Lusin sequences under CH and under Martin s Axiom

Similar documents
Lusin sequences under CH and under Martin s Axiom

INSEPARABLE SEQUENCES AND FORCING

A variant of Namba Forcing

SELF-DUAL UNIFORM MATROIDS ON INFINITE SETS

The Proper Forcing Axiom: a tutorial

PROPER FORCING REMASTERED

FORCING WITH SEQUENCES OF MODELS OF TWO TYPES

FORCING AXIOMS AND THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS, PART II: TRANSCENDING ω 1 -SEQUENCES OF REAL NUMBERS

Stat 451: Solutions to Assignment #1

VARIATIONS FOR SEPARATING CLUB GUESSING PRINCIPLES

TEST GROUPS FOR WHITEHEAD GROUPS

Classifying classes of structures in model theory

20 Ordinals. Definition A set α is an ordinal iff: (i) α is transitive; and. (ii) α is linearly ordered by. Example 20.2.

Qualifying Exam Logic August 2005

A NOTE ON THE EIGHTFOLD WAY

CCC Forcing and Splitting Reals

Slow P -point Ultrafilters

A DIRECT PROOF OF THE FIVE ELEMENT BASIS THEOREM

PCF THEORY AND CARDINAL INVARIANTS OF THE REALS

PSEUDO P-POINTS AND SPLITTING NUMBER

EXTERNAL AUTOMORPHISMS OF ULTRAPRODUCTS OF FINITE MODELS

Exercises for Unit VI (Infinite constructions in set theory)

Forcing Axioms and Inner Models of Set Theory

The axiom of choice and two-point sets in the plane

MORE ABOUT SPACES WITH A SMALL DIAGONAL

NAMBA FORCING, WEAK APPROXIMATION, AND GUESSING

COMPLETE SETS OF CONNECTIVES FOR GENERALIZED ŁUKASIEWICZ LOGICS KAMERYN J WILLIAMS. CUNY Graduate Center 365 Fifth Avenue New York, NY USA

Silver trees and Cohen reals

Ultrafilters with property (s)

THE CANTOR GAME: WINNING STRATEGIES AND DETERMINACY. by arxiv: v1 [math.ca] 29 Jan 2017 MAGNUS D. LADUE

Annals of Pure and Applied Logic

Diagonalize This. Iian Smythe. Department of Mathematics Cornell University. Olivetti Club November 26, 2013

CH AND THE MOORE-MROWKA PROBLEM

ON A THEOREM OF BANACH AND KURATOWSKI AND K-LUSIN SETS. Tomek Bartoszyński

ITERATIONS WITH MIXED SUPPORT

BOOLEAN ALGEBRAS WITH FEW ENDOMORPHISMS SAHARON SHELAH

Souslin s Hypothesis

A NEW LINDELOF SPACE WITH POINTS G δ

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved.

Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras

Cardinal characteristics, projective wellorders and large continuum

TRANSFERING SATURATION, THE FINITE COVER PROPERTY, AND STABILITY

GREGORY TREES, THE CONTINUUM, AND MARTIN S AXIOM

many). But no other examples were known even Sacks forcing. Also for e.g. V = V = L, we did not know a forcing making it not proper.

FORCING (LECTURE NOTES FOR MATH 223S, SPRING 2011)

Diamond, Continuum, and Forcing

Well-Ordered Sets, Ordinals and Cardinals Ali Nesin 1 July 2001

A UNIVERSAL SEQUENCE OF CONTINUOUS FUNCTIONS

The topology of ultrafilters as subspaces of 2 ω

Axioms of separation

Generalized Pigeonhole Properties of Graphs and Oriented Graphs

DO FIVE OUT OF SIX ON EACH SET PROBLEM SET

October 12, Complexity and Absoluteness in L ω1,ω. John T. Baldwin. Measuring complexity. Complexity of. concepts. to first order.

SEPARATING CLUB GUESSING PRINCIPLES IN THE PRESENCE OF FAT FORCING AXIOMS

On minimal models of the Region Connection Calculus

COMPLETE NORMALITY AND COUNTABLE COMPACTNESS

CITS2211 Discrete Structures (2017) Cardinality and Countability

Section 2: Classes of Sets

1. Introduction Definition 1.1. For an L ω1,ω-sentence φ, the spectrum of φ is the set

The Vaught Conjecture Do uncountable models count?

