GS/ECON 5010 section B Answers to Assignment 1 September Q1. Are the preferences described below transitive? Strictly monotonic? Convex?

Similar documents
Applications I: consumer theory

Week 7: The Consumer (Malinvaud, Chapter 2 and 4) / Consumer November Theory 1, 2015 (Jehle and 1 / Reny, 32

Structural Properties of Utility Functions Walrasian Demand

Problem set 2 solutions Prof. Justin Marion Econ 100M Winter 2012

Using Economic Contexts to Advance in Mathematics

The Fundamental Welfare Theorems

Midterm Exam, Econ 210A, Fall 2008

Microeconomics. Joana Pais. Fall Joana Pais

Notes on Consumer Theory

Week 9: Topics in Consumer Theory (Jehle and Reny, Chapter 2)

x 1 1 and p 1 1 Two points if you just talk about monotonicity (u (c) > 0).

Final Examination with Answers: Economics 210A

Consumer theory Topics in consumer theory. Microeconomics. Joana Pais. Fall Joana Pais

Econ 121b: Intermediate Microeconomics

Economics 401 Sample questions 2

Lecture 1. History of general equilibrium theory

September Math Course: First Order Derivative

Economics 121b: Intermediate Microeconomics Midterm Suggested Solutions 2/8/ (a) The equation of the indifference curve is given by,

ECON 4117/5111 Mathematical Economics Fall 2005

Utility Maximization Problem

Adv. Micro Theory, ECON

Advanced Microeconomic Analysis Solutions to Homework #2

Last Revised: :19: (Fri, 12 Jan 2007)(Revision:

Answers to Econ 210A Midterm, October A. The function f is homogeneous of degree 1/2. To see this, note that for all t > 0 and all (x 1, x 2 )

Midterm Examination: Economics 210A October 2011

Midterm #1 EconS 527 Wednesday, February 21st, 2018

Microeconomic Theory -1- Introduction

Econ 5150: Applied Econometrics Empirical Demand Analysis. Sung Y. Park CUHK

Demand Theory. Lecture IX and X Utility Maximization (Varian Ch. 7) Federico Trionfetti

Revealed Preferences and Utility Functions

Microeconomic Theory I Midterm October 2017

CHAPTER 4: HIGHER ORDER DERIVATIVES. Likewise, we may define the higher order derivatives. f(x, y, z) = xy 2 + e zx. y = 2xy.

Week 6: Consumer Theory Part 1 (Jehle and Reny, Chapter 1)

Maximum Value Functions and the Envelope Theorem

Lecture 3 - Axioms of Consumer Preference and the Theory of Choice

Advanced Microeconomic Analysis Solutions to Midterm Exam

Problem Set 5: Expenditure Minimization, Duality, and Welfare 1. Suppose you were given the following expenditure function: β (α

Hicksian Demand and Expenditure Function Duality, Slutsky Equation

Proportional Response as Iterated Cobb-Douglas

Rice University. Answer Key to Mid-Semester Examination Fall ECON 501: Advanced Microeconomic Theory. Part A

Utility Maximization Problem. Advanced Microeconomic Theory 2

Microeconomic Theory-I Washington State University Midterm Exam #1 - Answer key. Fall 2016

GARP and Afriat s Theorem Production

Public Goods and Private Goods

Monotone comparative statics Finite Data and GARP

PhD Qualifier Examination

EE290O / IEOR 290 Lecture 05

Microeconomics, Block I Part 1

Preferences and Utility

Microeconomics II Lecture 4. Marshallian and Hicksian demands for goods with an endowment (Labour supply)

Introduction to General Equilibrium: Framework.

Intro to Economic analysis

Mathematical Appendix

Beyond CES: Three Alternative Classes of Flexible Homothetic Demand Systems

Partial Solutions to Homework 2

Preferences and Utility

Advanced Microeconomic Theory. Chapter 2: Demand Theory

Beyond CES: Three Alternative Classes of Flexible Homothetic Demand Systems

1 + x 1/2. b) For what values of k is g a quasi-concave function? For what values of k is g a concave function? Explain your answers.

