Cooperative bargaining: independence and monotonicity imply disagreement

Similar documents
Randomized dictatorship and the Kalai-Smorodinsky bargaining solution

Bridging the gap between the Nash and Kalai-Smorodinsky bargaining solutions

A generalization of the Egalitarian and the Kalai Smorodinsky bargaining solutions

Stagnation proofness and individually monotonic bargaining solutions. Jaume García-Segarra Miguel Ginés-Vilar 2013 / 04

Game Theory. Bargaining Theory. ordi Massó. International Doctorate in Economic Analysis (IDEA) Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona (UAB)

1 Axiomatic Bargaining Theory

Nash Bargaining in Ordinal Environments

A Characterization of the Nash Bargaining Solution Published in Social Choice and Welfare, 19, , (2002)

Rationality and solutions to nonconvex bargaining problems: rationalizability and Nash solutions 1

ECONOMICS SERIES SWP 2009/16. Weakest Collective Rationality and the Nash Bargaining Solution. Nejat Anbarci and Ching-jen Sun

TWO-PERSON COOPERATIVE GAMES

Bargaining Efficiency and the Repeated Prisoners Dilemma. Bhaskar Chakravorti* and John Conley**

The Interdisciplinary Center, Herzliya School of Economics Advanced Microeconomics Fall Bargaining The Axiomatic Approach

The Nash bargaining model

Axiomatic bargaining. theory

Department of Economics

The Properly Efficient Bargaining Solutions

Nash Demand Game and the Kalai-Smorodinsky Solution

Mathematical Social Sciences

Economics 201B Economic Theory (Spring 2017) Bargaining. Topics: the axiomatic approach (OR 15) and the strategic approach (OR 7).

AN ORDINAL SOLUTION TO BARGAINING PROBLEMS WITH MANY PLAYERS

Bargaining on a Non-Convex Domain

Monotonic ɛ-equilibria in strongly symmetric games

A Constructive Proof of the Nash Bargaining Solution

CENTER FOR INTERNATIONAL ECONOMICS. Working Paper Series. Working Paper No On unication of solutions to the bargaining problem

Background notes on bargaining

Implementing the Nash Extension Bargaining Solution for Non-convex Problems. John P. Conley* and Simon Wilkie**

Weighted values and the Core in NTU games

Bargaining without Disagreement

ECONOMICS SERIES SWP 2012/7. Robustness of Intermediate Agreements and Bargaining Solutions. Nejat Anbarci and Ching-jen Sun

Nash Bargaining for Log-Convex Problems

Dual Bargaining and the Talmud Bankruptcy Problem

Relative Benefit Equilibrating Bargaining Solution and the Ordinal Interpretation of Gauthier s Arbitration Scheme

Axiomatic Foundations for Compromise Theory. John P. Conley* Richard McLean** and Simon Wilkie*** Revised: February 2014

Repeated bargaining. Shiran Rachmilevitch. February 16, Abstract

Efficiency, Fairness and Competitiveness in Nash Bargaining Games

Reference Functions and Possibility Theorems forcardinalsocialchoiceproblems. John P. Conley* Richard P. McLean** and Simon Wilkie***

Unique Nash Implementation for a Class of Bargaining Solutions

Comment on The Veil of Public Ignorance

Random Extensive Form Games and its Application to Bargaining

BARGAINING UNDER UNCERTAINTY: A NEW APPROACH BASED ON LOSSES

Social Choice Theory. Felix Munoz-Garcia School of Economic Sciences Washington State University. EconS Advanced Microeconomics II

Achieving Efficiency with Manipulative Bargainers

Axiomatic Characterization of Task Oriented Negotiation

On the Redundancy of the Implicit Welfarist Axiom in Bargaining Theory

Revisiting Nash Wages Negotiations in Matching Models

Manipulation of Preferences and Relative Utilitarianism

Almost Transferable Utility, Changes in Production Possibilities, and the Nash Bargaining and the Kalai-Smorodinsky Solutions

