INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC 8 Identity and Definite Descriptions

Similar documents
INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC 8 Identity and Definite Descriptions

INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC

INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC

I thank the author of the examination paper on which sample paper is based. VH

EXERCISES BOOKLET. for the Logic Manual. Volker Halbach. Oxford. There are no changes to the exercises from last year s edition

(c) Establish the following claims by means of counterexamples.

Class 29 - November 3 Semantics for Predicate Logic

The Natural Deduction Pack

Introduction to Logic and Axiomatic Set Theory

MAGIC Set theory. lecture 1

2-4: The Use of Quantifiers

Philosophy 240 Symbolic Logic Russell Marcus Hamilton College Fall 2014

cse541 LOGIC FOR COMPUTER SCIENCE

Proseminar on Semantic Theory Fall 2013 Ling 720 First Order (Predicate) Logic: Syntax and Natural Deduction 1

Propositional Logic Review

Proseminar on Semantic Theory Fall 2013 Ling 720 Propositional Logic: Syntax and Natural Deduction 1

Elementary Linear Algebra, Second Edition, by Spence, Insel, and Friedberg. ISBN Pearson Education, Inc., Upper Saddle River, NJ.

CPPE TURN OVER

INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC 3 Formalisation in Propositional Logic

Proof Techniques (Review of Math 271)

INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC 1 Sets, Relations, and Arguments. Why logic? Arguments

MAGIC Set theory. lecture 2

Axiomatic set theory. Chapter Why axiomatic set theory?

Interpretations of PL (Model Theory)

Final Exam (100 points)

cis32-ai lecture # 18 mon-3-apr-2006

Examples: P: it is not the case that P. P Q: P or Q P Q: P implies Q (if P then Q) Typical formula:

What are the recursion theoretic properties of a set of axioms? Understanding a paper by William Craig Armando B. Matos

INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC. Propositional Logic. Examples of syntactic claims

Chapter 2: Introduction to Propositional Logic

2010 Part IA Formal Logic, Model Answers

Discrete Structures Proofwriting Checklist

Discrete Mathematics

Overview of Today s Lecture

Propositional logic (revision) & semantic entailment. p. 1/34

Predicate Calculus. Lila Kari. University of Waterloo. Predicate Calculus CS245, Logic and Computation 1 / 59

CS1021. Why logic? Logic about inference or argument. Start from assumptions or axioms. Make deductions according to rules of reasoning.

G52DOA - Derivation of Algorithms Predicate Logic

CHAPTER 2 INTRODUCTION TO CLASSICAL PROPOSITIONAL LOGIC

Overview of Today s Lecture

Section 2.1: Introduction to the Logic of Quantified Statements

Formal Logic: Quantifiers, Predicates, and Validity. CS 130 Discrete Structures

First-Degree Entailment

CMPSCI 601: Tarski s Truth Definition Lecture 15. where

Introduction to Metalogic

Quantifiers Here is a (true) statement about real numbers: Every real number is either rational or irrational.

Handout: Proof of the completeness theorem

INF3170 Logikk Spring Homework #8 For Friday, March 18

Propositions and Proofs

Intermediate Logic. First-Order Logic

Arguments and Proofs. 1. A set of sentences (the premises) 2. A sentence (the conclusion)

TECHNISCHE UNIVERSITEIT EINDHOVEN Faculteit Wiskunde en Informatica. Final exam Logic & Set Theory (2IT61) (correction model)

Section 3.1: Direct Proof and Counterexample 1

The Substitutional Analysis of Logical Consequence

Introduction to Logic in Computer Science: Autumn 2006

CHAPTER 2. FIRST ORDER LOGIC

Truth, Subderivations and the Liar. Why Should I Care about the Liar Sentence? Uses of the Truth Concept - (i) Disquotation.

INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC 4 The Syntax of Predicate Logic

Before you get started, make sure you ve read Chapter 1, which sets the tone for the work we will begin doing here.

SKETCHY NOTES FOR WEEKS 7 AND 8

Predicates, Quantifiers and Nested Quantifiers

Gödel s Incompleteness Theorems

Restricted truth predicates in first-order logic

Meta-logic derivation rules

Symbolic Logic 3. For an inference to be deductively valid it is impossible for the conclusion to be false if the premises are true.