1. Suppose preferences are represented by the Cobb-Douglas utility function, u(x1,x2) = Ax 1 a x 2

Chapter 1 Consumer Theory Part II

The Consumer, the Firm, and an Economy

Consumer Theory. Ichiro Obara. October 8, 2012 UCLA. Obara (UCLA) Consumer Theory October 8, / 51

Market Equilibrium and the Core

Recitation #2 (August 31st, 2018)

Lecture Notes for Chapter 12

Duality. for The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics, 2nd ed. Lawrence E. Blume

Competitive Consumer Demand 1

Lakehead University ECON 4117/5111 Mathematical Economics Fall 2003

where u is the decision-maker s payoff function over her actions and S is the set of her feasible actions.

z = f (x; y) f (x ; y ) f (x; y) f (x; y )

1 Objective. 2 Constrained optimization. 2.1 Utility maximization. Dieter Balkenborg Department of Economics

The Ohio State University Department of Economics. Homework Set Questions and Answers

Properties of Walrasian Demand

Index. Cambridge University Press An Introduction to Mathematics for Economics Akihito Asano. Index.

Market Equilibrium Price: Existence, Properties and Consequences

Solutions to selected exercises from Jehle and Reny (2001): Advanced Microeconomic Theory

Chapter 8: Slutsky Decomposition

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program May 2012

Notes I Classical Demand Theory: Review of Important Concepts

Direct Complementarity

Microeconomic Theory: Lecture 2 Choice Theory and Consumer Demand

Econ Spring Review Set 1 - Answers ELEMENTS OF LOGIC. NECESSARY AND SUFFICIENT. SET THE-

The B.E. Journal of Theoretical Economics

Constrained optimization.

The New Palgrave: Separability

Advanced Microeconomics

Recitation 2-09/01/2017 (Solution)

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2016

I. An Introduction to Mathematical Economics.

3/1/2016. Intermediate Microeconomics W3211. Lecture 3: Preferences and Choice. Today s Aims. The Story So Far. A Short Diversion: Proofs

Advanced Microeconomic Analysis, Lecture 6

CONSUMER DEMAND. Consumer Demand

Functions. Paul Schrimpf. October 9, UBC Economics 526. Functions. Paul Schrimpf. Definition and examples. Special types of functions

ECON 5111 Mathematical Economics

f( x) f( y). Functions which are not one-to-one are often called many-to-one. Take the domain and the range to both be all the real numbers:

Universidad Carlos III de Madrid June Microeconomics Grade

Sometimes the domains X and Z will be the same, so this might be written:

Econ 101A Midterm 1 Th 29 September 2004.

In economics, the amount of a good x demanded is a function of the price of that good. In other words,

Transcription:

GS/ECON 5010 section B Answers to Assignment 1 September 2011 Q1. Are the preferences described below transitive? Strictly monotonic? Convex? Explain briefly. The person consumes 2 goods, food and clothing. A bundle A will be ranked as at least as good as bundle B if either of the following conditions holds : (i) bundle A contains at least twice as much food as bundle B ; (ii) bundle A contains at least half as much food as bundle B, and the amount of food in A added to the amount of clothing in A, is at least as large as the amount of food in B added to the amount of clothing in B. If neither (i) (ii) is true, then bundle A is not considered at least as good as bundle B. A1 First of all, the preferences are not transitive. To show this, what we need is a single example in which A B, and B C, but in which it is not true that A C. Suppose that A = (3, 8), B = (5, 5) and C = (7, 2), where the first number in each pair is the quantity of food in the bundle, and the second number is the quantity of clothing. Comparing A and B, part (ii) of the definition applies, so that A is at least as good as B. Comparing B and C, part (ii) of the definition applies again, so that B is at least as good as C. But the amount of food in C is me than twice as much as the amount of food in A. So A is not ranked as at least as good as C, which means the preferences are not transitive. The preferences here are strictly monotonic. Suppose that bundle A contains strictly me food than bundle B, and strictly me clothing. Then the definition above says that A must be ranked as at least as good as B. But neither (i) n (ii) holds when we compare B to A : B doesn t have twice as much food as A, and B does not have as much food plus clothing as A. So B is not at least as good as A. Saying A is at least as good as B, and B is not at least as good as A is exactly the same thing as saying A is strictly preferred to B. So if one bundle has strictly me of both goods, then it must be strictly preferred. (And if bundle A has at least as much of each good as B, then it must be at least as good as B, from part (ii) of the definition above.) The preferences are not convex. Again, to show this, a single counter example is sufficient. Suppose that A = (3, 12), B = (8, 0), and C = (2, 16). Part (i) of the definition says that B is at least as good as A. Part (ii) of the definition says that C is at least as good as A. Now let D be a convex combination of B and C, the bundle that is halfway between B and C. Then D = (5, 8). Bundle D does not contain at lest twice as much food as bundle A ; the amount of food in D, added to the amount of clothing in D, is less than the amount of food in A, added to the amount of clothing in A. So bundle D is not at least as good as A, even though it is a convex combination of bundles B and C. This example shows that preferences here are not convex, since B A, C A, but it is not true that D A, even though D is a convex combination of B and C.

