Takeuti s finitism and his proof of the consistency of arithmetic

Similar documents
Hilbert and the concept of axiom

PROOF-THEORETIC REDUCTION AS A PHILOSOPHER S TOOL

Kant and Finitism. Crossing Worlds: Mathematical logisc, philosophy, art: For Juliette Kennedy. Bill Tait. 4 June 2016

Class 15: Hilbert and Gödel

KRIPKE S THEORY OF TRUTH 1. INTRODUCTION

Proving Completeness for Nested Sequent Calculi 1

An Intuitively Complete Analysis of Gödel s Incompleteness

Goodstein s theorem revisited

Between proof theory and model theory Three traditions in logic: Syntactic (formal deduction)

Creative Objectivism, a powerful alternative to Constructivism

Takeuti s Well-Ordering Proof: Finitistically Fine?

Lecture 14 Rosser s Theorem, the length of proofs, Robinson s Arithmetic, and Church s theorem. Michael Beeson

Cogito ergo sum non machina!

INCOMPLETENESS I by Harvey M. Friedman Distinguished University Professor Mathematics, Philosophy, Computer Science Ohio State University Invitation

Introduction to Logic and Axiomatic Set Theory

Gödel s Programm and Ultimate L

How Philosophy Impacts on Mathematics

Kaplan s Paradox and Epistemically Possible Worlds

Axiomatic set theory. Chapter Why axiomatic set theory?

Hilbert s Program Then and Now

35 Chapter CHAPTER 4: Mathematical Proof

Real Analysis Prof. S.H. Kulkarni Department of Mathematics Indian Institute of Technology, Madras. Lecture - 13 Conditional Convergence

Russell s logicism. Jeff Speaks. September 26, 2007

The roots of computability theory. September 5, 2016

Completeness Theorems and λ-calculus

Peano Arithmetic. CSC 438F/2404F Notes (S. Cook) Fall, Goals Now

Introduction to Metalogic

CONSTRUCTION OF THE REAL NUMBERS.

Equivalent Forms of the Axiom of Infinity

Gödel and Formalism freeness. Juliette Kennedy

Gödel s Incompleteness Theorems

Leibniz and Cantor on the Actual Infinite

DECISIONS UNDER UNCERTAINTY

MAGIC Set theory. lecture 1

Math 300: Foundations of Higher Mathematics Northwestern University, Lecture Notes

To Infinity and Beyond

Semantic methods in proof theory. Jeremy Avigad. Department of Philosophy. Carnegie Mellon University.

Almost von Neumann, Definitely Gödel: The Second Incompleteness Theorem s Early Story

chapter 12 MORE MATRIX ALGEBRA 12.1 Systems of Linear Equations GOALS

What are the recursion theoretic properties of a set of axioms? Understanding a paper by William Craig Armando B. Matos

Abstract and Variable Sets in Category Theory 1

A Semantics of Evidence for Classical Arithmetic

Victoria Gitman and Thomas Johnstone. New York City College of Technology, CUNY

My thanks to the RESOLVE community for inviting me to speak here.

Philosophy of Mathematics Intuitionism

Axioms as definitions: revisiting Hilbert

SOME TRANSFINITE INDUCTION DEDUCTIONS

Church s undecidability result

TRUTH-THEORIES FOR FRAGMENTS OF PA

Hilbert s significance for the philosophy of mathematics (1922) Paul Bernays

MAGIC Set theory. lecture 2

Proof Theory and Subsystems of Second-Order Arithmetic

Products, Relations and Functions

THE CONSTRUCTIVE SECOND NUMBER CLASS*

This is logically equivalent to the conjunction of the positive assertion Minimal Arithmetic and Representability

Thomas Jech. The Pennsylvania State University. Until the 19th century the study of the innite was an exclusive domain of

Well-foundedness of Countable Ordinals and the Hydra Game

SOCRATES DID IT BEFORE GÖDEL

Direct Proof and Counterexample I:Introduction

Truth, Subderivations and the Liar. Why Should I Care about the Liar Sentence? Uses of the Truth Concept - (i) Disquotation.

