γ γ γ γ(α) ). Then γ (a) γ (a ) ( γ 1

Similar documents
Universal Algebra for Logics

Math 588, Fall 2001 Problem Set 1 Due Sept. 18, 2001

ClC (X ) : X ω X } C. (11)

RESIDUALLY FINITE VARIETIES OF NONASSOCIATIVE ALGEBRAS

ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY COURSE NOTES, LECTURE 2: HILBERT S NULLSTELLENSATZ.

10. Finite Lattices and their Congruence Lattices. If memories are all I sing I d rather drive a truck. Ricky Nelson

Properties of Boolean Algebras

(1) A frac = b : a, b A, b 0. We can define addition and multiplication of fractions as we normally would. a b + c d

Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras

Definitions. Notations. Injective, Surjective and Bijective. Divides. Cartesian Product. Relations. Equivalence Relations

SUBLATTICES OF LATTICES OF ORDER-CONVEX SETS, III. THE CASE OF TOTALLY ORDERED SETS

Sets and Motivation for Boolean algebra

arxiv:math/ v1 [math.gm] 21 Jan 2005

Equational Logic. Chapter Syntax Terms and Term Algebras

A CHARACTERIZATION OF LOCALLY FINITE VARIETIES THAT SATISFY A NONTRIVIAL CONGRUENCE IDENTITY

Joseph Muscat Universal Algebras. 1 March 2013

Math 222A W03 D. Congruence relations

2. Prime and Maximal Ideals

TROPICAL SCHEME THEORY

Semilattice Modes II: the amalgamation property

Homework Problems Some Even with Solutions

Abstract Algebra II Groups ( )

Congruence Boolean Lifting Property

Overgroups of Intersections of Maximal Subgroups of the. Symmetric Group. Jeffrey Kuan

INTRODUCING MV-ALGEBRAS. Daniele Mundici

Formal power series rings, inverse limits, and I-adic completions of rings

On the size of Heyting Semi-Lattices and Equationally Linear Heyting Algebras

Embedding theorems for normal divisible residuated lattices

GROUPS OF ORDER p 3 KEITH CONRAD

Residually Finite Varieties of Nonassociative Algebras Keith A. Kearnes a ; Young Jo Kwak a a

Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic

Lattices, closure operators, and Galois connections.

Honors Algebra 4, MATH 371 Winter 2010 Assignment 4 Due Wednesday, February 17 at 08:35

Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic

DEDEKIND S TRANSPOSITION PRINCIPLE

DISTRIBUTIVE, STANDARD AND NEUTRAL ELEMENTS IN TRELLISES. 1. Introduction

II. Products of Groups

1.1 Definition. A monoid is a set M together with a map. 1.3 Definition. A monoid is commutative if x y = y x for all x, y M.

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved.

Lecture 7 Cyclic groups and subgroups

Category theory for computer science. Overall idea

A Discrete Duality Between Nonmonotonic Consequence Relations and Convex Geometries

20 Group Homomorphisms

REPRESENTATION THEORY, LECTURE 0. BASICS

Definitions, Theorems and Exercises. Abstract Algebra Math 332. Ethan D. Bloch

Universal algebra for CSP Lecture 2

2) e = e G G such that if a G 0 =0 G G such that if a G e a = a e = a. 0 +a = a+0 = a.

23.1. Proof of the fundamental theorem of homomorphisms (FTH). We start by recalling the statement of FTH introduced last time.

NOTES ON THE FINITE LATTICE REPRESENTATION PROBLEM

THE LENGTH OF NOETHERIAN MODULES

2.3 The Krull-Schmidt Theorem

ABSTRACT ALGEBRA 1, LECTURES NOTES 5: SUBGROUPS, CONJUGACY, NORMALITY, QUOTIENT GROUPS, AND EXTENSIONS.

