Microeconomic Theory III Spring 2009

Similar documents
6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 7: Supermodular Games

Supermodular Games. Ichiro Obara. February 6, 2012 UCLA. Obara (UCLA) Supermodular Games February 6, / 21

1 Lattices and Tarski s Theorem

Short course on Comparative Statics and Comparative Information

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 8: Supermodular and Potential Games

Recitation 7: Uncertainty. Xincheng Qiu

Choice under Uncertainty

Course Handouts ECON 4161/8001 MICROECONOMIC ANALYSIS. Jan Werner. University of Minnesota

Consumer theory Topics in consumer theory. Microeconomics. Joana Pais. Fall Joana Pais

100 if α=red 0 if α=red f A,r = f A,b =

Advanced Microeconomic Analysis Solutions to Homework #2

Iterative Weak Dominance and Interval-Dominance Supermodular Games

On strategic complementarity conditions in Bertrand oligopoly

The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics Online

SUPPLEMENT TO THE COMPARATIVE STATICS OF CONSTRAINED OPTIMIZATION PROBLEMS (Econometrica, Vol. 75, No. 2, March 2007, )

Von Neumann Morgenstern Expected Utility. I. Introduction, Definitions, and Applications. Decision Theory Spring 2014

The Cake-Eating problem: Non-linear sharing rules

DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES

Microeconomic Theory I Midterm

Volume 30, Issue 3. Monotone comparative statics with separable objective functions. Christian Ewerhart University of Zurich

Mathematical Economics - PhD in Economics

Monotone comparative statics Finite Data and GARP

Lecture 6: Recursive Preferences

Course Handouts ECON 8101 MICROECONOMIC THEORY. Jan Werner. University of Minnesota

1: PROBABILITY REVIEW

Notes on Supermodularity and Increasing Differences. in Expected Utility

EC9A0: Pre-sessional Advanced Mathematics Course. Lecture Notes: Unconstrained Optimisation By Pablo F. Beker 1

Order on Types based on Monotone Comparative Statics

Global Games I. Mehdi Shadmehr Department of Economics University of Miami. August 25, 2011

Acta Mathematica Academiae Paedagogicae Nyíregyháziensis 21 (2005), ISSN

Measuring the informativeness of economic actions and. market prices 1. Philip Bond, University of Washington. September 2014

Mean-Scale Indifference Curves. For gambles with small variance, a second order Taylor s series expansion

Iterative Weak Dominance and Interval-Dominance Supermodular Games

Substitute Valuations with Divisible Goods

Advanced Microeconomics

The Interdisciplinary Center, Herzliya School of Economics Advanced Microeconomics Fall Bargaining The Axiomatic Approach

LECTURE 2. Convexity and related notions. Last time: mutual information: definitions and properties. Lecture outline

1 Uncertainty. These notes correspond to chapter 2 of Jehle and Reny.

Lecture Slides - Part 1

Iterative Weak Dominance and Interval-Dominance Supermodular Games

Fundamentals in Optimal Investments. Lecture I

The Le Chatelier Principle in lattices. Abstract

This corresponds to a within-subject experiment: see same subject make choices from different menus.

Robust Comparative Statics in Large Static Games

Directional Monotone Comparative Statics

Simultaneous Choice Models: The Sandwich Approach to Nonparametric Analysis

14.12 Game Theory Lecture Notes Theory of Choice

Thus far, we ve made four key assumptions that have greatly simplified our analysis:

Directional Monotone Comparative Statics

Chapter 2. Decision Making under Risk. 2.1 Consequences and Lotteries

Preferences and Utility

A Characterization of Strategic Complementarities

Supermodularity and risk aversion

Notes on Recursive Utility. Consider the setting of consumption in infinite time under uncertainty as in

On the (non-)lattice structure of the equilibrium set in games with strategic substitutes

Characterizing Stability Properties in Games with Strategic Substitutes

7) Important properties of functions: homogeneity, homotheticity, convexity and quasi-convexity