Procedures we can use to resolve disagreements

Nash Bargaining Theory with Non-Convexity and Unique Solution

Rules for Aggregating Information

1 Cooperative bargaining

Computational Game Theory Spring Semester, 2005/6. Lecturer: Yishay Mansour Scribe: Ilan Cohen, Natan Rubin, Ophir Bleiberg*

13 Social choice B = 2 X X. is the collection of all binary relations on X. R = { X X : is complete and transitive}

SANDWICH GAMES. July 9, 2014

Lecture notes on Bargaining and the Nash Program

Strategy-Proofness and the Core in House Allocation Problems

On the Impact of Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives

Stackelberg-solvable games and pre-play communication

Area I: Contract Theory Question (Econ 206)

Nash Bargaining Theory with Non-Convexity and Unique Solution

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India July 2012

Computational Properties of Quasi-Strict Equilibrium

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 7: Supermodular Games

Math 152: Applicable Mathematics and Computing

0R tr 9 Springer-Verlag 1989

Kalai-Smorodinsky Bargaining Solution Equilibria

Can everyone benefit from innovation?

Axiomatic Bargaining with Inequality Aversion: Norms vs. Preferences

The B.E. Journal of Theoretical Economics

Network Calculus. A General Framework for Interference Management and Resource Allocation. Martin Schubert

ON THE COASE THEOREM AND COALITIONAL STABILITY: THE PRINCIPLE OF EQUAL RELATIVE CONCESSION

On the Non-Symmetric Nash and Kalai Smorodinsky Bargaining Solutions. Yigal Gerchak

BIPARTITE GRAPHS AND THE SHAPLEY VALUE

Hypothetical Bargaining and Equilibrium Refinement in Non-Cooperative Games

Players Indifferent to Cooperate and Characterizations of the Shapley Value

A Logical Model of Nash Bargaining Solution

6.891 Games, Decision, and Computation February 5, Lecture 2

The Axiomatic Method in Social Choice Theory:

Nash Bargaining Equilibria for Controllable Markov Chains Games

A family of ordinal solutions to bargaining problems with many players

No-envy in Queueing Problems

Solution Homework 1 - EconS 501

Implementation of the Ordinal Shapley Value for a three-agent economy 1

The -nucleolus for NTU games and Shapley procedure

Extending the Nash solution to choice problems with reference points

An axiomatization of minimal curb sets. 1. Introduction. Mark Voorneveld,,1, Willemien Kets, and Henk Norde

Dominance and Admissibility without Priors

STABILITY IN MATHEMATICAL GAME THEORY

A Generic Approach to Coalition Formation

Coalitional Structure of the Muller-Satterthwaite Theorem

Bargaining games : a comparison of Nash s solution with the Coco-value. Daniel Huynh June 19, 2016

Social Welfare Functions that Satisfy Pareto, Anonymity, and Neutrality: Countable Many Alternatives. Donald E. Campbell College of William and Mary

The Distribution of Optimal Strategies in Symmetric Zero-sum Games

Computational Social Choice: Spring 2015

On the meaning of the Nash product. Walter Trockel

ONLINE APPENDIX TO HOW TO CONTROL CONTROLLED SCHOOL CHOICE (NOT FOR PUBLICATION)

Egalitarianism under Incomplete Information

Bargaining over multiple issues with maximin and leximin preferences

Sequential Equilibria of Multi-Stage Games with Infinite Sets of Types and Actions

Transcription:

Cooperative bargaining: independence and monotonicity imply disagreement Shiran Rachmilevitch September 23, 2012 Abstract A unique bargaining solution satisfies restricted monotonicity, independence of irrelevant alternatives, independence of equivalent utility representations, and symmetry the disagreement solution. It is also the unique bargaining solution that satisfies independence of irrelevant alternatives, continuity, and strong disagreement monotonicity. Keywords: Bargaining; Disagreement solution. JEL Classification: C78; D74. 1 Introduction A bargaining problem is a pair (S, d), where S R n is the feasible set, representing all possible (v-n.m) utility agreements among the n bargainers (henceforth players), and d S, the disagreement point, is a point that specifies their utilities in case they do not reach a unanimous agreement on some point of S. The following assumptions are made on (S, d): Department of Economics, University of Haifa, Mount Carmel, Haifa, 31905, Israel. shiranrach@econ.haifa.ac.il Web: http://econ.haifa.ac.il/ shiranrach/ Email: 1