Direct Proof and Counterexample I:Introduction. Copyright Cengage Learning. All rights reserved.

Seminaar Abstrakte Wiskunde Seminar in Abstract Mathematics Lecture notes in progress (27 March 2010)

Review: Stephen G. Simpson (1999) Subsystems of Second-Order Arithmetic (Springer)

Classical Propositional Logic

1. Introduction to commutative rings and fields

LECTURE 10: REVIEW OF POWER SERIES. 1. Motivation

The Syntax of First-Order Logic. Marc Hoyois

Notes on ordinals and cardinals

An Intuitive Introduction to Motivic Homotopy Theory Vladimir Voevodsky

NONSTANDARD MODELS AND KRIPKE S PROOF OF THE GÖDEL THEOREM

The concept of axiom in Hilbert s thought

Andrew Schumann, Roman Murawski Is the Polish Logic One of the Best Traditions Still? Studia Humana nr 3/4, 78-82

CONSERVATION by Harvey M. Friedman September 24, 1999

THE MATHEMATICAL UNIVERSE IN A NUTSHELL

The Independence of Peano's Fourth Axiom from. Martin-Lof's Type Theory without Universes. Jan M. Smith. Department of Computer Science

Throwing Darts, Time, and the Infinite

Absolutely ordinal definable sets

Chapter One. The Real Number System

Hilbert s problems, Gödel, and the limits of computation

König s Lemma and Kleene Tree

The Calculus of Inductive Constructions

Modern Algebra Prof. Manindra Agrawal Department of Computer Science and Engineering Indian Institute of Technology, Kanpur

On some Metatheorems about FOL

2. Introduction to commutative rings (continued)

Induction 1 = 1(1+1) = 2(2+1) = 3(3+1) 2

Connectedness. Proposition 2.2. The following are equivalent for a topological space (X, T ).

FACTORIZATION AND THE PRIMES

Countability. 1 Motivation. 2 Counting

This section will take the very naive point of view that a set is a collection of objects, the collection being regarded as a single object.

DR.RUPNATHJI( DR.RUPAK NATH )

INTRODUCTION TO CARDINAL NUMBERS

1. Introduction to commutative rings and fields

CHAPTER 11. Introduction to Intuitionistic Logic

Chapter 2 Classical Probability Theories

M.Burgin Department of Mathematics University of California, Los Angeles Los Angeles, CA 90095

Mathematics-I Prof. S.K. Ray Department of Mathematics and Statistics Indian Institute of Technology, Kanpur. Lecture 1 Real Numbers

The Limit of Humanly Knowable Mathematical Truth

Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (1666)

arxiv:math/ v2 [math.gn] 23 Sep 2003

The constructible universe

Transcription:

Takeuti s finitism and his proof of the consistency of arithmetic Andrew Arana Université Paris 1 Panthéon-Sorbonne Department of Philosophy, IHPST September 6, 2018

Finitist proofs of consistency

Let s outline Gentzen s proof of the consistency of PA. He designs a system of ordinals and an ordering of these ordinals that are each concrete and thus finitistically acceptable. This ordering has type ɛ 0. Proofs in PA are assigned these ordinals according to the rules of inference used. 1 31

Gentzen gives a procedure for reducing proofs so that each proof of inconsistency gets reduced to another proof of inconsistency with a smaller ordinal. If there is a proof of inconsistency, this procedure generates an infinitely decreasing sequence of such ordinals. By the well-ordering of the ordering of type ɛ 0, such a sequence is impossible. Thus there is no proof of inconsistency in PA. 2 31

Tarski, Contribution to the discussion of P. Bernays Zur Beurteilung der Situation in der beweistheoretischen Forschung (1954) Gentzen s proof of the consistency of arithmetic is undoubtedly a very interesting metamathematical result, which may prove very stimulating and fruitful. I cannot say, however, that the consistency of arithmetic is now much more evident to me (at any rate, perhaps, to use the terminology of the differential calculus more evident than by an epsilon) than it was before the proof was given. 3 31