Combinatorial dichotomies and cardinal invariants

INCREASING THE GROUPWISE DENSITY NUMBER BY C.C.C. FORCING HEIKE MILDENBERGER AND SAHARON SHELAH

An introduction to OCA

Uniquely Universal Sets

A sequential property of C p (X) and a covering property of Hurewicz.

Cardinal invariants of closed graphs

Sequences of height 1 primes in Z[X]

On The Model Of Hyperrational Numbers With Selective Ultrafilter

SOME USES OF SET THEORY IN ALGEBRA. Stanford Logic Seminar February 10, 2009

Maharam Algebras. Equipe de Logique, Université de Paris 7, 2 Place Jussieu, Paris, France

Ultrafilters and Set Theory. Andreas Blass University of Michigan Ann Arbor, MI

An Iterated Forcing Extension In Which All Aleph-1 Dense Sets of Reals Are Isomorphic

TOPOLOGY PROCEEDINGS Volume 28, No. 1, 2004 Pages

COUNTABLE COMPACTNESS, HEREDITARY π CHARACTER, AND THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS

On the Length of Borel Hierarchies

Introductory Analysis I Fall 2014 Homework #5 Solutions

More forcing notions imply diamond

UNIVERSALLY BAIRE SETS AND GENERIC ABSOLUTENESS TREVOR M. WILSON

arxiv:math/ v1 [math.lo] 5 Mar 2007

Löwenheim-Skolem Theorems, Countable Approximations, and L ω. David W. Kueker (Lecture Notes, Fall 2007)

Compact subsets of the Baire space

SOME CALKIN ALGEBRAS HAVE OUTER AUTOMORPHISMS

The onto mapping property of Sierpinski

Bounding by canonical functions, with CH

Forcing notions in inner models

DENSELY k-separable COMPACTA ARE DENSELY SEPARABLE

5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting

COMPACT C-CLOSED SPACES NEED NOT BE SEQUENTIAL

The Banach-Tarski paradox

INTRODUCTION TO CARDINAL NUMBERS

The Arkhangel skiĭ Tall problem under Martin s Axiom

Axioms for Set Theory

Principles of Real Analysis I Fall I. The Real Number System

BOUNDING, SPLITTING, AND ALMOST DISJOINTNESS

ITERATING ALONG A PRIKRY SEQUENCE

Successive cardinals with the tree property

Homogeneous Structures and Ramsey Classes

Filters and sets of Vitali type

3 COUNTABILITY AND CONNECTEDNESS AXIOMS

Template iterations with non-definable ccc forcing notions

Transcription:

arxiv:math/9807178v1 [math.lo] 15 Jul 1998 Lusin sequences under CH and under Martin s Axiom Uri Abraham Department of Mathematics and Computer Science, Ben-Gurion University, Beér-Sheva, Israel Saharon Shelah Institute of Mathematics The Hebrew University, Jerusalem, Israel February 1, 2008 Abstract Assuming the continuum hypothesis there is an inseparable sequence of length ω 1 that contains no Lusin subsequence, while if Martin s Axiom and CH is assumed then every inseparable sequence (of length ω 1 ) is a union of countably many Lusin subsequences. 1 Preface ω is the set of natural numbers. For A, B ω we write A B iff A \ B is finite, and A B iff A B is finite (almost inclusion, almost disjointness). Let A = A ζ ζ ω 1 be a sequence of pairwise almost disjoint subsets of ω 1. So A ζ ω and A ζ1 A ζ1 for ζ 1 ζ 2. We say that A is inseparable if there is no B ω for which ( ℵ 1 A A)(A B) & ( ℵ 1 A A)(A ω \ B). The work was carried in the meeting in Lyon in 1996. Publication # 537. 1