A GUIDE FOR MORTALS TO TAME CONGRUENCE THEORY

4.2 Chain Conditions

ARCHIVUM MATHEMATICUM (BRNO) Tomus 48 (2012), M. Sambasiva Rao

ANNIHILATOR IDEALS IN ALMOST SEMILATTICE

On poset Boolean algebras

10. Noether Normalization and Hilbert s Nullstellensatz

GEOMETRIC CONSTRUCTIONS AND ALGEBRAIC FIELD EXTENSIONS

Class Notes on Poset Theory Johan G. Belinfante Revised 1995 May 21

IDEMPOTENT n-permutable VARIETIES

Remarks on categorical equivalence of finite unary algebras

Finite homogeneous and lattice ordered effect algebras

Notes on ordinals and cardinals

Finite pseudocomplemented lattices: The spectra and the Glivenko congruence

Relations on Hypergraphs

Boolean Algebras, Boolean Rings and Stone s Representation Theorem

Rohit Garg Roll no Dr. Deepak Gumber

The Blok-Ferreirim theorem for normal GBL-algebras and its application

The Shape of Congruence Lattices. Keith A. Kearnes Emil W. Kiss

1.2 Posets and Zorn s Lemma

CHAPTER III NORMAL SERIES

Some algebraic properties of. compact topological groups

On a quasi-ordering on Boolean functions

Congruence lattices of finite algebras and intervals in subgroup lattices of finite groups

TEST GROUPS FOR WHITEHEAD GROUPS

AN AXIOMATIC FORMATION THAT IS NOT A VARIETY

MATH 101: ALGEBRA I WORKSHEET, DAY #3. Fill in the blanks as we finish our first pass on prerequisites of group theory.

Notes on p-divisible Groups

CONTINUITY. 1. Continuity 1.1. Preserving limits and colimits. Suppose that F : J C and R: C D are functors. Consider the limit diagrams.

GENERALIZED DIFFERENCE POSETS AND ORTHOALGEBRAS. 0. Introduction

Π 0 1-presentations of algebras

Section III.15. Factor-Group Computations and Simple Groups

Quasi-primal Cornish algebras

Algebraic Geometry: Limits and Colimits

STRONGLY JÓNSSON AND STRONGLY HS MODULES

Lecture 1: Lattice(I)

Tensor Product of modules. MA499 Project II

Math 250A, Fall 2004 Problems due October 5, 2004 The problems this week were from Lang s Algebra, Chapter I.

ON FILTERS IN BE-ALGEBRAS. Biao Long Meng. Received November 30, 2009

Lecture 2. (1) Every P L A (M) has a maximal element, (2) Every ascending chain of submodules stabilizes (ACC).

120A LECTURE OUTLINES

Disjoint n-amalgamation

INTRODUCTION TO THE GROUP THEORY

STABLE MODULE THEORY WITH KERNELS

its image and kernel. A subgroup of a group G is a non-empty subset K of G such that k 1 k 1

Closure operators on sets and algebraic lattices

A Primer on Homological Algebra

CATEGORY THEORY. Cats have been around for 70 years. Eilenberg + Mac Lane =. Cats are about building bridges between different parts of maths.

Is g one-to-one? Is g onto? Why? Solution: g is not one-to-one, since for c A, g(b) = g(c) = c. g is not onto, since a / g(a).

Transcription:

The Correspondence Theorem, which we next prove, shows that the congruence lattice of every homomorphic image of a Σ-algebra is isomorphically embeddable as a special kind of sublattice of the congruence lattice of the algebra itself. To prepare for the theorem we must describe the special kind of sublattices that are involved. Let L = L,, be a lattice. A subset X of L is a lower segment x X implies y X for every y x. An lower segment is an ideal of L if it is closed under join, i.e., x, y X implies x y X. An ideal is obviously a subuniverse of L, infact,ifx Xthen x y X for every y L. A dual ideal of L is an ideal of the dual lattice, i.e., X is a dual ideal if x X implies y X for every y x (X is an upper segment), and X is closed under meet. A dual ideal of L is also a subuniverse. For every a L we define: L(a] ={x L:x a} and L[a) ={x L:a x}. It is easy to see that L(a] is an ideal of L and L[a) is a dual ideal. L[a) andl(a] are subuniverses of L and the corresponding sublattices are denoted by L[a) andl(a], respectively. If L is a complete lattice, then L[a) andl(a] are complete sublattices (exercise). L(a] is called the principal ideal generated by a and L(a] istheprincipal dual ideal generated by a. See Figure 9 L[a) c d d c d a L c d d d c L(a] Figure 9 Forexample,inthechainlattice R,, of real numbers under the natural ordering, the principal ideals are the lower infinite closed intervals (,a] and the principal dual ideals are the upper infinite closed intervals [a, ). Theorem 2.31 (Correspondence Theorem). Let A be a Σ-algebra and γ a congruence on A. Then Co(A/γ) = Co(A)[γ). In particular, the mapping /γ is an isomorphism from Co(A)[γ) to Co(A/γ), where /γ = { a/γ, a /γ : aa }. Proof. For Co[γ) wehave/γ = { γ (a), γ (a) :aa } = γ (), where γ : A A/γ is the natural map. So we must show that γ : Co(A)[γ) Co(A/γ) is a lattice isomorphism. Note that rker( γ )=γ, because γ (a) = γ (a )iffa/γ = a /γ iff a γ a. 38