Girard, The Blind Spot (2011) Concerning Gentzen s second consistency proof, André Weil said that Gentzen proved the consistency of arithmetic, i.e., induction up to the ordinal ω, by means of induction up to ɛ 0, the venom being that ɛ 0 is much larger than ω. 4 31

Hilbert & Bernays, Grundlagen der Mathematik, Vol. 1 (1934) Our treatment of the basics of number theory and algebra was meant to demonstrate how to apply and implement direct contentual inference that takes place in thought experiments [Gedanken-Experimenten] on intuitively conceived objects and is free of axiomatic assumptions. Let us call this kind of inference finitist inference for short, and likewise the methodological attitude underlying this kind of inference as the finitist attitude or the finitist standpoint.... With each use of the word finitist, we convey the idea that the relevant consideration, assertion, or definition is confined to objects that are conceivable in principle, and processes that can be effectively executed in principle, and thus it remains within the scope of a concrete treatment. 5 31

Hilbert, Die Grundlagen Der Elementaren Zahlentheorie (1931) This is the fundamental mode of thought that I hold to be necessary for mathematics and for all scientific thought, understanding, and communication, and without which mental activity is not possible at all. Tait, Finitism (1981) [Finitistically acceptable reasoning] is a minimal kind of reasoning presupposed by all non-trivial mathematical reasoning about numbers. 6 31

Hilbert & Bernays, Grundlagen der Mathematik, Vol. 1 (1934) Regarding this goal [of proving consistency], I would like to emphasize that an opinion, which had emerged intermittently namely that some more recent results of Gödel would imply the infeasibility of my proof theory has turned out to be erroneous. Indeed, that result shows only that for more advanced consistency proofs the finitist standpoint has to be exploited in a manner that is sharper [schärferen] than the one required for the treatment of the elementary formulations. 7 31

In Gentzen s proof every step except the well-ordering of the ordering of type ɛ 0 can be effected in primitive recursive arithmetic (generally accepted to be finitistically acceptable). In particular, it needs to be proved that every strictly decreasing computable sequence of ordinals in this ordering is finite. This is the part of the proof that needs to be justified from the finitist standpoint. 8 31

Hilbert & Bernays, Grundlagen der Mathematik, Vol. 2 (1939) The question arises as to whether finitary methods are in a position to exceed the domain of inferences formalizable in Z µ. This question is admittedly, as so formulated, not precise; because we have introduced the expression finitary not as a sharply delimited endpoint, but rather as a designation of a methodological guideline, which would enable us to recognize certain kinds of concept formation and certain kinds of inferences as definitely finitary and others as definitely not finitary, but which however delivers no exact separating line between those which satisfy the demands of the finitary method and those which do not. 9 31

Takeuti s argument

Takeuti, Consistency Proofs and Ordinals (1975) Gödel s incompleteness theorem has changed the meaning of Hilbert s program completely. Because of Gödel s result consistency proofs now require a method that is finite (or constructive) but which is nevertheless very strong when formalized. People think this is impossible or at least unlikely and extremely difficult. The situation is somewhat similar to that of finding a new axiom that carries conviction and decides the continuum hypothesis. The claim about decreasing sequences of ordinals has the provability strength of the consistency of PA, but is still, Takeuti alleges, finitistically acceptable. 10 31

Takeuti calls an ordinal µ accessible if it has been finitistically proved that every strictly decreasing sequence starting with µ is finite. This is the step in Gentzen s proof that needs to be finitistically justified: that every ordinal up to ɛ 0 is accessible. Takeuti observes that it is clear that every natural number is accessible. The crux of his argument is to extend this observation to infinite ordinals. 11 31

Firstly, he argues that ω + ω is accessible: the first term µ 0 of any decreasing sequence from ω + ω is either of the form n or ω + n. If the former, then we re done. If the latter, then consider the sequence µ n+1 < < µ 2 < µ 1 < µ 0. This sequence has length n + 2 and thus µ n+1 must be a natural number. Such reasoning will also show that ordinals to ω ω are accessible. For ordinals written in Cantor normal form up to ɛ 0, Takeuti explains how to continue this reasoning. 12 31

