MAC-CPTM Situations Project

Similar documents
Prompt. Commentary. Mathematical Foci

MAC-CPTM Situations Project

Discrete Mathematics for CS Spring 2008 David Wagner Note 4

Mathematical Induction

Situation: Summing the Natural Numbers

Discrete Mathematics and Probability Theory Spring 2014 Anant Sahai Note 3

MAC-CPTM Situations Project. Situations 24: Absolute Value Equations and Inequalities

MAC-CPTM Situations Project

Mathematical Induction. Section 5.1

MAC-CPTM Situations Project

Situation 29: Trigonometric Identities

n(n + 1). 2 . If n = 3, then 1+2+3=6= 3(3+1) . If n = 2, then = 3 = 2(2+1)

Discrete Mathematics and Probability Theory Fall 2013 Vazirani Note 1

CS 220: Discrete Structures and their Applications. Mathematical Induction in zybooks

MAC-CPTM Situations Project. Situation 10: Simultaneous Equations

Introduction to Induction (LAMC, 10/14/07)

At the start of the term, we saw the following formula for computing the sum of the first n integers:

Climbing an Infinite Ladder

Mathematical Induction. How does discrete math help us. How does discrete math help (CS160)? How does discrete math help (CS161)?

Conjectures and proof. Book page 24-30

MAC-CPTM Situations Project. Situation 10: Simultaneous Equations

Chapter 2. Mathematical Reasoning. 2.1 Mathematical Models

Use mathematical induction in Exercises 3 17 to prove summation formulae. Be sure to identify where you use the inductive hypothesis.

Exercises. Template for Proofs by Mathematical Induction

Climbing an Infinite Ladder

Sequences of Real Numbers

What can you prove by induction?

Discrete Mathematics. Spring 2017

Hence, the sequence of triangular numbers is given by., the. n th square number, is the sum of the first. S n

MATHEMATICAL INDUCTION

MAC-CPTM Situations Project Situation 10: Simultaneous Equations Revised 04/13/06 Dennis Hembree and Erik Tillema

Induction and recursion. Chapter 5

PUTNAM TRAINING MATHEMATICAL INDUCTION. Exercises

1.2 Inductive Reasoning

Introducing Proof 1. hsn.uk.net. Contents

CMPSCI 250: Introduction to Computation. Lecture 11: Proof Techniques David Mix Barrington 5 March 2013

3 The language of proof

Discrete Mathematics and Probability Theory Spring 2016 Rao and Walrand Note 3

Contents. Counting Methods and Induction

Lecture Notes on Inductive Definitions

Every positive two digit number is greater than the product of it s digits. Asks class is it true? can you find a counter-example etc.

MAC-CPTM Situations Project

Lecture 6 : Induction DRAFT

35 Chapter CHAPTER 4: Mathematical Proof

Situation 41: Square Roots

With Question/Answer Animations

Supplementary Notes on Inductive Definitions

Lecture Notes on Inductive Definitions

Mathematical Induction

CISC-102 Fall 2017 Week 3. Principle of Mathematical Induction

INDUCTION AND RECURSION

Mathematical Induction. Rosen Chapter 4.1,4.2 (6 th edition) Rosen Ch. 5.1, 5.2 (7 th edition)

Direct Proofs. the product of two consecutive integers plus the larger of the two integers

Proof Techniques (Review of Math 271)

CSCE 222 Discrete Structures for Computing. Proofs. Dr. Hyunyoung Lee. !!!!! Based on slides by Andreas Klappenecker

Induction 1 = 1(1+1) = 2(2+1) = 3(3+1) 2

Mathematical Induction. Defining Functions. Overview. Notation for recursive functions. Base case Sn(0) = 0 S(n) = S(n 1) + n for n > 0

Law of Trichotomy and Boundary Equations

21 Induction. Tom Lewis. Fall Term Tom Lewis () 21 Induction Fall Term / 14

PROOF WITHOUT WORDS MATH CIRCLE (BEGINNERS) 05/06/2012

Manipulating Radicals

Chapter Summary. Mathematical Induction Strong Induction Well-Ordering Recursive Definitions Structural Induction Recursive Algorithms

DR.RUPNATHJI( DR.RUPAK NATH )

Tutorial on Mathematical Induction

2010 HSC NOTES FROM THE MARKING CENTRE MATHEMATICS EXTENSION 1

9.4. Mathematical Induction. Introduction. What you should learn. Why you should learn it

Math 414, Fall 2016, Test I

What mathematical knowledge does Mr. Fernandez need so that he might change his approach to radicals with his students?

Mathematical Induction

Math 31 Lesson Plan. Day 2: Sets; Binary Operations. Elizabeth Gillaspy. September 23, 2011

means is a subset of. So we say A B for sets A and B if x A we have x B holds. BY CONTRAST, a S means that a is a member of S.