Thus A is inseparable iff the collection of B ω for which there is an unbounded set of ζ s with A ζ B forms a filter on ω. An inseparable family can be constructed in ZFC alone (Lusin [1], cited by [2]). We say that A is a Lusin sequence if for every i < ω 1 and n ω {j < i A i A j n} is finite. A seemingly stronger property is the following. We say that A is a Lusin* family if for every i < ω 1 and n ω {j < i : A i A j < n} is finite. It is not difficult to prove that every Lusin sequence is inseparable, and one can construct a Lusin sequence in ZFC. Is this the only way to build inseparable families? The answer depends on set-theoretical assumptions as the following two results show (obtained by the first and second author respectively). Theorem 1.1 (1) CH implies that there is an inseparable family which contains no Lusin subsequence. (2) Martin s Axiom+ CH implies that every inseparable sequence is a countable union of Lusin* sequences. 2 Proofs 2.1 CH gives an inseparable non-lusin sequence Assume the continuum hypothesis (CH) throughout this subsection. We shall define a sequence A = A α α ω 1 of almost disjoint subsets of ω which is inseparable by virtue of the following property. 2

For every infinite X ω one of the following three possibilities holds: (1) 1. X is finitely covered by A (which means that for some finite set u ω 1 X {A α α u}. 2. ω 1 \ X is finitely covered by A. 3. For some α 0 < ω 1 for all α 0 α < ω 1 X splits A α (which means that both X A α and A α \ X are infinite). It is quite obvious that if A satisfies this property (1) then it is inseparable, and so we describe the construction assuming CH of a sequence that satisfies this property, but does not contain any Lusin subsequence. Let X ξ ξ ω 1 be an enumeration of all infinite subsets of ω, and let e i i ω 1 be an enumeration of all countable subsets of ω 1 of order-type a limit ordinal. The sequence A = A α α ω 1 is defined by induction on α. Each A α is required to satisfy the following three properties. 1. A α ω is infinite and A β A α for all β < α. 2. For every ξ < α one of the following holds: (a) X ξ is finitely covered by A β β < α, or (b) ω \ X ξ is finitely covered by A β β < α, or else (c) X ξ splits A α (both X ξ A α and A α \ X ξ are infinite). 3. For every i < α such that e i α there are two possibilities: (a) For some m ω A α A ξ m+1 for an infinite number of indices ξ e i. (This is the good possibility.) (b) For some m A α there is ξ 0 < sup(e i ) such that for every ξ 0 < ξ e i min(a ξ \ m + 1) < min(a α \ m + 1). (2) (This possibility shows that α is not in the structure of which e i is an elementary submodel.) 3

If we succeed then A is inseparable (by 2) pairwise almost disjoint sequence (by 1) which contains no Lusin subsequence (by 3) as we show. Suppose that I ω 1 is uncountable, and L = A i i I is a subsequence of A. We want to find some α I and m ω for which {ξ I α A α A ξ m} is infinite. Consider the structure on I with predicates ω 1, and the binary relation m A i (for m ω, i I). Let e I be the universe of a countable elementary substructure. Then e = e i for some i ω 1. Let α I be any ordinal such that α > i and α > sup(e). We want to prove that possibility 3(a) holds for α. Suppose on the contrary that 3(b) holds. Then there are m A α and ξ 0 < sup(e) such that condition 3(b) holds. As e i is an elementary substructure, we actually have: for every ξ 0 < ξ I min(a ξ \ m + 1) < min(a α \ m + 1). But this is clearly impossible for ξ = α itself! So now we turn towards the construction with its three properties listed in 2. To construct A α it is convenient to define a poset P and a countable collection of dense subsets of P. Then we define a filter G P such that G intersects each of the dense sets in the countable collection. With this we define A α = {a E (a, E) G}, and A α should have all three properties because of the choice of the dense sets. In this fashion one does not have to overspecify the construction. A condition p = (a, E) P consists of: 1. A finite a ω (which will grow to become A α ). 2. A finite set E α (p promises that any extension a of a will add no new elements to a A β for β E). The partial order on P is defined accordingly by (a 1, E 1 ) (a 0, E 0 ) iff a 1 is an end-extension of a 1 such that for every k a 1 \a 0 and every ξ E 0, k A ξ We say that an end-extension a 1 of a 0 respects E (where E ω 1 is finite) if a 1 \ a 0 A β = for every β E. So (a 1, E 1 ) extends (a 0, E 0 ) iff a 1 is an end-extension of a 0 that respects E 0 and E 1 extends E 0 in any way. Now we shall define a countable collection of dense sets. First, to ensure that A α is infinite, for every k ω and p P observe that there is an extension (a, E ) with k < sup(a ). Then to ensure that A α A β for all β < α observe that (a, E {β}) extends p. This takes care of 1. 4