S is compact and convex; d < x for some x S; 1 For all x S and y R n : d y x y S. Denote by B the collection of all such pairs (S, d). A solution is any function µ: B R n that satisfies µ(s, d) S for all (S, d) B. Given a feasible set S, the weak Pareto frontier of S is W P (S) {x S : y > x y / S} and the strict Pareto frontier of S is P (S) {x S : y x y / S}. The best that player i can hope for in the problem (S, d), given that each j i obtains at least d j utility units, is a i (S, d) max{x i : x S d }, where S d {x S : x d}. The point a(s, d) = (a 1 (S, d),, a n (S, d)) is the ideal point of the problem (S, d). The Kalai-Smorodinsky solution, KS, due to Kalai and Smorodinsky (1975), is defined by KS(S, d) W P (S) [d; a(s, d)]. 2 The Nash solution, N, due to Nash (1950), is defined to be the unique maximizer of Π i (x i d i ) over S d. Consider the following axioms, in the statements of which (S, d) is an arbitrary problem. Weak Pareto Optimality (WPO): µ(s, d) W P (S). Individual Rationality (IR): µ(s, d) S d. Let F A denote the set of positive affine transformations from R to itself. 3 1 Vector inequalities: xry if and only if x i Ry i for all i, R {>, }; x y if and only if x y & x y. 2 Given two vectors x and y, the segment connecting them is denoted [x; y]. 3 i.e., the set of functions f of the form f(x) = αx + β, where α > 0. 2

Independence of Equivalent Utility Representations (IEUR): f = (f 1,, f n ) (F A ) n f µ(s, d) = µ(f S, f d). 4 Let Π denote the set of permutations on {1,, n}. Symmetry (SY): i, j {1,, n}: [(π S = S)&(π d = d) π Π] µ i (S, d) = µ j (S, d). Say that a solution is admissible if it satisfies WPO, IR, IEUR, and SY. The Nash solution is the only admissible solution that satisfies the following axiom, in the statement of which (S, d) and (T, e) are arbitrary problems. Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives (IIA): [S T ]&[d = e]&[µ(t, e) S] µ(s, d) = µ(t, e). In words, IIA says that deleting unchosen options should not change the bargaining s outcome. Consider the 2-person case, namely n = 2. Given x S d, let gi S (x j ) be the maximal possible payoff for i in S given that j s payoffs is x j. Consider the following axiom, in the statement of which (S, d) and (T, d) are arbitrary 2-person problems with a common disagreement point. Individual Monotonicity (IM): 4 If f i : R R for each i, x R n, and A R n, then: (f 1,, f n ) x (f 1 (x 1 ),, f n (x n )) and (f 1,, f n ) A {(f 1,, f n ) a : a A}. 3