Profit Maximization and Supermodular Technology

Direct Complementarity

Robust comparative statics in large static games

LECTURE 4 LECTURE OUTLINE

Microeconomic Theory (501b) Problem Set 10. Auctions and Moral Hazard Suggested Solution: Tibor Heumann

MIT Spring 2016

Bayesian Persuasion Online Appendix

On the existence of monotone selections

Toward a Systematic Approach to the Economic Effects of Risk: Characterizing Utility Functions

Almost essential: Consumption and Uncertainty Probability Distributions MICROECONOMICS

Homework #6 (10/18/2017)

THE VALUE OF INFORMATION AND DISPERSION

Substitute Valuations, Auctions, and Equilibrium with Discrete Goods

DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES

Economics 2010c: Lectures 9-10 Bellman Equation in Continuous Time

Robert Wilson (1977), A Bidding Model of Perfect Competition, Review of Economic

Problem Set 4 - Solution Hints

working paper department technology massachusetts of economics institute of 50 memorial drive Cambridge, mass

Structural Properties of Utility Functions Walrasian Demand

Economics 201B Economic Theory (Spring 2017) Bargaining. Topics: the axiomatic approach (OR 15) and the strategic approach (OR 7).

Winter Lecture 10. Convexity and Concavity

Stochastic Optimization with Risk Measures

The Non-Existence of Representative Agents

Robust Comparative Statics for Non-monotone Shocks in Large Aggregative Games

Lecture 4: Optimization. Maximizing a function of a single variable

Birgit Heydenreich, Rudolf Müller, Marc Uetz, Rakesh Vohra. Characterization of Revenue Equivalence RM/07/017. JEL code: D71, C72, C69

Economics of disagreement. financial intuition for the Rényi divergence

ECON 626: Applied Microeconomics. Lecture 11: Maximum Likelihood

Robust Comparative Statics of Non-monotone Shocks in Large Aggregative Games

1 Overview. 2 Multilinear Extension. AM 221: Advanced Optimization Spring 2016

Static Problem Set 2 Solutions

Microeconomic Theory I Midterm October 2017

Mechanism Design with Correlated Types

Risk Aversion and Risk Vulnerability in the Continuous and Discrete Case

Monetary Risk Measures and Generalized Prices Relevant to Set-Valued Risk Measures

Alp Simsek (MIT) Recitation Notes: 1. Gorman s Aggregation Th eorem2. Normative Representative November 9, Household Theorem / 16

Characterizing stability properties in games with strategic substitutes

market prices 1 Philip Bond, University of Washington July 2015

Handout 4: Some Applications of Linear Programming

Economics 401 Sample questions 2

Sensitivity analysis of the expected utility maximization problem with respect to model perturbations

THE UTILITY PREMIUM. Louis Eeckhoudt, Catholic Universities of Mons and Lille Research Associate CORE

Microeconomics III Final Exam Answers 3/22/11 Muhamet Yildiz

Transcription:

MIT OpenCourseWare http://ocw.mit.edu 14.123 Microeconomic Theory III Spring 2009 For information about citing these materials or our Terms of Use, visit: http://ocw.mit.edu/terms.

MIT 14.123 (2009) by Peter Eso Lecture 5: Background Risk 1. Calibrating Risk Aversion 2. Refresher on (Log-)Supermodularity 3. Background Risk & DARA Solve: Problem set handed out in class.