CM10196 Topic 2: Sets, Predicates, Boolean algebras

Ling 98a: The Meaning of Negation (Week 5)

Victoria Gitman and Thomas Johnstone. New York City College of Technology, CUNY

Computational Logic. Recall of First-Order Logic. Damiano Zanardini

Russell s logicism. Jeff Speaks. September 26, 2007

Introduction to Logic

3. The Logic of Quantified Statements Summary. Aaron Tan August 2017

Automated Reasoning Lecture 5: First-Order Logic

Draft of February 2019 please do not cite without permission. A new modal liar 1 T. Parent

INTENSIONS MARCUS KRACHT

Announcements & Such

15414/614 Optional Lecture 3: Predicate Logic

A Little History Incompleteness The First Theorem The Second Theorem Implications. Gödel s Theorem. Anders O.F. Hendrickson

Math 144 Summer 2012 (UCR) Pro-Notes June 24, / 15

Generalized Quantifiers Logical and Linguistic Aspects

DEFINITE DESCRIPTIONS: LANGUAGE, LOGIC, AND ELIMINATION

Logic and Mathematics:

Proving logical equivalencies (1.3)

Supplementary Logic Notes CSE 321 Winter 2009

Notes on Propositional and First-Order Logic (CPSC 229 Class Notes, January )

Lecture 13: Soundness, Completeness and Compactness

Ling 130 Notes: Predicate Logic and Natural Deduction

Truth-Functional Logic

KRIPKE S THEORY OF TRUTH 1. INTRODUCTION

Relational Reasoning in Natural Language

The Philosophy of Mathematics after Foundationalism

THE LOGIC OF QUANTIFIED STATEMENTS. Predicates and Quantified Statements I. Predicates and Quantified Statements I CHAPTER 3 SECTION 3.

Direct Proof and Counterexample I:Introduction

Classical Propositional Logic

Truthmaker Maximalism defended again. Eduardo Barrio and Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereyra

Class 15: Hilbert and Gödel

Direct Proof and Counterexample I:Introduction. Copyright Cengage Learning. All rights reserved.

185.A09 Advanced Mathematical Logic

First Order Logic (1A) Young W. Lim 11/18/13

We introduce one more operation on sets, perhaps the most important

Transcription:

INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC 8 Identity and Definite Descriptions Volker Halbach The analysis of the beginning would thus yield the notion of the unity of being and not-being or, in a more reflected form, the unity of differentiatedness and non-differentiatedness, or the identity of identity and non-identity. Hegel, The Science of Logic

8.1 Qualitative and Numerical Identity Assume Keith and Volker don t share a car; they only have the same model of the same year (same colour etc). Keith and Volker have the same car. Keith and Volker have identical cars. This an example of (approximate) qualitative identity.

8.1 Qualitative and Numerical Identity Assume Keith and Volker don t share a car; they only have the same model of the same year (same colour etc). Keith and Volker have the same car. Keith and Volker have identical cars. This an example of (approximate) qualitative identity. Qualitative identity can be formalised as a binary predicate letter expressing close similarity or sameness in all relevant aspects.

8.1 Qualitative and Numerical Identity This is the same car as the car that was seen at the scene. This means probably that the very same car and not just a car of the same brand, the same colour etc was seen at the scene.

8.1 Qualitative and Numerical Identity This is the same car as the car that was seen at the scene. This means probably that the very same car and not just a car of the same brand, the same colour etc was seen at the scene. This is an example of numerical identity.

8.1 Qualitative and Numerical Identity This is the same car as the car that was seen at the scene. This means probably that the very same car and not just a car of the same brand, the same colour etc was seen at the scene. This is an example of numerical identity. Occasionally it s ambiguous whether numerical or qualitative identity is meant. In what follows I talk about numerical identity.

8.1 Qualitative and Numerical Identity The language L = is L 2 plus an additional binary predicate letter = that is always interpreted as identity.

8.1 Qualitative and Numerical Identity The language L = is L 2 plus an additional binary predicate letter = that is always interpreted as identity. In L 2 we can formalise is identical to as a binary predicate letter, but this predicate letter can receive arbitrary relations as extension (semantic value).