Let β Co(A/γ). By Lem. 2.30(i) we have γ 1 γ (β) Co(A), i.e., 1 γ (β) Co(A)[γ). γ 1 γ (β) =βby set theory since the mapping a, a a/γ, a /γ from A 2 to (A/γ) 2 is surjective. Let Co(A)[γ), i.e., γ Co(A). Then γ () Co(A/γ) by Lem. 2.30(ii) because the relation kernel of γ,namelyγ, is included in. We claim that 1 γ γ () =. By set theory 1 γ γ(). For the opposite inclusion, suppose a a ( 1 γ γ() ). Then γ (a) γ (a ) ( γ 1 γ γ () ).But γ (a)=a/γ and γ (a )=a/γ, and γ 1 γ γ () γ () by set theory. So a/γ γ() a /γ. Thusthereexista 0,a 0 Asuch that a/γ = a 0/γ and a /γ = a 0 /γ (i.e., a 0 γ a and a 0 γ a )anda 0 a 0.Sinceγ we have a a. Thus 1 γ γ() =. Hence γ :Co(A)[γ) Co(A/γ) is a bijection with inverse 1 γ. implies γ () γ ( ) which in turn implies = 1 γ γ () 1 γ γ ( )=. So γ is strictly order-preserving and hence a lattice isomorphism by Thm. 1.8. As an example we consider the 3-atom Boolean algebra B 3 (or more precisely its lattice reduct). Let h be the endomorphism of B 3 indicated by the arrows in Figure 10 and let be its relation kernel. 39 1 1 γ β γ β c a c b a β γ γ β β γ B 3 b B 2 a β b γ c 0 Figure 10 is indicated on the Hasse diagram for B 3 by labeling the edge between every pair of elements congruent mod with. The two proper congruences β and γ that properly include are also indicated on the diagram. β and γ are respectively he relation kernels of the endomorphisms that push the right front face onto the back left face, and the left front face onto the back right face. The quotient lattice B 3 / is isomorphic to the image of B 3 under h which is the 2-atom Boolean algebra B 2. As guaranteed by the Correspondence Theorem there are just two proper congruences of B 2 corresponding respectively to the β and γ; moreoverco(b 2 )andco(b 3 )[) are isomorphic. See Figure 11. In general, to form the join of a pair of congruences in the lattice of congruences (and also in the lattice of equivalence relations) one has to take arbitrary long alternating relative products of the two congruences (see Theorem 1.17, and the exercise immediately following

