Basic set-theoretic techniques in logic Part II, Counting beyond infinity: Ordinal numbers

Similar documents
Basic set-theoretic techniques in logic Part III, Transfinite recursion and induction

MATH 3300 Test 1. Name: Student Id:

Discrete Mathematics for CS Spring 2007 Luca Trevisan Lecture 27

CITS2211 Discrete Structures (2017) Cardinality and Countability

20 Ordinals. Definition A set α is an ordinal iff: (i) α is transitive; and. (ii) α is linearly ordered by. Example 20.2.

Math 3361-Modern Algebra Lecture 08 9/26/ Cardinality

ADVANCED CALCULUS - MTH433 LECTURE 4 - FINITE AND INFINITE SETS

Cardinality and ordinal numbers

A non-turing-recognizable language

Ordinals and Cardinals: Basic set-theoretic techniques in logic

Math 105A HW 1 Solutions

Discrete Mathematics and Probability Theory Spring 2014 Anant Sahai Note 20. To Infinity And Beyond: Countability and Computability

Countability. 1 Motivation. 2 Counting

One-to-one functions and onto functions

Notes on ordinals and cardinals

Math 455 Some notes on Cardinality and Transfinite Induction

INTRODUCTION TO CARDINAL NUMBERS

Cantor s Letter to Dedekind

Part II Logic and Set Theory

Well-Ordered Sets, Ordinals and Cardinals Ali Nesin 1 July 2001

Mathematics 220 Workshop Cardinality. Some harder problems on cardinality.

SETS AND FUNCTIONS JOSHUA BALLEW

1.4 Cardinality. Tom Lewis. Fall Term Tom Lewis () 1.4 Cardinality Fall Term / 9

Section 7.5: Cardinality

Some. AWESOME Great Theoretical Ideas in Computer Science about Generating Functions Probability

Unsolvable problems, the Continuum Hypothesis, and the nature of infinity

Preference and Utility

ABOUT THE CLASS AND NOTES ON SET THEORY

Set Theory and the Foundation of Mathematics. June 19, 2018

Great Theoretical Ideas in Computer Science. Lecture 5: Cantor s Legacy

NOTES FOR 197, SPRING 2018

Ordinals. Mustafa Elsheikh elsheimm at mcmaster dot ca. Wed 18 Nov 2008

Math 4603: Advanced Calculus I, Summer 2016 University of Minnesota Notes on Cardinality of Sets

DO FIVE OUT OF SIX ON EACH SET PROBLEM SET

On Transfinite Cardinal Numbers

Section 2: Classes of Sets

MATH 220 (all sections) Homework #12 not to be turned in posted Friday, November 24, 2017

Date: October 24, 2008, Friday Time: 10:40-12:30. Math 123 Abstract Mathematics I Midterm Exam I Solutions TOTAL

Part II. Logic and Set Theory. Year

Trees and generic absoluteness

S15 MA 274: Exam 3 Study Questions

Handout 2 (Correction of Handout 1 plus continued discussion/hw) Comments and Homework in Chapter 1

Extended Essay - Mathematics

Sets, Models and Proofs. I. Moerdijk and J. van Oosten Department of Mathematics Utrecht University


The Axiom of Choice. Contents. 1 Motivation 2. 2 The Axiom of Choice 2. 3 Two powerful equivalents of AC 4. 4 Zorn s Lemma 5. 5 Using Zorn s Lemma 6

CSCI3390-Lecture 6: An Undecidable Problem

0 Logical Background. 0.1 Sets

Algorithms: Lecture 2

CSE 20 DISCRETE MATH. Fall

Discrete Mathematics 2007: Lecture 5 Infinite sets

Diagonalize This. Iian Smythe. Department of Mathematics Cornell University. Olivetti Club November 26, 2013

The cardinal comparison of sets

Today. Wrapup of Polynomials...and modular arithmetic. Coutability and Uncountability.

Zermelo-Fraenkel Set Theory

6. The transfinite ordinals*

Math 300: Final Exam Practice Solutions

the time it takes until a radioactive substance undergoes a decay

Chapter 20. Countability The rationals and the reals. This chapter covers infinite sets and countability.

5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting

POL502: Foundations. Kosuke Imai Department of Politics, Princeton University. October 10, 2005

X = { X f X i A i : (œx, y 0 X)[x /= y œi[ x i /= y i ]]}.