For every X ω such that neither X nor ω \X are covered by A β β < α, and for every k ω, define D X,k P by: (a, E) D X,k iff both a X and a \ X contain k members. Claim 2.1 D X,k is dense (open) in P. Proof. Suppose that (a 0, E 0 ) P. Since neither X nor its complement are -included in A = {A β β E 0 }, both X \A and (ω \X) \A are infinite. We can find an end-extension a 1 of a 0 such that (a 1 \ a 0 ) A = and both a 1 X and a 1 \X contain k members. Thus (a 0, E 0 ) < (a 1, E 0 ) D X,k. So add to the countable list of dense sets all sets D Xξ,k for k ω and ξ < α such that neither X ξ nor ω \ X ξ are finitely covered by A β β < α. This ensures 2. The main issue of the proof is to take care of 3. What dense sets will do the job? Fix e = e i for some i < α such that e α. We say that p = (a, E) P is of type (a) if for some m a the following holds. For every end-extension a of a that respects E (a \a is disjoint to {A β β E}) and for every ξ 0 e there is some ξ e, ξ 0 ξ, such that A ξ a m + 1. (3) If p is of type (a) then 1. the least m a that satisfies is denoted m p, 2. any extension of p is also of type (a) (with the same m). We say that p = (a, E) P is of type (b) if there are two successive members of a, m and n (so m, n a and (m, n) a = ). such that for some ξ 0 e for every ξ 0 ξ e A ξ (m, n). Claim 2.2 Any condition in P has an extension of type (a) or an extension of type (b). Proof. Given p = (a, E) let m = max(a). Is p of type (a) by virtue of m? If yes, we are done, and if not then there are 1. a an end-extension of a, respecting E, and 2. ξ 0 e, 5

such that for every ξ e with ξ 0 ξ A ξ a \ m + 1. Let n > maxa be such that n {A β β E} and consider the condition p = (a {n}, E) extending p. Then for every ξ 0 ξ e A ξ (m, n). That is, p is of type (b). For every ξ 0 e define D ξ0,e by p = (a, E) D ξ0,e iff either p is of type (b) or p is of type (a) and there exists some ξ e E above ξ 0 with A ξ a m + 1 (where m = m p ). D ξ0,e is dense by the following argument. Suppose p 0 P is given. If p 0 is extendible into a condition of type (b) then we are done. Assume that p 1 = (a 1, E 1 ) p 0 is of type (a). By definition of type (a), there is some ξ e, with ξ 0 ξ such that A ξ a 1 m + 1. Hence (a 1, E 1 {ξ}) D ξ0,e as required. Add to the countable list of dense sets all sets D ξ0,e where e = e i for some i < α such that e i α and ξ 0 e i. This ensures property 3 (of 2). Suppose that A α is defined from the filter G that intersects all the above dense sets. Given i such that e i = e α, we ask: is there (a, E) G of type (b) for e? If yes, then possibility 3(b) holds for A α. If no, then there is an m and an unbounded set of ξ e such that A ξ A α m+1. To see this, observe that m p = m is fixed for all p G of type (a). Now consider any ξ 0 e, and pick p = (a, E) D ξ0,e G. Then p is of type (a) and there is ξ E e i above ξ 0 with A ξ a m + 1. Thus A ξ A α m + 1 follows. 2.2 Martin s Axiom: Inseparable contains a Lusin* subsequence Assume Martin s Axiom +2 ℵ 0 > ℵ 0. Let A = A ζ ζ ω 1 be an inseparable sequence of length ω 1 (any length below the continuum works). Define the following poset: ordered by Q = {(u, n) u ω 1 is finite and n < ω} (u 1, n 1 ) (u 2, n 2 ) iff u 1 u 2 & n 1 n 2 & i u 1 j u 2 \u 1 j < i A i A j > n 1. (4) This is easily shown to be transitive. We intend to prove that Q is a c.c.c poset and that for every α < ω 1 and k < ω the set D α,k of (u, n) in Q for which sup(u) > α and n > k is dense. So if G Q is a filter provided by Martin s 6