40 B2 B3 γ β γ β Co(B 3 )[) B2 Co(B 2 ) Co(B 3 ) B3 Figure 11 it, together with Theorem 2.29). For an important class of algebras only one iteration of the relative product is needed. Theorem 2.32. Let A be a Σ-algebra and let, β Co(A). The following are equivalent. (i) ; β β ;. (ii) ; β = β ;. (iii) ; β Co(A). (iv) ; β = Co(A) β. Proof. Here is the chain of implications we will prove: (i) (ii) = (iv) (iii) = (ii). (i) (ii). The implication from right to left is trivial. Assume ;β β;. Sinceand β are symmetric, = and β = β. Thusβ;= β; =(;β) (β;) = ; β=;β. (i) = (iv). Assume ; β = β ;. By Theorems 1.17 and 2.29 we have Co(A) β = Eq(A) β = ; β ; β ; ; β (;β) n. The claim is that ( ; β) n = ; β for all n ω. Thisistrivialifn=1. (;β) n+1 = ( ; β) n ; β = ; β ; ; β = ; ; β ; β = ; β. ind. hyp. (ii) So Co(A) β = ; β. (iii) (iv). Obvious. (iii) = (ii). Assume ; β Co(A). Then ; β =(;β) = β; =β;. Definition 2.33. A Σ-algebra A has permutable congruence relations if, for all, β Co(A), ; β = β ;. Theorem 2.34. Every group has permutable congruence relations. Proof. Let G = G,, 1,e be a group and, β Co(G). Suppose a, b ;β. Then there is a c G such that acβb. The claim is that a = ac 1 c β ac 1 b cc 1 b = b.

ac 1 β ac 1 and c β b imply (ac 1 )c β (ac 1 )b, anda cand c 1 b c 1 b imply a(c 1 b) c(c 1 b). So a, b β;. Hence ; β β ;. The permutability of congruence relations on groups is a reflection of the fact that normal subuniverses permute under complex product, and hence that the relative product of two normal subuniverses is a normal subuniverse (recall the correspondence between congruences and normal subuniverses). This property of normal subgroups implies the following important property of groups. For all normal subuniverses N, M, andqof a group G, N M implies N(M Q) =M (NQ). This is the modular law for the lattice of normal subuniverses. Definition 2.35. A lattice is modular if it satisfies the quasi-identity (23) x, y ( x y x (y z) y (x z) ). Remarks: (1) The inclusion x (y z) y (x z) always holds if x y because x y and x x z imply x y (x z), and y z y and y z z x z imply y z y (x z). And x y (x z) andy z y (x z) together imply x (y z) y (x z). (2) The quasi-identity (23) is equivalent to the quasi-identity (by custom we omit the explicit quantifier) (x y) x x (y z) y (x z) ), and hence to the identity obtained by substituting x y for x in the right-hand side of this quasi-identity: (x y) (y z) ( ) ( ) (x y) y (x y) z. }{{} y So every distributive lattice is modular, but not conversely. The 3-atom distributive lattice M 3 (see Figure 12) is modular but not conversely. 41 M 3 Figure 12 There is easy way to see that a lattice is modular from its Hasse diagram. Let L be an arbitrary lattice and let x, y, z be arbitrary elements such that x y. If the equation on the right side of (23) fails to hold, it is a easy to see that sub-poset of L with elements x, y, z, x z,y z, y (x z), and x (y z) has the Hasse diagram given in Figure 13. Hence if a lattice fails to satisfy the modular law, then it must contain the lattice in Figure 14 as a sublattice.

42 x z y y (x z) x (y z) z x y z Figure 13 N 5 Figure 14 This is the lattice N 5. It is clearly nonmodular and from the above analysis we see that an arbitrary lattice is nonmodular iff it includes N 5 as a sublattice. This simple characterization of nonmodular lattices is due to Dedekind. It follows immediately from this that D 3 is modular. Dedekind was also the one to show that the lattice of normal subgroups of a a lattice is modular. We will generalize this result to show that any congruence-permutable Σ-algebra has a modular congruence lattice. It turns our that there is more general form of the modular law that holds for the binary relations on any set. Lemma 2.36 (Generalized Modular Law for Relations). Let A be any nonempty set and let Eq(A) and β, γ A A. (24) β implies β ; ( β) ; β = (β ; γ ; β). Proof. Assume β. Thenβ;( γ);β ;;=. Since the inclusion β ;( γ);β β ; γ ; β is obvious, we have the inclusion from left to right on the right-hand side of (24). So it suffices to prove (β ; γ ; β) β ; ( β) ; β. Let x, y (β;γ;β), and let a, b A such that xβaγbβy. Consider the diagram in Figure 15.