Figure 1 (Figure 1 shows the set of bundles which are at least as good as (3, 12) : they are all the bundles on, to the right of, the red line in the figure. This is not a convex set.)

Q2. Are the preferences represented by the utility function below strictly monotonic? Convex? Explain briefly. U(x 1, x 2, x 3 ) = max (x 1 + x 2 + x 3, 3x 1 ) A2. These preferences are not convex. To show preferences are not convex ( not monotonic, not transitive), it is sufficient to provide a single counter example. So let A = (3, 3, 3), B = (4, 0, 0), C = (0, 6, 6). The utility levels f the 3 bundles are U(A) = 9, U(B) = 12, U(C) = 12. So both B and C are at least as good as A, since they each yield higher utility. Now take a convex combination of B and C : D 0.5B + 0.5C = (2, 3, 3). Since U(D) = max (8, 6) = 8, therefe U(D) < U(A). The bundle D is on a lower indifference surface than bundle A, even though D is a convex combination of two bundles (B and C) which are each on higher indifference surfaces than A. Q3. Calculate a person s Marshallian demand functions, if her preferences can be represented by the utility function u(x 1, x 2 ) = min (x 1 + x 2, 2x 2 ) A3. Calculus is not that much help here, since the indifference curves f this utility function are kinked (as in the diagram) : if x 1 > x 2, then u(x 1, x 2 ) = 2x 2 and the slope of the indifference curve is 0 ; if x 1 < x 2, then u(x 1, x 2 ) = x 1 + x 2 and the slope of the indifference curve is 1. So, unless = p 2, the solution to the consumer s maximization is at a kink a cner. If > p 2, then the slope of the budget line is greater than the slope of the indifference curve, so that the consumer is at a cner : she maximizes her utility by spending all her money on good 2. If < p 2, then the slope of the budget line is between the slopes of the two segments of the indifference curves. The consumer chooses the kink, at which x 1 = x 2. If = p 2, then the consumer is indifferent among all points on the budget line f which x 2 x 1 : she does not have a unique Marshallian demand, because her preferences are not strictly convex. So her Marshallian demands are : (i) if > p 2, then x M 1 (, p 2, y) = 0 and x M 2 (, p 2, y) = y/p 2. (ii) if = p 2, then x M 1 (, p 2, y) is any x 1 less than equal to y/2, and x M 2 (, p 2, y) = y x M 1 (, p 2, y). (iii) if < p 2, then x M 1 (, p 2, y) = y +p 2 = x M 2 (, p 2, y).

Figure 3 (Figure 3 : Indifference Curves f Question # 3)

Q4. Calculate a person s Marshallian demand functions, if her preferences can be represented by the utility function u(x 1, x 2, x 3 ) = x 1 1 x 2 4 (x 3 ) 2 A4. These are quasi linear preferences, since the utility function is of the fm u(x 1, x 2, x 3 ) = ax 1 + f(x 2, x 3 ) (where here a = 1 and f(x 2, x 3 ) = 1 x 2 4 (x 3 ) 2 ). With quasi linear preferences, the Marshallian demands f goods 2 and 3 will be independent of income. To solve f the person s Marshallian demands, take the first der conditions from the person s utility maximization, u i (x 1, x 2, x 3 ) = λp i, f i = 1, 2, 3. Here, those conditions are u 1 (x 1, x 2, x 3 ) = 1 = λ (4 1) u 2 (x 1, x 2, x 3 ) = 1 (x 2 ) 2 = λp 2 (4 2) u 3 (x 1, x 2, x 3 ) = 8 (x 3 ) 3 = λp 3 (4 3) Equation (4 1) implies that λ = 1, so that equation (4 2) can be written 1 (x 2 ) 2 = p 2 (4 4) x 2 = p1 p 2 (4 5) Equation (4 5) is the Marshallian demand function f good #2, since it expresses quantity demanded of good #2 as a function of prices and income. Substituting f λ into equation (4 3) yields 8 (x 3 ) 3 = p 3 (4 6) x 3 = 2( p 3 ) 1/3 (4 7) which is the Marshallian demand function f good #3. To get the Marshallian demand function f good #1, the budget constraint must be used. Since x 1 + p 2 x 2 + p 3 x 3 = y, therefe, From equations (4 5) and (4 7) x 1 = y p 2x 2 p 3 x 3 x M 1 (, p 2, p 3, y) = y p2 2( p 3 ) 2/3 (4 8)

