. A quick review of singularities of pairs Given a pair (X, ), it is natural to introduce some measure of its singularities. As K X + is Q-Cartier, for any birational morphism π : Y X from a normal variety, we can consider K Y + Y = π (K X + ), where Y is implicitly defined, given the choice π K Y = K X. If X is smooth and = 0, then Y < 0 for all Y X. On the other hand, as we saw with the cone over a rational curve, this is not always the case for singular varieties. Furthermore, if 0, the bigger its coefficients are, the more positive Y becomes. In particular, if has some irreducible component with coefficient greater than one, one can find a higher model Y where some coefficient of Y gets arbitrarily positive [KM98, cf. Chapter 2]. Therefore, the coefficients of Y, as Y varies among the higher birational models of X, measure how singular the pair (X, ) is. We say that (X, ) is Kawamata log terminal, in short klt, if for any divisor E on a model Y we have mult E ( Y ) <. Similarly, we say that (X, ) is log canonical, in short lc, if mult E ( Y ) for any such E. Log canonical singularities are the broader class of singularities appearing in the minimal model program. Kawamata log terminal singularities represent a class of milder singularities, and they are considerably better behaved than general log canonical ones. Given a pair (X, ), there is an algorithmic way to determine whether it is klt or lc. Let π : Y X be a log resolution of (X, ). Then, (X, ) is klt if and only if mult E ( Y ) < for any prime divisor E on Y. Similarly, (X, ) is lc if and only if mult E ( Y ) for any such E [KM98, cf. Lemma 2.30 and Corollary 2.3]. 3

As our main focus is adjunction, we are interested in pairs (X, ) with = S +B, and S normal prime divisor. Clearly, (X, ) is not klt, as mult S ( ) =. Still, we can ask for it to be almost klt. If a pair (X, ) is log canonical, and, in addition, mult E ( Y ) < for all Y and E exceptional over X, we say that (X, ) is purely log terminal, in short plt. Thus, a pair (X, ) is plt if the multiplicities of the exceptional divisors behave as in the klt case, while is allowed to have components with coefficient. 4. Adjunction and singularities In the previous sections we introduced the notion of different, and discussed a way of measuring the singularities of a pair. Given a pair (X, = S +B), the adjunction formula provides a new pair (S, Diff(B)). Therefore, it is natural to investigate how the singularities of these two relate. Let π : Y X be a log resolution of the pair (X, S+B), and denote by π S : S S the induced morphism from the strict transform of S to S itself. As S is part of the boundary, S is smooth, and Ex(π S) = Ex(π) S. Thus, as S + Ex(π) is a simple normal crossing divisor, π S is a log resolution of (S, Diff(B)). Now, we want to rephrase what it means for (X, S +B) and (S, Diff(B)) to have a certain kind of singularities in terms of the coefficients of the π-exceptional divisors. By further blow-ups, we may assume that every π-exceptional divisor intersecting S has center contained in S. Then, write Y = i a i D i, and define divisors A := i a i < a i D i, F := i a i a i D i. First, we notice that (X, S + B) is log canonical if and only if F = F, and it is plt if and only if it is log canonical, F is not exceptional, and it is the disjoint union of its irreducible components [KM98, cf. Corollary 2.3 and Proposition 5.5]. Now, define F := F S. Then, (S, Diff(B)) is klt if and only if S F =. Similarly, (S, Diff(B)) is log canonical if and only if F = F holds in a neighborhood of S. Our goal is to relate the singularities of (X, S + B) and the ones of (S, Diff(B)). Clearly, we can not infer anything about the geometry of (X, S+B) away from S just looking at (S, Diff(B)). Therefore, we will more precisely be interested into relating the singularities of (X, S + B) in