SHOW ALL YOUR WORK IN A NEAT AND ORGANIZED FASHION

1 Implication and induction

Math 6/7 Honors - Expectations for Exit Exam/Testing Out

Induction and Recursion

INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC

Induction. Announcements. Overview. Defining Functions. Sum of Squares. Closed-form expression for SQ(n) There have been some corrections to A1

e π i 1 = 0 Proofs and Mathematical Induction Carlos Moreno uwaterloo.ca EIT-4103 e x2 log k a+b a + b

HOW TO WRITE PROOFS. Dr. Min Ru, University of Houston

CS 2110: INDUCTION DISCUSSION TOPICS

Chapter 1: Inductive and Deductive Reasoning

Lecture 3: Sizes of Infinity

Reading 5 : Induction

AQA Level 2 Further mathematics Further algebra. Section 4: Proof and sequences

The Lost Cousin of the Fundamental Theorem of Algebra

Appendix G: Mathematical Induction

ACCUPLACER MATH 0310

Mapping Australian Curriculum (AC) Mathematics and VELS Mathematics. Australian Curriculum (AC) Year 9 Year 10/10A

Mini-Course on Limits and Sequences. Peter Kwadwo Asante. B.S., Kwame Nkrumah University of Science and Technology, Ghana, 2014 A REPORT

CS 124 Math Review Section January 29, 2018

Chapter One Hilbert s 7th Problem: It s statement and origins

Direct Proof and Counterexample I:Introduction

Trinity Christian School Curriculum Guide

Direct Proof and Counterexample I:Introduction. Copyright Cengage Learning. All rights reserved.

What is proof? Lesson 1

For all For every For each For any There exists at least one There exists There is Some

BHP BILLITON UNIVERSITY OF MELBOURNE SCHOOL MATHEMATICS COMPETITION, 2003: INTERMEDIATE DIVISION

cse547, math547 DISCRETE MATHEMATICS Professor Anita Wasilewska

3.1 Induction: An informal introduction

Chapter 2 Section 2.1: Proofs Proof Techniques. CS 130 Discrete Structures

Transcription:

Prompt MAC-CPTM Situations Project Situation 51: Proof by Mathematical Induction Prepared at the University of Georgia Center for Proficiency in Teaching Mathematics 13 October 2006-Erik Tillema 22 February 2007-Jeremy Kilpatrick Edited at Pennsylvania State University Mid-Atlantic Center for Mathematics Teaching and Learning 04 February 2009 Heather Godine, Maureen Grady, and Svetlana Konnova 07 September 2009 M. Kathleen Heid A teacher of a calculus course gave her students the opportunity to earn extra credit by proving various algebraic formulas by mathematical induction. For example, one of the formulas was the following: 1 2 + 2 2 +... + n 2 = (n)(n + 1)(2n + 1)/6. Only one student in the class was able to prove any of the formulas. After the student had presented his three proofs to the class on three consecutive days, another student complained: I don t get what he is proving. And besides that, how do you get the algebraic formulas to start with? Commentary Given that it is a deductive process, mathematical induction is an unfortunate term. George Pólya used to say that a better term would be mathematical complement to induction. Although an inductive process can be used to verify a conjecture involving n for any finite n, mathematical induction is needed to prove the conjecture for all natural numbers n. The foci consider several important aspects of developing proofs by mathematical induction that students might find difficult or confusing, as well as some ways of generating conjectures that have an inductive proof. Focus 1 looks at a common image for what proof by mathematical induction accomplishes. Focus 2 examines a problem context in which a recursion relationship might be formed and used to formulate an algebraic statement that can be proved by mathematical induction. Focus 3 gives several examples of how figurate representation of numbers can lead to conjectures about algebraic formulas and subsequent proofs by induction. Foci 4 and 5 analyze the structure of inductive proof by providing some examples in which one of the two conditions for induction fails. Focus 4 suggests why a problem situation might be a better starting point for a proof by mathematical induction than an algebraic formula (true or false) because in the latter case, one starts with an analysis of a type of proof rather than the generation of a proof itself. Sit51_MathInduction_090907.doc Page 1 of 7