[a j (S, d) = a j (T, d)]&[g S i (x j ) g T i (x j ) x S d T d ] µ i (S, d) µ i (T, d). In words, IM says that if the feasible set stretches in the i-th direction, then player i should not get hurt. Kalai and Smorodinsky (1975) proved that for n = 2, KS is the unique admissible solution that satisfies IM. 5 In the n 3 case, the idea of individual monotonicity can be formulated in several ways; the following in the statement of which (S, d) and (T, d) are arbitrary n-person problems with a common disagreement point is a common and transparent one (see Thomson (1994)). Restricted Monotonicity (RM): If a(s, d) = a(t, d) and S T, then µ(s, d) µ(t, d). The Kalai-Smorodinsky solution is the only admissible solution that satisfies RM. Since N KS, it follows that under admissibility, IIA and RM or, to use slightly more general terms, independence and monotonicity are not compatible. Can we make them compatible by compromising on efficiency? The following result shows that this compromise does not take us very far. Theorem 1. There exists a unique bargaining solution that satisfies independence of equivalent utility representations, independence of irrelevant alternatives, symmetry, and restricted monotonicity. This is the disagreement solution: µ(s, d) d. Proof. Obviously the disagreement solution satisfies the axioms. Conversely, let µ be an arbitrary solution that satisfies them. For each x (0, 1], let Q x = conv hull{0, e i, x 1 : i = 1,, n}. 6 First, I argue that if µ(q x, 0) = 0 for some x (0, 1], then µ(s, d) d. To see this, let (S, d) be an arbitrary problem and suppose that µ(q x, 0) = 0 for some x (0, 1]. 5 IR is redundant: the other axioms suffice for the characterization. 6 0 (0,, 0), 1 (1,, 1), and e i is R n s i-th unit vector. 4

By IEUR we may assume d = 0. By IEUR, µ(m Q x, 0) = M µ(q x, 0) = M 0 = 0 for every M > 0. Fix a sufficiently large M such that there exists a symmetric feasible set T such that T R n + = M Q x and T S. By SY, µ(t, 0) = z 1 for some z. By RM and the fact that T M Q x, z 0. Then, it must be that z = 0 otherwise, the combination of µ(m Q x, 0) = 0 with the fact z 1 M Q x would contradict IIA. Therefore z = 0. By IIA, µ(s, 0) = 0. I argue that if µ is different than the disagreement solution then µ(q x, 0) = x 1 for all x (0, 1]. To see this, note that, by SY, µ(q x, 0) = y 1, for some y x. If y < x, then there is a λ (0, 1) such that y 1 λ Q x, and therefore, by IIA, µ(λ Q x, 0) = y 1. On the other hand, by IEUR, µ(λ Q x, 0) = λy 1, hence y = 0, in contradiction to the fact that µ is not the disagreement solution. Let B {(S, d) B : P (S) = W P (S)}. I will prove that if µ is different than the disagreement solution then it coincides with the Kalai-Smorodinsky solution on B. This would be a contradiction, because KS violates IIA on B. Suppose then that µ is not the disagreement solution and let (S, d) B. By IEUR, we can assume d = 0 and a(s, d) = 1. Let T = conv hull{0, e i, KS(S, d) : i = 1,, n}. Since T = Q x for x = KS 1 (S, d) = = KS n (S, d), 7 and since µ is not the disagreement solution, it follows from the previous paragraph that µ(t, 0) = KS(S, d). By RM, µ(s, d) µ(t, 0) = KS(S, d). Since W P (S) = P (S) and KS(S, d) W P (S), µ(s, d) = KS(S, d). Remark 1 : Given a nonzero vector p, the corresponding proportional solution (due to Kalai (1977)) is defined by µ p (S, d) d + a p, where a > 0 is the maximum such that the aforementioned expression is in S. Corresponding to p = 1 is the egalitarian solution and corresponding to p = e i is the i-th dictatorial solution. The former satisfies all the axioms from Theorem 1 besides IEUR, and the latter all of them but SY. 7 Since both the disagreement and ideal points have equal coordinates, all the players enjoy the same payoffs under KS. 5