a neighborhood of S and the ones of (S, Diff(B)). Therefore, we have to refine the above observations in order to talk about the singularities of (X, S + B) in a neighborhood of S. The divisors contributing to the singularities in a neighborhood of S are the divisors on Y that map to S. Equivalently, they are the divisors on Y that intersect π (S). Hence, (X, S + B) is plt in a neighborhood of S if and only if π (S) F =. Analogously, (X, S + B) is log canonical near S if and only if F = F in a neighborhood of π (S). These observations lead to the following statement, also known as adjunction [KM98, cf. Proposition 5.46]. 4

Theorem 4.. Let (X, S + B) be a pair, where S is a normal prime divisor. If (X, S + B) is plt near S, then (S, Diff(B)) is klt. Analogously, if (X, S + B) is log canonical near S, then (S, Diff(B)) is log canonical. From the above discussion, it is not clear whether there is any way to reverse the implications in Theorem 4.. Indeed, imagine there are two exceptional divisors E and E 2 that are both mapped into S by π, and assume that E S and E 2 S =. As E E 2 π (S), we need to control the coefficients of both of them to infer anything about the singularities of (X, S + B) near S. On the other hand, only E contributes to the singularities of (S, Diff(B)), while E 2 is apparently irrelevant. Surprisingly, we have the following very powerful result. Theorem 4.2 ([KM98, Corollary 5.49]). Let g : Y X be a proper and birational morphism and D = d i D i a Q-divisor such that g D is effective and (K Y + D) is g-nef. Let Z Y be the subset of points where (Y, D) is not sub-klt. Then Z is connected in a neighborhood of any fiber of g. Theorem 4.2 is a direct consequence of the connectedness principle [KM98, Theorem 5.48]. As in the statement D is not necessarily effective, we say it is a subboundary. Thus, what is called klt in the case of pairs, is named sub-klt in such a setup. Now, we apply Theorem 4.2 to the above situation. The sub-boundary D will be Y. Thus, π Y = 0 is a boundary, and, as K Y + Y = π (K X + ), (K Y + Y ) is π-trivial. Hence, the hypotheses of Theorem 4.2 are satisfied. Then, assume (S, Diff(B)) is klt. For every x S there is an open neighborhood U x such that π (U x ) ( S F ) is connected. As S F =, we conclude that π (U x ) F =. As x varies in S, this implies that (X, S + B) is plt. Thus, we get a first formualtion of inversion of adjunction [KM98, cf. Theorem 5.50]. Theorem 4.3. Let (X, S + B) be a pair, where S is a normal prime divisor. Then, (X, S + B) is plt near S if and only if (S, Diff(B)) is klt. Unfortunately, a pair (X, ) may or may not be log canonical along the locus where it fails to be Kawamata log terminal. Therefore, Theorem 4.2 can not be applied to get a full statement for inversion of adjunction in the log canonical case. On the other hand, it can still be exploited to get some partial result in this direction [KM98, cf. Theorem 5.50]. 5. Log canonical inversion of adjunction As discussed in the previous section, it is natural to expect inversion of adjunction to hold also in the log canonical case. Unfortunately, the techniques illustrated so far are not powerful enough to perform such extension. Using more modern techniques, Kawakita proved inversion of adjunction in the log canonical case [Kaw07]. A few years later, using the techniques developed in [BCHM0], Hacon extended Kawakita s result to higher codimensional log canonical centers [Hac4]. The purpose of this section is to give a rough sketch of Hacon s approach, limiting ourselves to the divisorial case. We will adopt the notation introduced in the previous section. 5