8.1 Qualitative and Numerical Identity The language L = is L 2 plus an additional binary predicate letter = that is always interpreted as identity. In L 2 we can formalise is identical to as a binary predicate letter, but this predicate letter can receive arbitrary relations as extension (semantic value). In L = the new binary predicate letter is always taken to express identity.

8.2 The Syntax of L = Definition (atomic formulae of L = ) All atomic formulae of L 2 are atomic formulae of L =. Furthermore, if s and t are variables or constants, then s = t is an atomic formula of L =.

8.2 The Syntax of L = Definition (atomic formulae of L = ) All atomic formulae of L 2 are atomic formulae of L =. Furthermore, if s and t are variables or constants, then s = t is an atomic formula of L =. c = a, x = y 3, x 7 =x 7, and x = a are all atomic formulae of L =.

8.2 The Syntax of L = Definition (atomic formulae of L = ) All atomic formulae of L 2 are atomic formulae of L =. Furthermore, if s and t are variables or constants, then s = t is an atomic formula of L =. c = a, x = y 3, x 7 =x 7, and x = a are all atomic formulae of L =. The symbol = now plays two roles: as symbol of L = and as a symbol in the metalanguage.

8.2 The Syntax of L = One can use connectives and quantifiers to build formulae of L = in the same ways as in L 2.

8.2 The Syntax of L = One can use connectives and quantifiers to build formulae of L = in the same ways as in L 2. x = y and x(rx y 2 y 2 =x) are formulae of L =.

8.2 The Syntax of L = One can use connectives and quantifiers to build formulae of L = in the same ways as in L 2. x = y and x(rx y 2 y 2 =x) are formulae of L =. The notion of an L = -sentence is defined in analogy to the notion of an L 2 -sentence.

8.3 Semantics Everything is as for L 2, except that an additional clause needs to be added to the definition of satisfaction, where A is an L 2 -structure, s is a variable or constant, and t is a variable or constant: (ix) s = t α A =T if and only if s α A = t α A.

8.3 Semantics Everything is as for L 2, except that an additional clause needs to be added to the definition of satisfaction, where A is an L 2 -structure, s is a variable or constant, and t is a variable or constant: (ix) s = t α A =T if and only if s α A = t α A. All other definitions of Chapter 5 carry over to L =, just with L 2 replaced by L =.

8.3 Semantics Everything is as for L 2, except that an additional clause needs to be added to the definition of satisfaction, where A is an L 2 -structure, s is a variable or constant, and t is a variable or constant: (ix) s = t α A =T if and only if s α A = t α A. All other definitions of Chapter 5 carry over to L =, just with L 2 replaced by L =. Caution: L = -structures don t assign semantic values to the symbol =. There is no difference between L = and L 2 -structures!

8.3 Semantics x y x = y isn t logically true.

8.3 Semantics x y x = y isn t logically true. Counterexample: Let A be any L 2 -structure with {1, 2} as its domain.

Natural Deduction for L = has the same rules as Natural Deduction for L 2 except for rules for =: 8.4 Proof Rules for Identity

8.4 Proof Rules for Identity Natural Deduction for L = has the same rules as Natural Deduction for L 2 except for rules for =: =Intro Any assumption of the form t = t where t is a constant can and must be discharged. A proof with an application of =Intro looks like this: [t = t]

8.4 Proof Rules for Identity =Elim If s and t are constants, the result of appending ϕ[t/v] to a proof of ϕ[s/v] and a proof of s = t or t =s is a proof of ϕ[t/v]. ϕ[s/v] ϕ[t/v] s = t =Elim ϕ[s/v] ϕ[t/v] t =s =Elim Strictly speaking, only one of the versions is needed, as from s = t one can always obtain t =s using only one of the rules.