Equations (4 5), (4 7) and (4 8) define the Marshallian demands only if all three expressions have non negative values. If is so high that expression (4 8) is negative, then the person is at a cner solution. She chooses to consume none of good 1, and chooses x 2 and x 3 so as to maximize 1 x 1 2 (x 3 ) 2 subject to the constraint that p 2 x 2 + p 3 x 3 y. The first der conditions f this maximization imply that p 2 x 2 + 2(p 2 p 3 ) 2/3 x 2/3 2 = y (4 9) which implicitly defines the Marshallian demand function f good 2, when good 1 is so expensive that the person chooses not to consume any of good 1. But I don t think that equation (4 9) can be solved explicitly f x 2. Q5. Calculate the Marshallian and Hicksian demand functions, the indirect utility function, and the expenditure function f a consumer whose preferences can be represented by the utility function u(x 1, x 2 ) = ln x 1 + ln x 2 ln (x 1 + x 2 ) A5. The first der conditions from the consumer s utility maximization problem are 1 1 = λ (5 1) x 1 x 1 + x 2 1 1 = λp 2 (5 2) x 2 x 1 + x 2 which can be re arranged to x 2 x 1 (x 1 + x 2 ) = λ (5 3) x 1 x 2 (x 1 + x 2 ) = λp 2 (5 4) Setting the left side of (5 3) divided by the left side of (5 4) equal to the right side of (5 3) divided by the right side of (5 4), ( x 2 x 1 ) 2 = p 2 (5 5) x 2 = ( p 2 )x 1 (5 6) Substituting f x 2 from (5 6) into the budget constraint x 1 + p 2 x 2 = y yields x 1 ( + ( p 2 )) = y (5 7) x 1 = y p1 ( + p 2 ) (5 8)

which is the Marshallian demand function f good #1. Substituting from (5 8) into (5 6) yields the Marshallian demand function f good #2, x M 2 (, p 2, y) = y p2 ( + p 2 ) (5 9) level, are The first der conditions f the dual problem, minimizing the cost of a given utility µ x 1 µ = (5 9) x 1 + x 2 µ µ = p 2 (5 10) x 2 x 1 + x 2 These two equations again imply equation (5 6) above. Substituting f x 2 from (5 6) into the given utility constraint implies that ln x 1 + ln x 2 ln (x 1 + x 2 ) = ū ln x 1 + ln ln p 2 + ln x 1 ln ( + p 2 ) ln x 1 + ln p 2 = ū (5 11) x 1 = eū p1 + p 2 p2 (5 12) which is the Hicksian demand function f good 1. Substituting from (5 12) into (5 6) yields the Hicksian demand function f good #2, x H 2 (, p 2, ū) = eū p1 + p 2 p1 (5 13) The expenditure function is defined as cost of the Hicksian demands, x H 1 (, p 2, ū) + p 2 x H 2 (, p 2, ū). From equations (5 12) and (5 13), then e(, p 2, ū) = eū[ + p 2 ] 2 (5 14) The indirect utility can be calculated as v(, p 2, y) = ln x M 1 (, p 2, y) + ln x M 2 (, p 2, y) ln [x 1 M (, p 2, y) + x M 2 (, p 2, y)] which (from equations (5 7) and (5 8)) equals v(, p 2, y) = ln y 2 ln [ + p 2 ] (5 15) Equations (5 14) and (5 15) confirm that here e(, p 2, v(, p 2, y)) = y, and v(, p 2, e(, p 2, u)) = u. As well, equations (5 12), (5 13) and (5 14) show that Shepherd s lemma holds : e/ p i = x H i (, p 2, u) f i = 1, 2.

[These preferences are actually examples of CES preferences. Suppose that ρ = 1, in the textbook fmulation of CES preferences. Then U(x 1, x 2 ) = [x 1 1 + x 1 2 ] 1 The expression in the square brackets is x1 1 + x 1 2 = 1/x 1 + 1/x 2 = x 1+x 2 x 1 x 2. Taking this to the power 1 means inverting it, so that f CES preferences when ρ = 1. U(x 1, x 2 ) = x 1x 2 x 1 + x 2 And the direct utility function u(x 1, x 2 ) = ln x 1 + ln x 2 ln (x 1 + x 2 ) is the natural logarithm of this CES utility function U(x 1, x 2 ).]