Assume by contradiction that (S, Diff(B)) is log canonical, and (X, S + B) is not log canonical along S. Using the minimal model program [KK0, Theorem 3.], we can find a birational model π : Y X satisfying the following: Y is Q-factorial, i.e. every Weil divisor is Q-Cartier; Y = i a id i 0; (Y, Y := a i a id i + a i > D i), is dlt; every π-exceptional divisor appears in Y with coefficients at least. We recall that a pair (Y, Y ) is called dlt if it is log canonical, and it is simple normal crossing along the locus where it is not plt [KM98, cf. Definition 2.37]. Such a model is called dlt model of (X, ). Note that Y is not smooth in general. Let Γ := Y S, and define Σ := Y S Γ. As (S, Diff(B)) is log canonical, Σ S =. Now, fix an ample divisor H such that K Y + S + Γ + H is nef over X. Then, we can run a relative (K Y + S +Γ)-MMP over X with scaling of H [BCHM0, cf. 3.0]. This produces a sequence of birational maps φ i : Y i Y i+, which are flips or divisorial contractions, and induced morphisms π i : Y i X. For any divisor G on Y, we denote by G i its strict transform on Y i. In addition, there is a non-increasing sequence of rational numbers {s i } i 0 such that: either s N+ = 0 for some N N, or lim i s i = 0; K Yi + S i + Γ i + sh i is π i -nef for all s i s s i+. First, assume that S i Σ i for some i 0. Then, we can write (π i (K X + )) Si = K Si + Diff(Γ i + Σ i ). As S i Σ i, ( S i, Diff(Γ i + Σ i )) is not log canonical. On the other hand, as S i is normal and K Si + Diff(Γ i + Σ i ) = π Si (K S + Diff(B)), ( S i, Diff(Γ i + Σ i )) is log canonical. Thus, we get the required contradiction. Therefore, we may assume S i Σ i = for all i 0. One can show that there exists i 0 N such that, for any i i 0, S i S i+ is an isomoprhism in codimension. Then, fix m 0 such that mσ is an integral divisor. By the properties of the sequence {s i } i 0, we can find i i 0 such that s i > s m i+ and a divisor Θ i, m ) is klt and that (Y i, Θ i, m H i mσ i S i Q,X K Yi + Θ i, + (m ) m ( K Yi + S i + Γ i + ) m H i. such As K Yi + S i + Γ i + m H i is nef over X, we can apply Kawamata-Viehweg vanishing [KM98, cf. proof of Corollary 2.68 and Theorem 2.70]. It follows that R π i, O Yi (H i mσ i S i ) = 0. As a consequence, the morphism of sheaves π i, O Yi (H i mσ i ) π Si, O S i (H i mσ i ) = π Si, O S i (H i ) is surjective. On the other hand, for m 0 the subsheaves π i, O Yi (H i mσ i ) = π i0, O Yi0 (H i0 mσ i0 ) π i0, O Yi0 (H i0 ) 6

are contained in I πi0 (Σ i0 ) π i0, O Yi0 (H i0 ). Since we are assuming that (X, S + B) is not log canonical near S, we have S π i0 (Σ i0 ). As S i0 S i is an isomorphism in codimension, the induced homomorphism π i, O Yi (H i mσ i ) π Si, O Si (H i ) = π Si0, O Si0 (H i0 ) is not surjective. Thus, we get the required contradiction. This leads to a version of inversion of adjuction for log canonical pairs. Theorem 5. (cf. Theorem.2). Let (X, S + B) be a pair, where S is a normal prime divisor. Then, (X, S + B) is log canonical near S if and only if (S, Diff(B)) is log canonical. References [BCHM0] C. Brikar, P. Cascini, C. D. Hacon, and J. McKernan. Existence of minimal models for varieties of log general type. In: Journal of the American Mathematical Society 23.2 (200), pp. 405 468. [Hac4] C. D. Hacon. On the Log Canonical Inversion of Adjunction. In: Proceedings of the Edinburgh Mathematical Society 57. (204), pp. 39 43. [Har77] R. Hartshorne. Algebraic Geometry. Ed. by Springer-Verlag. Vol. 52. Graduate Texts in Mathematics. New York, 977. [Kaw07] M. Kawakita. Inversion of adjunction on log canonicity. In: Inventiones mathematicae 67. (2007), pp. 29 33. [KK0] J. Kollár and S. J. Kovács. Log canonical singularities are Du Bois. In: Journal of the American Mathematical Society 23.3 (200), pp. 79 83. [KM98] J. Kollár and S. Mori. Birational Geometry of Algebraic Varieties. Ed. by Cambridge University Press. Vol. 34. Cambridge Tracts in Mathematics. New York, 998. S. Filipazzi, Department of Mathematics, University of Utah, Salt Lake City, UT 842, USA E-mail address: filipazz@math.utah.edu 7