8.4 Proof Rules for Identity x y (Rx y (x = y Ryx))

8.4 Proof Rules for Identity x y (Rx y (x = y Ryx)) Here is the proof:

8.4 Proof Rules for Identity x y (Rx y (x = y Ryx)) Here is the proof: Rab a =b

8.4 Proof Rules for Identity x y (Rx y (x = y Ryx)) Here is the proof: =Elim Rab a =b Raa

8.4 Proof Rules for Identity x y (Rx y (x = y Ryx)) Here is the proof: =Elim Rab a =b Raa a =b

8.4 Proof Rules for Identity x y (Rx y (x = y Ryx)) Here is the proof: =Elim Rab a =b Raa a =b Rba

8.4 Proof Rules for Identity x y (Rx y (x = y Ryx)) Here is the proof: =Elim Rab [a =b] Raa [a =b] =Elim Rba a =b Rba

8.4 Proof Rules for Identity x y (Rx y (x = y Ryx)) Here is the proof: =Elim [Rab] [a =b] Raa [a =b] =Elim Rba a =b Rba Rab (a =b Rba)

8.4 Proof Rules for Identity x y (Rx y (x = y Ryx)) Here is the proof: =Elim [Rab] [a =b] Raa [a =b] =Elim Rba a =b Rba Rab (a =b Rba) y (Ray (a = y Rya))

8.4 Proof Rules for Identity x y (Rx y (x = y Ryx)) Here is the proof: =Elim [Rab] [a =b] Raa [a =b] =Elim Rba a =b Rba Rab (a =b Rba) y (Ray (a = y Rya)) x y (Rx y (x = y Ryx))

Theorem (adequacy) Assume that ϕ and all elements of Γ are L = -sentences. Then Γ ϕ if and only if Γ ϕ. 8.4 Proof Rules for Identity

8.4 Uses of identity Using = one can formalise overt identity claims: William ii is Wilhelm ii.

8.4 Uses of identity Using = one can formalise overt identity claims: William ii is Wilhelm ii. formalisation a = b a: William ii b: Wilhelm ii

Don t confuse identity with predication. 8.4 Uses of identity

8.4 Uses of identity Don t confuse identity with predication. William is an emperor.

8.4 Uses of identity Don t confuse identity with predication. William is an emperor. formalisation Qa a: William Q:... is an emperor Here is forms part of the predicate is an emperor.

8.4 Uses of identity Don t confuse identity with predication. William is an emperor. formalisation Qa a: William Q:... is an emperor Here is forms part of the predicate is an emperor. William is the emperor. Here is expresses identity.

Identity can also be used in formalisations of sentences that do not involve identity explicitly. 8.4 Uses of identity

8.4 Uses of identity Identity can also be used in formalisations of sentences that do not involve identity explicitly. There is exactly one perfect being.

8.4 Uses of identity Identity can also be used in formalisations of sentences that do not involve identity explicitly. There is exactly one perfect being. formalisation x (Px y (Py x = y)) P:... is a perfect being

8.4 Uses of identity Identity can also be used in formalisations of sentences that do not involve identity explicitly. There is exactly one perfect being. formalisation x (Px y (Py x = y)) P:... is a perfect being Similar tricks work for various other numerical quantifiers at least three, at most 2, and so on. There is no reference to numbers.

Definite descriptions 8.4 Uses of identity The following expressions are definite descriptions:

8.4 Uses of identity Definite descriptions The following expressions are definite descriptions: the present king of France

8.4 Uses of identity Definite descriptions The following expressions are definite descriptions: the present king of France Tim s car

8.4 Uses of identity Definite descriptions The following expressions are definite descriptions: the present king of France Tim s car the person who has stolen a book from the library and who has forgotten his or her bag in the library Formalising definite descriptions as constants brings various problems as the semantics of definite descriptions doesn t match the semantics of constants in L =.

8.4 Uses of identity Russell s trick Tim s car is red.

8.4 Uses of identity Russell s trick Tim s car is red. Paraphrase Tim owns exactly one car and it is red.

8.4 Uses of identity Russell s trick Tim s car is red. Paraphrase Tim owns exactly one car and it is red. formalisation x (Qx Rbx y (Q y Rby x = y) Px) b: Tim Q:... is a car R:... owns... P:... is red

8.4 Uses of identity This formalisation is much better than the formalisation of Tim s car as a constant. For instance, the following argument comes out as valid if Russell s trick is used (but not if a constant is used): Tim s car is red. Therefore there is a red car. formalisation x(qx Rbx y(q y Rby x = y) Px) x(px Qx) The proof is in the Manual.

8.4 Uses of identity This formalisation is much better than the formalisation of Tim s car as a constant. For instance, the following argument comes out as valid if Russell s trick is used (but not if a constant is used): Tim s car is red. Therefore there is a red car. formalisation x(qx Rbx y(q y Rby x = y) Px) x(px Qx) The proof is in the Manual. So the English argument is valid in predicate logic with identity.