Axiom which intersects each of these dense sets, then U = {u n(u, n) G} is uncountable and A α α U is a Lusin* sequence. (Because if i U and k < ω then the collection of A j for j U i such that A i A j k is finite by the following argument. For some (u, n) G i u and n k. This implies that A i A j > k for every j < i such that j U \ u.) The full result, concerning the decomposition of A into countably many Lusin* subsequences, follows from the fact that (under Martin s Axiom) if Q is a c.c.c poset, then Q is a countable union of filters (each intersects the required dense sets). (Consider the poset Q <ω consisting of finite sequences from Q, ordered coordinate-wise.) It is easy to see that if (u, n) Q and v is any end-extension of u then (u, n) (v, n). Also, if n m then (u, n) (u, m). This shows that the required sets D α,k are indeed dense in Q, and so the main point of the proof is to show that Q satisfies the c.c. condition. Lemma 2.3 Q satisfies the c.c. condition. Proof. Let (u ζ, n ζ ) ζ ω 1 be an ω 1 -sequence of conditions in Q. We may assume that for some fixed n and k n = n ζ and k = u ζ for all ζ ω 1, and that the sets u ζ s form a system. That is, for some finite c 0 ω 1 c 0 = u ζ1 u ζ2 for all ζ 1 ζ 2 and max(u ζ1 ) < min(u ζ2 \ c 0 ) for ζ 1 < ζ 2. We want to find ζ 1 < ζ 2 such that (u ζ1 u ζ2, n) extends both (u ζ1, n) and (u ζ2, n). It is evident that (u ζ1 u ζ2, n) extends (u ζ1, n) (the lower part) but the problem is the possibility that for some i u ζ2 and j u ζ1 \ c 0 A i A j n. We shall find two uncountable sets K, L ω 1 such that for every ζ 1 K and ζ 2 L (u ζ1, n) and (u ζ2, n) are compatible. We start with K 0 = L 0 = ω 1, and define K i+1 K i and L i+1 L i by induction for i < u ζ \ c 0 (any ζ as these sets have all the same size). The definition of K i and L i depends on a finite parameter set, and it is convenient to have a countable model in which the definition is carried on. So let M H ω1, A, Q, {(u ζ, n ζ ) : ζ ω 1 } be a countable elementary submodel. The following lemma is used. Lemma 2.4 Let U, V M be two uncountable subsets of ω 1 and n < ω. There are uncountable subsets U 1 U and V 1 V (definable in M) such that for every ζ U 1 and ξ V 1 A ζ A ξ > n (and hence ({ζ}, n) and ({ξ}, n) are compatible in Q). 7

It should be obvious how successive applications of the lemma yield the c.c.c., and so we turn to the proof of the lemma. Let δ = ω 1 M be the set of countable ordinals in our countable structure M. Case 1: for some ζ U \ δ and ξ V \ δ A ζ A ξ > n. In this case pick X A ζ A ξ with X > n, and let U 1 = {i U X A i }, V 1 = {j V X A j }. Both U 1 and V 1 are uncountable (for if U 1 is countable then it would be included in M, but A ζ shows that this is not the case). Case 2: not Case 1. So for every ζ U \δ and ξ V \δ A ζ A ξ n. Let 0 m 0 n be the maximal size of some intersection F = A ζ A ξ for indices ζ and ξ as above. Then U 1 = {i U F A i } and V 1 = {j V X A j } are uncountable and for i U 1 and j V 1 A i A j = F (by maximality of F ). So the sets A ζ \ F and A ξ for ζ U \ δ and ξ V \ δ are pairwise disjoint, which gives a contradictory separation of A. 3 References References [1] N. Lusin, Sur les parties de la suite des nombres entiers, Comptes Rendus (Doklady) de l Academie des Sciences de l URSS 40 (1943), 175 178. [2] M. Scheepers, Gaps in ω ω, Israel Mathematical Conference Proceedings, Vol. 6, (1993), 439 561. 8