Calibrating Risk Aversion Suppose u is CRRA(ρ) = x 1-ρ /(1-ρ), and the agent s initial wealth is w = $100,000. Consider a gamble ± $X with 50-50% chance. X=30,000; ρ = 40: Risk premium is about $28,700 too high. X=30,000; ρ = 2: Risk premium is about $9,000 OK? X=500; ρ = 2: Risk premium is about $2.5 too low? It may be difficult to come up with reasonable parameters that match introspection and real-life evidence. Luckily, the Equity Premium Puzzle fizzled in 2008! Today: Background risk in real life (not present in bare-bones examples) may cause some of the apparent puzzles. Decisionmaking with risky initial wealth is non-trivial & interesting. 14.123 Lecture 5, Page 2

Lattices DEF: For any partially ordered set (X, ) and all x, y X define The join x y = inf{z X : z x, z y}; The meet x y = sup{z X : x z, y z}. DEF: (X, ) is a lattice if x, y X: x y X, x y X. DEF: Given (X, ), for S, Z X, let S Z ( S weakly exceeds Z in the strong set order ) if {x S, y Z} {x y S, x y Z}. THM: (X, ) is a lattice iff X X. (trivial) DEF: (X, ) is a complete lattice if S X, inf S X, sup S X. DEF: L is a sublattice of a partially ordered set (X, ) if L is a subset of X and it is a lattice. 14.123 Lecture 5, Page 3

Sublattices of n Example: L = n, is the usual (coordinate-wise) order on vectors; x y is coordinate-wise maximum, x y coordinate-wise minimum. Sublattices of 2 : Not sublattices of 2 : 14.123 Lecture 5, Page 4

(Log-)Supermodularity DEF: A function f: X is supermodular if for all x, y X, f(x y) + f(x y) f(x) + f(y). DEF: A function f: X + is log-supermodular if for all x, y X, f(x y) f(x y) f(x) f(y). That is, h is log-spm if log(f) is supermodular. THM (Topkis): A twice-differentiable f: n is supermodular iff for all i,j = 1,,n, i j, and x n, 2 f(x)/ x i x j 0. Examples: If X =, then f is supermodular, as well as log-spm. If X = n and f(x) f( x n ), then f is log-spm iff log-convex. (Log-)supermodularity captures complementarity. 14.123 Lecture 5, Page 5

Single Crossing DEF: Given lattice (X, ), function f: X, is quasi-supermodular if x,y X, f(x) f(x y) (>) 0 implies f(x y) f(y) (>) 0. THM: If a function is supermodular or log-spm then it is quasi-spm. DEF: g: is single-crossing if t t: g(t) (>) 0 g(t ) (>) 0. DEF: f: satisfies single-crossing differences if z > z, g(t) f(z,t) f(z,t) is single-crossing. THM: If (X, ) is a sublattice of n, then quasi-supermodularity single-crossing differences in every pair of coordinates. Prove both Theorems in Recitation. Single-crossing conditions are used in a variety of settings. 14.123 Lecture 5, Page 6

Monotonic Comparative Statics DEF: Let B,B X. B B if b B, b B : b b B and b b B. THM (Topkis): Let (X, ) be a partially ordered set, f: X a supermodular function, B a sublattice of (X, ), and t t. Then, x * (t,b) argmax { f(x,t) x B } is sublattice of (X, ) that is increasing ( isotone ) in t and B. THM (Milgrom & Shannon): Let (X, ) be a sublattice of n and T. If B is a sublattice of X and f: X T is q-spm, then x * (t,b) argmax { f(x,t) x B } is increasing in B and t. Prove the latter Theorem in Recitation. 14.123 Lecture 5, Page 7

Instances of Log-Supermodularity In mathematical statistics: Total Positivity of Order 2 (Karlin). (Re-)discovered and first applied in economics by Ian Jewitt, Paul Milgrom, and Xavier Vives (separately) in the 80 s. The price-elasticity of demand, P D P (P,t)/D(P,t), is weakly increasing in t iff the demand function, D(P,t), is log-spm. ln(d(p,t))/ P = D P (P,t)/D(P,t). By Topkis Thm: D(P,t), is log-spm iff D P (P,t)/D(P,t) in t. A vector of random variables is affiliated (a notion of positively correlated used in auction theory) iff their joint pdf is log-spm. Definition of affiliated pdf f : f(z z ) f(z z ) f(z) f(z ). Non-negative correlation conditional on any outcome-pair. 14.123 Lecture 5, Page 8