Mathematical Foci Mathematical Focus 1 Proof by mathematical induction can be portrayed with an image of any process involving a basis (k = 0) and an inductive step (if the conjecture holds for n = k, it holds for n = k + 1). It may be useful to provide some images of what mathematical induction does. One good image might be of a ladder that is infinitely tall (with the rungs representing the set of positive integers). In doing a proof by induction, we first have to check whether we can get on the first rung of the ladder (which corresponds to checking whether the base case of the proposition holds true). Once we know we can get on the ladder, we have to check that if we are on any step of the ladder, we can proceed to the next one; namely, if we are on the k th rung, we can move to the (k + 1) st rung (which corresponds to showing that if the proposition holds for k it will hold for k + 1). By proving these two things, we claim that, using the principle of mathematical induction, we can get to any rung of the ladder (which corresponds to proving that the proposition is true for all k). An alternate image used to illustrate proof by mathematical induction involves the domino effect. Imagine an infinite row of dominoes standing on end. If one knows that the first domino will fall, and if one knows that when domino k falls, its next neighbor (k + 1) will fall, then by the principle of mathematical induction, all the dominos will fall. Mathematical Focus 2 Proof by mathematical induction can be motivated by a recursion relationship using a graphic display. Many recursion formulas create problem-solving opportunities that might lead to an algebraic formulation of a situation and a subsequent proof by mathematical induction. One such problem situation 1 is the following: Suppose you have a 2 n 2 n chessboard. Show that if you remove one square (shown in black,) you can cover the remaining squares on the board with L-triominoes (shown in purple). 1 This problem situation arose in Patricia Wilson s EMAT 6650 (Historical and Cultural Foundations of Mathematics) course. Sit51_MathInduction_090907.doc Page 2 of 7

In the case shown above, there is an 8 8 chessboard. It is easy to show that it is possible to find a covering of the chessboard, but it is a little difficult to see a pattern in a particular covering of a chessboard of this size. This difficulty provides a good opportunity to use Polya s heuristic strategy of looking at a related problem that is simpler. Let s examine a 2 2 and 4 4 chessboard. In the 2 2 case, we can clearly cover the chessboard without any difficulty. That is, we can place a triomino as we please, and exactly one space will be left over: We might next look at a 4 4 board and notice that it is composed of exactly four 2 2 chessboards (and further that there are four 4 4 chessboards in an 8 8 chessboard). In making this observation, we can establish a recursion relationship between successive chessboards. Also, we might observe that our 4 4 board will have exactly one 2 2 chessboard with the space taken out of it and three 2 2 chessboards with exactly one space not covered. We can cover those three spaces with exactly one triomino (shown on the left). Having made these observations, we can set up a recursion relationship between successive boards and make a more formal proof by mathematical induction. Note that in this case we might simply do the proof by writing out our observations. On the other hand, we might use this problem to show that (2 2n 1)/3 is a whole number for all n > 1. To think of this algebraic formulation, we notice that the chessboard contains 2 2n squares and that removing one of the squares gives us 2 2n 1 remaining squares to be covered. Also, each triomino contains 3 squares. Most importantly, we have to see that the spatial arrangement of the triominoes on the board does not affect the solution of the problem. Imagine cutting the board at each row and putting the rows end to end. Then imagine changing the L-triominoes to straight triominoes (shown below for the 4 4 chessboard). Sit51_MathInduction_090907.doc Page 3 of 7

We can once again use a recursive argument to show that we can cover all but one of the squares of our transformed board with our transformed triominoes. From this spatial configuration, we may become more convinced that we are asking ourselves a question of division. That is, how many threes are in a row of length 2 2n 1? The answer is a whole number. Mathematical Focus 3 Figurate numbers can also be used to generate identities that can then be proved by mathematical induction. Consider a figurate representation for the square numbers using dots. In that configuration, one might observe the pattern below: The configuration suggests that n 2 = 1 + 3 + + (2n 1). Having made a conjecture about the formula, we can then try to prove it by mathematical induction. (Also, how might a formula for the sum of the first n even numbers be found and proved?) A second situation that uses figurate numbers and that extends Situation 39, which demonstrates n(n +1) several ways to get an intuitive feeling for why the sum of the first n integers equals, is 2 to find the sum of the first n sums of the first n integers. Algebraically, if T 1 = 1, T 2 = 1 + 2, T n = 1 + 2 + + n, then we want to find T 1 + T 2 + + T n. We can introduce the situation by finding both an additive and multiplicative solution to the following problem. Suppose there are five points on a circle. How many possible triangles can you make? We can structure the problem additively by thinking about the number of triangles with AB as the base (3), with BC as the base (2 more), and with CD as the base (1 more), or T 1 + T 2 + T 3. Sit51_MathInduction_090907.doc Page 4 of 7

Multiplicatively, we can think about choosing sets of three points from five or 5. After solving 3 the problem for several numbers of points, we might conjecture that T 1 + T 2 +...+ T n = n + 2 = 1 6 (n + 2)(n +1)(n), and use the problem context to prove the identity 3 by mathematical induction. (An extension of the problem would be to find an additive and multiplicative way of thinking about the number of diagonals that can be drawn in a convex n- gon). We might then consider using the identity to find an identity for 1 2 + 2 2 +...+ n 2. We again make a figurate representation of the problem to help us see what the identity might be. The first four square numbers are shown below: Knowing that we have a formula for the sum of the first n triangular numbers, we break the figure into triangular numbers: From our example of the sum of the first four square numbers, we might observe that the sum of the first n square numbers is 2T 1 + 2T 2 +...+ 2T n 1 + T n = n + 2 + n +1. A little algebraic 3 3 manipulation gives 1 2 + 2 2 +...n 2 = 1 6 (2n +1)(n +1)(n), another formula that we conjecture to be true and whose validity might be established by mathematical induction. A final problem might be to look at the square of the sum of the first n integers: (1 + 2 + + n) 2. We again might want to make a figurate representation of the case for n = 4: Sit51_MathInduction_090907.doc Page 5 of 7