Initial Ordinals. Proposition 57 For every ordinal α there is an initial ordinal κ such that κ α and α κ.

Notes on counting. James Aspnes. December 13, 2010

Axioms of separation

ECS 120 Lesson 18 Decidable Problems, the Halting Problem

Exercises for Unit VI (Infinite constructions in set theory)

ALMOST DISJOINT AND INDEPENDENT FAMILIES. 1. introduction. is infinite. Fichtenholz and Kantorovich showed that there is an independent family

SELF-DUAL UNIFORM MATROIDS ON INFINITE SETS

Philosophy of Religion. Notes on Infinity

Discrete Structures for Computer Science

Introduction to Model Theory

The Different Sizes of Infinity

Chapter 1 : The language of mathematics.

This section will take the very naive point of view that a set is a collection of objects, the collection being regarded as a single object.

Reed-Solomon code. P(n + 2k)

Some Function Problems SOLUTIONS Isabel Vogt Last Edited: May 24, 2013

(D) Introduction to order types and ordinals

A NEW SET THEORY FOR ANALYSIS

Selected problems from past exams

Sets and Infinity. James Emery. Edited: 2/25/ Cardinal Numbers 1. 2 Ordinal Numbers 6. 3 The Peano Postulates for the Natural Numbers 7

Every Linear Order Isomorphic to Its Cube is Isomorphic to Its Square

Chapter One. The Real Number System

1 Partitions and Equivalence Relations

6c Lecture 14: May 14, 2014

Section Summary. Sequences. Recurrence Relations. Summations. Examples: Geometric Progression, Arithmetic Progression. Example: Fibonacci Sequence

Lecture 1. Econ 2001: Introduction to Mathematical Methods (a.k.a. Math Camp) 2015 August 10

We are going to discuss what it means for a sequence to converge in three stages: First, we define what it means for a sequence to converge to zero

More Model Theory Notes

REU 2007 Transfinite Combinatorics Lecture 9

Equations and Infinite Colorings Exposition by Stephen Fenner and William Gasarch

Introduction to the Theory of Computing

6 CARDINALITY OF SETS

ITERATIONS WITH MIXED SUPPORT

Part IA Numbers and Sets

A Readable Introduction to Real Mathematics

Math 144 Summer 2012 (UCR) Pro-Notes June 24, / 15

Description of the book Set Theory

Statistical Inference

2.2 Lowenheim-Skolem-Tarski theorems

Transcription:

Basic set-theoretic techniques in logic Part II, Counting beyond infinity: Ordinal numbers Benedikt Löwe Universiteit van Amsterdam Grzegorz Plebanek Uniwersytet Wroc lawski ESSLLI, Ljubliana August 2011

Summary of the first lecture: We have discussed how to measure the infinity, in particular measuring the size of the set o natural numbers:

Now for something slightly different. Have you ever counted up to 1000? 1, 2, 3,..., 1000. It takes more than 16 minutes but surely we can do it. We can also imagine ourselves counting up to 10 1010 though it will be really time-consuming. Can we count beyond infinity? If so we need a new name:

Having ω (sometimes denoted ω 0 ) at hand we can continue: 0, 1, 2,..., 2011,..., ω, ω + 1, ω + 2,..., ω + ω,... Is there any use of this?

Pros and Cons of Hitch Hiking a a after Roger Waters, ex Pink Floyd Suppose you are hitchhiking from A to B. Pros: should be for free. Cons: the route may be complicated, starting from A B (0 stops), to A S 1 B (1 stop), A S 1 S 2 B (2 stops), and so on.

Pros and Cons of Hitch Hiking, continued Suppose that on our way we may be offered a lift by little dwarfs in their little cars, moving us only a tiny little bit forward: A S 1 S 2... S n... B. Then we may call such a route ω. Can you imagine hitchhiking in the ω + 1 or ω + ω style?

All the hitchhiker s routes Denote the collection of all possible routes by ω 1 ; ω 1 = {0, 1, 2,..., ω, ω + 1, ω + 2..., ω + ω, ω + ω + 1,...}. Note that 1 + ω is the same as ω but ω + 1 is different. With every route α we can think of α + 1, so there is no largest element of ω 1. Every route α has finitely or countably many stops. If α is a route and X is any nonempty set of stops appearing in α then X has the first stop. If α 1, α 2,... is any sequence of routes then there is a route α which is more complicated than all α n s. The set ω 1 of all routes is uncountable.