Remark 2 : Note that IR is not invoked in Theorem 1. Remark 3 : If IR is added to the axioms listed in Theorem 1, then a much shorter proof obtains. Roth (1980) showed that when one deletes WPO from the list of Nash s axioms, the only solutions that satisfy the remaining axioms are the Nash solution and the disagreement solution. Then, with IR added to the axioms list, it follows that only the disagreement solution satisfies the axioms, because the Nash solution violates RM. IR is important for Roth s theorem; here is an example of a solution that satisfies all of Nash s axioms besides WPO and IR, and is different from the disagreement solution and the Nash solution the anti Nash solution, that picks for every (S, d) the maximizer of the Nash product over {x S : x d}. RM imposes a monotonicity condition on the feasible sets. The following axiom expresses a similar requirement from disagreement-point-changes. In its statement, (S, d) and (T, e) are arbitrary problems and i is an arbitrary player. Strong Disagreement Point Monotonicity (S.DIM): If T = S, a(s, d) / S, e i > d i, and e i = d i, then µ i (T, e) > µ i (S, d). 8 The Nash solution satisfies IIA but not S.DIM, and in the 2-person case the Kalai- Smorodinsky solution satisfies S.DIM but not IIA. This is another example of the informal intuition that the Nash solution is independent, the Kalai-Smorodinsky solution is monotonic, and these two principles are not compatible. I end this paper with a result that formalizes the (essential) incompatibility of IIA and S.DIM. This result is stated for the subclass of B that satisfy the following: for every feasible set S, 8 The first disagreement monotonicity axiom to be introduced to the literature, which is due to Thomson (1987), is stated in terms of a weak inequality. Livne (1989) was the first to consider strict-inequality disagreement monotonicity. 6

if {x 1,, x K } S, then y S, where y i = min{x 1 i,, x K i }. Call this domain B. Additionally, I will make use of the following axiom, in the statement of which (S, d) is an arbitrary problem and {(S n, e)} is an arbitrary sequence of problems sharing the same disagreement point. Continuity (CONT): If e = d and {S n } converges to S in the Hausdorff topology, then µ(s n, e) µ(s, d). Theorem 2. There exists a unique bargaining solution on B that satisfies independence of irrelevant alternatives, strong disagreement monotonicity, and continuity. This is the disagreement solution: µ(s, d) d. Proof. Obviously the disagreement solution satisfies the axioms. Conversely, let µ be an arbitrary solution that satisfies them. Let (S, d). By CONT, we may assume that a(s, d) / S. Assume by contradiction that x d, where x µ(s, d). Wlog, suppose that x 1 d 1. Case 1: x 1 > d 1. Let ɛ x 1 d 1. Recall that d S, there is some s S with s > d, and S is convex and comprehensive; therefore, there is a sufficiently small δ (0, ɛ ) such that s i d + δ e i S for all i = 1,, n. Let T {y S : y x} and T conv hull(t {d, s i : i = 1,, n}). By IIA, µ(t, d) = x. By S.DIM, µ 1 (T, s 1 ) > x 1, which is impossible. Case 2: x 1 < d 1. Let Q {y S : y 1 x 1 }. By IIA, µ(q, d) = x. Let ɛ (0, d 1 x 1 ) and let e d ɛ e 1. By S.DIM, µ 1 (Q, e) < x 1, which is impossible. 9 Acknowledgments: I am grateful to Ehud Kalai, Al Roth, Joel Sobel, and William Thomson for their helpful comments. 9 The restriction to B guarantees that e Q, therefore (Q, e) is a well-defined problem. 7

References Kalai, E. (1977) Proportional solutions to bargaining situations: interpersonal utility comparisons, Econometrica, 45, 1623-1630. Kalai, E. and Smorodinsky, M. (1975), Other solutions to Nash s bargaining problem, Econometrica, 43, 513-518. Livne, Z.A (1989), Axiomatic characterizations of the Raiffa and the Kalai-Smorodinsky solutions to the bargaining problem, Operations Research, 37,972-980. Nash, J. F. (1950), The bargaining problem, Econometrica, 18, 155-162. Roth, A.E. (1980), The Nash solution as a model of rational bargaining. In: Extremal Methods and Systems Analysis, A.V. Fiacco and K.O. Kortanek, eds., Springer Verlag, 306-311. Thomson, W. (1987), Monotonicity of bargaining solutions with respect to the disagreement point, Journal of Economic Theory, 42,50-58. Thomson, W. (1994), Cooperative models of bargaining. In: Handbook of game theory, vol 2., Aumann R.J., Hart S. eds., North-Holland, Amsterdam 1237-1284. 8