How many groups of four are in the figure above? There are 5 vertical groups (the sum of the 2 4 first four integers), and there are horizontal groups (the sum of the first three integers), 2 giving a total of 4 5 2 + 4 2 dots. A little algebraic simplification shows that there are 4 3 dots in the outermost region of the figure. A similar process shows us that in computing the dots in groups of threes gives us 3 3 dots, and so on. That yields a conjecture for the following identity: (1 + 2 + n) 2 = 1 3 + 2 3 + + n 3. We then can prove the formula by mathematical induction. Mathematical Focus 4 Proof by mathematical induction requires both a basis step and an inductive step; it fails if either is lacking. Many of the examples in which one of the steps fails are somewhat trivial, but they can nonetheless give us some feeling for the importance of both. For instance, consider the inequality 5(2 n ) > 6 n. It holds true for n =1 (we can get on the ladder). Now assume the inequality is true for n = k and try to show that it is true for n = k + 1. We need to show that 5(2 k +1 ) > 6 k +1 given that 5(2 k ) > 6 k. We use the inductive hypothesis to form the inequality 5(2 k +1 ) = 2(5(2 k ) > 2(6 k ), and we would like to be able to conclude that 2(6 k ) > 6(6 k ) = 6 k +1. However, that would imply that 2 > 6, which is false. Seeing no way to proceed, we check our assumption. If n = 2, 5(2 n ) > 6 n yields 20 > 36, which is false. In this case, we were able to get on the first step of the ladder but not able to move from rung to rung. We might now consider the inequality 3 n > 5(3 n ). Suppose we begin by assuming that it is true for n = k and try to prove it for n = k + 1. We find that 3 k +1 = 3(3 k ) > 3(5(3 k ) = 5(3 k +1 ), and the inequality holds true based on our inductive hypothesis (we are able to move from rung to rung). However, in the case of n = 1 the inequality does not hold. We are unable to get on the ladder Sit51_MathInduction_090907.doc Page 6 of 7

even though if we could, we could move from rung to rung. These examples illustrate that both conditions need to be met in for a proof by mathematical induction to work. They also suggest that it is worth checking several cases when proving something by induction. Checking several cases, however, is not a substitute for a proof, as can be seen by the inequality 3 n > n!. This inequality holds for the first six cases, but it is false when n = 7. For any a, the inequality a n > n! will eventually become false even though we can make the n for which it becomes false arbitrarily large. This example demonstrates that proof by mathematical induction is in fact deductive. That is, we are not drawing a conclusion based solely on repeated observations (inductive reasoning), instead, we are establishing two premises and stating that if both premises hold true we can assert the conclusion (deductive reasoning). The three examples in this focus taken together suggest the relationship of the premises to the conclusion as well as the role that observation plays in relation to a proof by induction. Mathematical Focus 5 Proof by mathematical induction requires one to consider the basis step, depending on the nature of the operations involved. In case we wish to prove a statement defined from a binary operation, then the basis step has to contain the n = 2 case. An example of a binary operation could be an operation that includes an equivalence relation. In the middle of the 20th century, George Pólya posed the following exercise: Find the error in the following argument, which proposes to prove that all horses are of the same color using the method of mathematical induction. * Basis: If there is only one horse, there is only one color. * Induction step: Assume as induction hypothesis that within any set of n horses, there is only one color. Now look at any set of n + 1 horses. Number them: 1, 2, 3,..., n, n + 1. Consider the sets {1, 2, 3,..., n} and {2, 3, 4,..., n + 1}. Each is a set of only n horses; therefore within each there is only one color. But the two sets overlap, so there must be only one color among all n + 1 horses. Let us analyze the use of the method of mathematical induction for the example given above. For the basis step, the n = 1 case is trivial because any horse is the same color as itself. However, the logic of the inductive step is incorrect when n = 2. In case n = 2 we have to consider two sets {1} and {2} and they do not overlap. Therefore, even thought the inductive step is correct in all cases when n > 2, the logic of the inductive step is incorrect when n = 2. Consequently, the method of mathematical induction cannot be applied to prove that that all horses are of the same color, because the basis step for this example, where the binary operation is involved has to consider the n = 2 case and it fails. Sit51_MathInduction_090907.doc Page 7 of 7