8.4 Uses of identity By using Russell s trick one can formalise definite descriptions in such way that the definite description may fail to refer to something. Constants, in contrast, are assigned objects in any L 2 -structure.

8.4 Uses of identity By using Russell s trick one can formalise definite descriptions in such way that the definite description may fail to refer to something. Constants, in contrast, are assigned objects in any L 2 -structure. Using Russell s trick offers more ways to analyse sentences containing definite descriptions and negations.

8.4 Uses of identity By using Russell s trick one can formalise definite descriptions in such way that the definite description may fail to refer to something. Constants, in contrast, are assigned objects in any L 2 -structure. Using Russell s trick offers more ways to analyse sentences containing definite descriptions and negations. Volker s Ferrari is red. Volker s Ferrari isn t red. The first sentence is false, but is the second sentence true?

8.4 Uses of identity By using Russell s trick one can formalise definite descriptions in such way that the definite description may fail to refer to something. Constants, in contrast, are assigned objects in any L 2 -structure. Using Russell s trick offers more ways to analyse sentences containing definite descriptions and negations. Volker s Ferrari is red. Volker s Ferrari isn t red. The first sentence is false, but is the second sentence true? There is a reading under which both sentence are false. This reading can be made explicit in L = using Russell s analysis of definite descriptions.

8.4 Uses of identity Volker s Ferrari isn t red. formalisation x((qx Rax) y(q y Ray x = y) Px) a: Volker Q:... is a Ferrari R:... owns... P:... is red This formalisation expresses that Volker has exactly one Ferrari and that it isn t red.

8.4 Uses of identity Volker s Ferrari isn t red. formalisation x((qx Rax) y(q y Ray x = y) Px) a: Volker Q:... is a Ferrari R:... owns... P:... is red This formalisation expresses that Volker has exactly one Ferrari and that it isn t red. Under this analysis Volker s Ferrari is red and Volker s Ferrari isn t red are both false.

8.4 Uses of identity It s not the case (for whatever reason) that Volker s Ferrari is red. I tend to understand this sentence in the following way: formalisation x((qx Rax) y(q y Ray x = y) Px)

8.4 Uses of identity It s not the case (for whatever reason) that Volker s Ferrari is red. I tend to understand this sentence in the following way: formalisation x((qx Rax) y(q y Ray x = y) Px) Perhaps the sentence Volker s Ferrari isn t red can be understood as saying the same; so it is ambiguous (scope ambiguity concerning ). x((qx Rax) y(q y Ray x = y) Px)

8.4 Uses of identity It s not the case (for whatever reason) that Volker s Ferrari is red. I tend to understand this sentence in the following way: formalisation x((qx Rax) y(q y Ray x = y) Px) Perhaps the sentence Volker s Ferrari isn t red can be understood as saying the same; so it is ambiguous (scope ambiguity concerning ). x((qx Rax) y(q y Ray x = y) Px)

8.4 Uses of identity Logical constants I have treated identity, the connectives and expressions like all etc. as subject-independent vocabulary. Perhaps there are more such expressions: many, few, infinitely many

8.4 Uses of identity Logical constants I have treated identity, the connectives and expressions like all etc. as subject-independent vocabulary. Perhaps there are more such expressions: many, few, infinitely many necessarily, possibly

8.4 Uses of identity Logical constants I have treated identity, the connectives and expressions like all etc. as subject-independent vocabulary. Perhaps there are more such expressions: many, few, infinitely many necessarily, possibly it s obligatory that

8.4 Uses of identity Logical constants I have treated identity, the connectives and expressions like all etc. as subject-independent vocabulary. Perhaps there are more such expressions: many, few, infinitely many necessarily, possibly it s obligatory that At any rate the logical vocabulary of L = is sufficient for analysing the validity of arguments in (large parts of) the sciences and mathematics. Perhaps the above expressions can be analysed in L = in the framework of specific theories.

The dark side The dark side So far you have seen the logician mainly as a kind of philosophical hygienist, who makes sure that philosophers don t blunder by using logically invalid arguments or by messing up the scopes of quantifiers or connectives. Logic seems to be an auxiliary discipline for sticklers who secure the foundations of other disciplines.