It is crucial that each of these steps can be shown by a finitistically acceptable argument. That is, they must be effectively executed in principle... within the scope of a concrete treatment. We are meant to see this by Gedankenexperimenten. But are these steps really thinkable in an effective, concrete way? This must be confirmed in order to accept Takeuti s proof of the consistency of arithmetic as finitary. 13 31

Challenges to Takeuti

The system of ordinal notations used here, Kleene s O, is known to be a Π 1 1 set. Can we finitistically prove things about terminating decreasing sequences in O in light of this set s complexity? Rathjen (2014) has noted that the accessibility of ɛ 0 used in Takeuti s proof of consistency is only Π 0 2. 14 31

Takeuti, Axioms of Arithmetic and Consistency (Sugaku Seminar, 1994) There is not much reason to oppose this idea by claiming that the notion that all decreasing sequences terminate within finite steps is a Π 1 1 notion in Kleene s hierarchy. What is important is not which hierarchy the notion belongs to, but how clear it is. Takeuti, Consistency Proofs and Ordinals (1975) This proof is very clear and transparent if one is familiar with the primitive recursive structure of the ordinals less than ɛ 0. 15 31

Gentzen, Die Widerspruchsfreiheit der reinen Zahlentheorie (1936) We might, for example, visualize the initial cases with the characteristics 1, 2, 3 in detail. As the characteristic grows, nothing new is basically added; the method of progression always remains the same. It must of course be admitted that the complexity of the multiply-nested infinities which must be run through grows considerably; this running through must always be regarded as potential... The difficulty lies in the fact that although the precise finitist sense of the running through of the ρ-numbers is reasonably perspicuous in the initial cases, it becomes of such great complexity in the general case that it is only remotely visualizable... 16 31

Gödel, On an extension of finitary mathematics which has not yet been used (1972) The situation may be roughly described as follows: Recursion for ɛ 0 could be proved finitarily if the consistency of number theory could. On the other hand the validity of this recursion can certainly not be made immediately evident, as is possible, for example in the case of ω 2. That is to say, one cannot grasp at one glance the various structural possibilities which exist for decreasing sequences, and there exists, therefore, no immediate concrete knowledge of the termination of every such sequence. But furthermore such concrete knowledge (in Hilbert s sense) cannot be realized either by a stepwise transition from smaller to larger ordinal numbers, because the concretely evident steps, such as α α 2, are so small that they would have to be repeated ɛ 0 times in order to reach ɛ 0. 17 31

Gödel, Über eine bisher noch nicht benützte Erweiterung des finite Standpunktes (1958) It cannot be determined out of hand whether the need for abstract notions is due merely to the practical impossibility of our intuitively imagining states of affairs that are all too complex from the combinatorial point of view or whether there are theoretical reasons for it. 18 31

This practical problem means that some knowers may be able to have immediate concrete knowledge of the termination of some sequences, but not of others ; while other knowers may be yet more capable of such intuitions. One person might intuit accessibility up to, say, ω 2 ; another to ω ω ; another to ɛ 0. If this is right, then Takeuti s sharpening of finitism loses the quality stressed by Hilbert, that finitary reasoning is the core type of reasoning common to all scientific knowledge, and hence knowers. 19 31

But here we recognize, as did Gödel, that the problem arises from identifying intuition and visualizability. Letter of Gödel to Bernays, 25 July 1969 Hilbert s finitism (through the requirement of being intuitive [Anschaulichkeit]) has a quite unnatural boundary. This identification is a remnant of the classical Kantian understanding of intuition as (something like) visualization, which is to be contrasted with the abstract apprehension characteristic of logical knowledge. 20 31