Instances of Log-Supermodularity A parametrized family of payoff-distributions F(x,t) is increasing in t in the MPR sense iff F is log-spm. F(x,1) MPR-dominates F(x,0) iff F(x,1)/F(x,0) in x. A parametrized family of payoff-distributions F(x,t) is increasing in t in the MLR sense iff F is log-spm. F(x,1) MLR-dominates F(x,0) iff F (x,1)/f (x,0) in x. A Bernoulli-vNM utility index u is DARA iff u (w+z) is log-spm in wealth (w) and the realization of the prize (z). u is log-spm iff log-convex; ln(u (x))/ x = u (x)/u (x). Agent 1 is more risk averse than 2 if u i (w) is log-spm in (w,i). log-spm: ln(u i (w))/ w = u i (w)/u i (w) is increasing in i. 14.123 Lecture 5, Page 9

A Theorem from Statistics Let X = X 1 X n and Z = Z 1 Z m be sublattices of n and m with X i and Z j for all i and j. Let T. Suppose u: X Z + is a bounded utility function and f: Z T + is a probability density function on Z for all t T. Define THM U(x,t) = u(x,z) f(z,t)dz. (Karlin): If u and f are log-spm, then U is log-spm. Remark: Products of log-spm functions are clearly log-spm, but arbitrary sums of log-spm functions are not log-spm. 14.123 Lecture 5, Page 10

MCS in Decision Theory THM: If u and f are log-spm, then t T and sublattice B X, x * (t,b) argmax {U(x,t) x B} is increasing in t and B. That is, for all t t and sublattices B B (in strong set order), we have x * (t,b ) x * (t,b). Combine Karlin s Thm (previous slide) with Milgrom & Shannon s Thm (slide #6). 14.123 Lecture 5, Page 11

Problem with Background Risk Agent has vnm utility u for wealth, strictly increasing & concave. The agent is exposed to uninsurable risk: Her initial wealth is ~ ~ w 0 + w, where w 0 is a scalar, w is a random variable. ~ ~ Can invest in asset with random net return x, independent of w. ~ ~ Problem: Invest α to maximize E[u(w 0 +w+αx)]. ~ ~ Define v(z) = E[u(z+w)]. Problem max α E[v(w 0 +αx)]. Are good properties of u inherited by v? Clearly, v > 0, v < 0. (Differentiation goes through E.) If u is DARA, is v DARA as well? ~ If u is DARA & E[w] 0, then is v more risk averse than u? 14.123 Lecture 5, Page 12

DARA with Background Risk THM: If u: is a DARA utility and f a pdf on Z, then is a DARA utility function. v(x) Z u(x+z) f(z)dz, x, u is DARA u (x 1 +x 2 +z) is log-spm in (x 1,x 2,z). f is log-spm because Z is one-dimensional. Let v (x 1 +x 2 ) Z u (x 1 +x 2 +z) f(z)dz. By Karlin s Thm, v (x 1 +x 2 ) is log-spm in (x 1,x 2 ), hence v is DARA. Similar theorems are not true if u is not DARA. 14.123 Lecture 5, Page 13

DARA with Background Risk THM: Given utility u: and pdf f with zf(z)dz 0, if r A (x,u) is decreasing and convex in x, then v(x) Z u(x+z) f(z)dz, x, is more risk averse than u. To show: Z u (x+z) f(z)dz/ Z u (x+z) f(z)dz r A (x,u), that is, Z r A (x+z,u) u (x+z) f(z)dz r A (x,u) Z u (x+z) f(z)dz. Left-hand side exceeds Z r A (x+z,u) f(z)dz Z u (x+z) f(z)dz because both r A and u are decreasing in z. (Cov(r A,u ) 0.) Z r A (x+z,u) f(z)dz r A (x+e[z],u) by convexity of r A, and r A (x+e[z],u) r A (x,u) because E[z] 0 and DARA. Why assume E[z] 0? Otherwise background risk could increase wealth, possibly reducing risk aversion (DARA). 14.123 Lecture 5, Page 14