The dark side The dark side So far you have seen the logician mainly as a kind of philosophical hygienist, who makes sure that philosophers don t blunder by using logically invalid arguments or by messing up the scopes of quantifiers or connectives. Logic seems to be an auxiliary discipline for sticklers who secure the foundations of other disciplines. But there is also a dark side. Here is an example.

The dark side The dark side So far you have seen the logician mainly as a kind of philosophical hygienist, who makes sure that philosophers don t blunder by using logically invalid arguments or by messing up the scopes of quantifiers or connectives. Logic seems to be an auxiliary discipline for sticklers who secure the foundations of other disciplines. But there is also a dark side. Here is an example. 10

Russell s paradox The dark side If there are any safe foundations in any discipline, then the foundations of mathematics and logic should be unshakable. I have used sets for the foundations of logic: sets, relations, and functions. L 2 -structures are defined in terms of sets. Large parts of various disciplines (mathematics, sciences, various parts of philosophy) are founded on set theory. Sets replace in many cases the role assigned to universals in classical philosophy.

Russell s paradox The dark side If there are any safe foundations in any discipline, then the foundations of mathematics and logic should be unshakable. I have used sets for the foundations of logic: sets, relations, and functions. L 2 -structures are defined in terms of sets. Large parts of various disciplines (mathematics, sciences, various parts of philosophy) are founded on set theory. Sets replace in many cases the role assigned to universals in classical philosophy. But the theory of sets is threatened by paradox.

The dark side (Exercise 7.6) There is not set {d d d} that contains exactly those things that do not have themselves as elements. Thus defining sets using expressions {d...d...} is risky. So presumably the assumptions about sets you used at school form an inconsistent set of assumptions: anything can be proved from them.

Russell s paradox shattered Frege s foundations of mathematics. The dark side

The dark side Russell s paradox shattered Frege s foundations of mathematics. In the early 20th century logicians developed theories of sets in which the Russell paradox does not arise (e.g. Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory). They are still in use.

The dark side Russell s paradox shattered Frege s foundations of mathematics. In the early 20th century logicians developed theories of sets in which the Russell paradox does not arise (e.g. Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory). They are still in use. But there remained doubt in the hearts of some mathematicians and philosophers: they still didn t know that the theory of sets (and therefore the foundations of mathematics) is consistent as there could be other paradoxes.

The dark side Russell s paradox shattered Frege s foundations of mathematics. In the early 20th century logicians developed theories of sets in which the Russell paradox does not arise (e.g. Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory). They are still in use. But there remained doubt in the hearts of some mathematicians and philosophers: they still didn t know that the theory of sets (and therefore the foundations of mathematics) is consistent as there could be other paradoxes. The hope: one day a white knight would come and prove, using the instruments of logic, that the revised theory of sets is (syntactically or semantically) consistent. Some tried...

The dark side In the end a black knight came and, using the methods of logic, proved roughly the following: If there is a proof of the consistency of set theory, using the tools of logic and set theory, then set theory is inconsistent.

The dark side In the end a black knight came and, using the methods of logic, proved roughly the following: If there is a proof of the consistency of set theory, using the tools of logic and set theory, then set theory is inconsistent. We can never prove, perhaps never know, that the foundations are safe (consistent). Not only did the white knights fail, they failed by necessity.

The dark side In the end a black knight came and, using the methods of logic, proved roughly the following: If there is a proof of the consistency of set theory, using the tools of logic and set theory, then set theory is inconsistent. We can never prove, perhaps never know, that the foundations are safe (consistent). Not only did the white knights fail, they failed by necessity. Gödel s proof is so devastatingly general that replacing set theory with a tamer theory will not help against Gödel s result. One can prove the consistency of one s standpoint only if that standpoint is inconsistent.

The dark side In the end a black knight came and, using the methods of logic, proved roughly the following: If there is a proof of the consistency of set theory, using the tools of logic and set theory, then set theory is inconsistent. We can never prove, perhaps never know, that the foundations are safe (consistent). Not only did the white knights fail, they failed by necessity. Gödel s proof is so devastatingly general that replacing set theory with a tamer theory will not help against Gödel s result. One can prove the consistency of one s standpoint only if that standpoint is inconsistent. What remains is, perhaps, faith...