New horizons open when we recognize that Takeuti came from a considerably different background from Hilbert, Bernays, and Gödel. He was a Japanese thinker with relatively little access to Western texts until he came to the USA. In fact, questions about knowledge from finite and infinite standpoints, of the concrete and the abstract, of the intuitive and the logical, were already being studied in Japan in the 1910s, before Hilbert s seminal work on these questions that gave birth to proof theory. There is good reason to think that Takeuti was knowledgable about this work. 21 31

Takeuti as a Japanese philosopher

Takeuti, Proof theory and set theory (1985) Foundational problems begin when we realize that we cannot examine infinitely many objects one by one. However, it is very easy for us to imagine an infinite mind which can do so. Actually by working in mathematics we have been building up our intuition on what an infinite mind can do. An infinite mind must be able to operate on infinitely many objects as freely as we operate on finitely many objects. Thus it can unite members of a set D to form arbitrary subsets of D. It can examine each of these subsets and so on. Takeuti, About mathematics (Japanese, 1972) Speaking more clearly, modern mathematics or modern set theory is our hypothesis or conjecture about infinite mind. 22 31

Takeuti explains that testing this conjecture leads to three problems for the foundations of mathematics. 1. To formulate the function of infinite mind. 2. To justify our intuition of the world of infinite mind using only our finite mind. 3. To formulate the function of finite mind. 23 31

Takeuti, Proof theory and set theory (1985) A long time ago when I discussed my standpoint with Gödel, I used different terminology. It was Gödel who suggested the phrase infinite mind, and infinite mind became standard terminology in our discussions. While Takeuti does not say what terminology he previously used, such notions had been studied in Japan in the early twentieth century. Takeuti mentions some familiarity with the works of Suetsuna, a number theorist who wrote on philosophy of mathematics and later on Kegon Buddhism; Suetsuna pursued a kind of finitism. Suetsuna was heavily influenced by Nishida, the foremost Japanese philosopher of the twentieth century. 24 31

In work starting in the 1910s, Nishida contrasted a logical standpoint from a mathematical standpoint, where the latter involves concrete intuitions of wholes, rather than the parts that arise from logical analysis. He held that we cannot intuit the infinite as a whole, since we are finite. But we can self-reflect: we can, in intuition, make ourselves the object of our thought, and then make the content of that intuition into a further object, in intuition; and so on. 25 31

26 31

Following Royce, Nishida elaborated on this Dedekindian construction, talking of drawing a map of where you are now, point by point, including the map you are drawing. Nishida called this capacity self-awareness [jikaku 自覚 ] and maintained that the resulting object is the true sense of infinity ( Understanding in logic and in mathematics, 1912). 27 31

Takeuti, Proof theory and set theory (1985) We believe that the set universe is a growing universe i.e., the creation of sets by the infinite mind is always in process and never finished. The picture that the infinite mind is endlessly creating sets starting with the empty set provides us with some reason to justify the axioms of set theory. Moreover the infinite mind, as a mind, reflects on what he is doing. So he can imagine the stage when he finishes his creation and starts it again after that. 28 31

Note the following passage of the Avatamsaka-sutra, a key text in the Kegon Buddhism of Nishida: The Buddha is also like the mind, and living beings are like the Buddha. It must be known that the Buddha and the mind are, in their essence, inexhaustible. If one understands that the activity of the mind creates the worlds everywhere, he will see the Buddha, and understand the real nature of the Buddha. 29 31

Takeuti, Proof theory and set theory (1985) Gentzen s proof is an assurance from the finite standpoint of the truth as conceived by the infinite mind. The philosophical upshot of this reading is that we should try to understand Takeuti s finitism in the light of Japanese thought as much as the usual writing on finitism that draws on Kant as understood by Hilbert & Bernays, for example. 30 31

A mathematical upshot of this reading is that Takeuti s finitism, more than Hilbert & Bernays, can provide for a hierarchy of finitisms. We can stratify these new finitisms by quantifier complexity. But not just any quantification, but only on ordinals, which have a nice structure (the "true" structure of infinity) and which do not require checking through a disorderly set like the set of all informal infinitary proofs. At least this is an idea. 31 / 31