Now a serious stuff! Definition We say that a set X is linearly ordered by < if for any x, y, z X x x; Example x < y and y < z imply x < z; if x y then x < y or y < x. The set R of reals is linearly ordered by the natural order. All words are linearly ordered by the lexicographic order.

Definition A set X is well-ordered by < if it is linearly ordered and Example every nonempty subset A of X has a least element. The set N is well-ordered. Hmmmm, should be obvious... The interval [0, 1] has the least element (= 0) but is not well-ordered because its subset A = {1, 1/2, 1/3,... } does not contain a least element. Definition Two well-ordered sets (X, <) and (Y, <) are isomorphic if there is a bijection f : X Y such that x 1 < x 2 is equivalent to f (x 1 ) < f (x 2 ); for any x 1, x 2 X.

Theorem 1 If (X, <) is well-ordered and f : X X is an increasing function then f (x) x for every x X. 2 If (X, <) is well-ordered and f : X X is an isomorphism then f is the identity function. Proof. Suppose that f (x) x does not hold for all x; it means that the set A = {x X : f (x) < x} is nonempty. Take its minimal element x 0. Then y 0 = f (x 0 ) < x 0 (since x 0 A), and f (y 0 ) < f (x 0 ) = y 0 (since f is increasing). It follows that y 0 A, a contradiction with y 0 < x 0. By the first part we have f (x) x for any x. We can also apply the first part to the inverse function f 1 : X X : f 1 (x) x so x = f (f 1 (x)) f (x). Hence f (x) = x for all x.

If X is well-ordered and a X then the set {x X : x < a} is called the initial segment of X given by a. Theorem Let (X, <) and (Y, <) be two well-ordered sets. Then either 1 X and Y are isomorphic, or 2 X is isomorphic to some initial segment of Y, or 3 Y is isomorphic to some initial segment of X. Definition An ordinal number is the order type of some well-ordered set. If α is the order type of X and β is the order type of Y then 1 α = β, 2 α < β, 3 β < α, in the corresponding cases.

Example 0 is the order type of the empty set; 1 is the order type of a set consisting of one element; ω = ω 0 is the order type of {0, 1, 2,...}; We may as well think that ω is the set {0, 1, 2,...}. Definition ω 1 is the least order type of a well-ordered uncountable set. We have α < ω 1 whenever α is an order type of a countable set. We may think that ω 1 = {0, 1, 2,..., ω, ω + 1,..., α,...} is the set of all order types of countable sets.

Ordinal and cardinal numbers An ordinal number α is a cardinal number if for every β < α we have β < α. 0, 1, 2,... are cardinal numbers. ω is a cardinal number (denoted ℵ 0 ). ω + 1, ω + ω are not cardinal numbers. ω 1 is the next cardinal number denoted as ℵ 1. ω 2 is the least order type of a set of cardinality > ℵ 1 ; ℵ 2 = ω 2. We can define ℵ 0 < ℵ 1 < ℵ 2 <.... Then ℵ ω comes. And so on... Do you understand? a a In mathematics, you don t understand things. You just get used to them. (John von Neumann)

Handling the continuum We have an exact list of cardinal numbers ℵ 0 < ℵ 1 < ℵ 2 <.... Before we defined another list ℵ 0 < 2 ℵ 0 < 2 2ℵ 0 <.... We also considered c the cardinality of R. Let us prove that c = 2 ℵ 0.

2 ℵ 0 = c. Note that 2 ℵ 0 (by the definition the cardinality of P(N)) is the cardinality of the set {0, 1} N of all infinite sequences of of 0 s and 1 s. The function f : {0, 1} N R, where f (x 1, x 2,...) = n=1 2x n 3 n, is one-to-one. It follows that 2 ℵ 0 c. Every x [0, 1] has a unique infinite binary expansion x = (0, x 1 x 2...) (2). This shows that [0, 1] admits one-to-one function into {0, 1} N, and c = [0, 1] 2 ℵ 0. Finally c = 2 ℵ 0 by the Cantor-Bernstein theorem.