43 x β a a γ y β b Figure 15 There are two ways to get from a to b. One is directly along the γ-arrow. The other is back along the reverse of the β-arrow to x and and then along the -arrow to y and then along the reverse of the β-arrow to b. Thisgivesa( β;; β)b.but β;; β ;; =, β since is assumed to be an equivalence relation. So a ( γ) b, and hence xβa( γ)bβy. So x, y β;( γ)β. Theorem 2.37. Let A be a Σ-algebra. If A has permutable congruence relations, then Co(A) is modular. Proof. Let, β, γ Co(A). β ; γ ; β = β ; β ; γ = β ; γ = β. And β ; ( γ); β = β ;β ;( γ)=β;( γ)=β ( γ). Thus, by Lem. 2.36, β implies β ( γ)= (β )γ). 2.7. Simple algebras. A common theme in algebra is to analyze the structure of a complex algebra by attempting to decompose it in some regular way into simpler algebras. The simplest groups from this point of groups are the groups that have no nonisomorphic nontrivial homomorphic images. These are the so-called simple groups and they have natural generalization to arbitrary Σ-algebras. Definition 2.38. A Σ-algebra A is simple if it is nontrivial ( A 2) and CoA = { A, A }. Equivalently, A is simple if it is nontrivial and, for every Σ-algebra B and every epimorphism from A to B, either B =1orh:A =B. Remarks: (1) Let Co(A). By the Correspondence Theorem A/ is simple iff is a coatom of the congruence lattice Co(A), i.e., is a maximal proper congruence. (2) A is simple iff A 2andΘ A (a, b)= A every pair a, b of distinct elements of A. Examples: (1) A group is simple iff it has no normal subuniverses. The alternating group A n is simple for every n 5. (2) The only simple Abelian groups are Z p for each prime p. (3) Every field R, +,,, 0, 1 is simple.

44 (4) The n-atom modular lattice M n is simple for every n 3. See Figure 16. M n a 1 a 2 a 3 a n 1 a n Figure 16 To see this first let = Θ Mn (a i,a j )withi j.1=a i a j a i a i =a i =a i a i a i a j =0. SoΘ Mn (a i,a j )= Mn. Now let = Θ Mn (a i,0) and choose any j i. 1=a i a j 0 a j =a j. So Θ Mn (a j,1) Θ Mn (a i, 0) for all j i. If i, j, k are all distinct, then a j 1 a k, and hence Mn = Θ Mn (a j,a k ) Θ M n (a i,0). Similarly Θ Mn (a i, 1) = Mn. (5) The only simple mono-unary algebras are cycles of prime order (exercise). The proof of the following theorem is also left as an exercise. Theorem 2.39. Let A be a nontrivial Σ-algebra. (i) If A finitely generated as a congruence of A, then there exists a simple Σ-algebra B such that B A. (ii) If Σ is finite (i.e., it has only a finite number of operation symbols) and A is finitely generated as a subuniverse of itself, then there exists a simple Σ-algebra B such that B A. Under the hypotheses of (ii) it can be shown that A is finitely generated. As a corollary of this theorem every finite nontrivial Σ-algebra has a simple homomorphic image. Lemma 2.40. Let A be a nontrivial Σ-algebra. If A is nonsimple, then A has a nonsimple subalgebra that is generated by at most four elements. Proof. Suppose A is nonsimple. Then there exist a, b A, a b, such that Θ A (a, b) A. Let c, d A such that c, d / Θ A (a, b), and let B = Sg A {(a, b, c, d} and = Θ A (a, b) B 2. Co(B), a, b,and c, d.so B, B. Hence B is not simple. As an immediate consequence of the lemma we have: Theorem 2.41. If every finitely generated subalgebra of a Σ-algebra A is simple, then so is A. Let Σ be a multi-sorted signature with sort set S, andletaand B be Σ-algebras. A homomorphism h for A to B is a S-sorted set h s : s S such that h s : A s B s for every s S and such that, for every σ Σ with type s 1,...,s n s and all a 1,...,a n A s1 A sn, ( h s σ A (a1,...,a n ) ) =σ B( h s1 (a 1 ),...,h sn (a n ) ).

A congruence on A is an S-sorted set s : s S such that s Eq(A s )foreach s S,andforeveryσ Σwith type s 1,...,s n s and all a 1,...,a n, b 1,...,b n A s1 A sn, i n(a i si b i )= σ A (a 1,...,a n ) s σ A (b 1,...,b n ). 45