FERMAT S LAST THEOREM FOR n = 3, NOTES FOR MATH In these notes, we prove Fermat s Last Theorem for n = 3.

Similar documents
School of Mathematics

1. Factorization Divisibility in Z.

Math 324, Fall 2011 Assignment 7 Solutions. 1 (ab) γ = a γ b γ mod n.

NOTES ON SIMPLE NUMBER THEORY

PRACTICE PROBLEMS: SET 1

Homework due on Monday, October 22

All variables a, b, n, etc are integers unless otherwise stated. Each part of a problem is worth 5 points.

COMP239: Mathematics for Computer Science II. Prof. Chadi Assi EV7.635

MATH 152 Problem set 6 solutions

18. Cyclotomic polynomials II

ALGEBRA. 1. Some elementary number theory 1.1. Primes and divisibility. We denote the collection of integers

2. THE EUCLIDEAN ALGORITHM More ring essentials

Chapter 1. From Euclid to Gauss. 1.1 Prime numbers. If a, b Z we say that a divides b (or is a divisor of b) and we write a b, if.

MATH 361: NUMBER THEORY TWELFTH LECTURE. 2 The subjects of this lecture are the arithmetic of the ring

CHAPTER 6. Prime Numbers. Definition and Fundamental Results

An integer p is prime if p > 1 and p has exactly two positive divisors, 1 and p.

MATH 361: NUMBER THEORY FOURTH LECTURE

LARGE PRIME NUMBERS (32, 42; 4) (32, 24; 2) (32, 20; 1) ( 105, 20; 0).

CISC-102 Fall 2017 Week 6

(January 14, 2009) q n 1 q d 1. D = q n = q + d

Number Theory Math 420 Silverman Exam #1 February 27, 2018

Math 109 September 1, 2016

MATH FINAL EXAM REVIEW HINTS

4 Powers of an Element; Cyclic Groups

NOTES ON INTEGERS. 1. Integers

6]. (10) (i) Determine the units in the rings Z[i] and Z[ 10]. If n is a squarefree

A field F is a set of numbers that includes the two numbers 0 and 1 and satisfies the properties:

Homework 3, solutions

p = This is small enough that its primality is easily verified by trial division. A candidate prime above 1000 p of the form p U + 1 is

Math 109 HW 9 Solutions

Discrete valuation rings. Suppose F is a field. A discrete valuation on F is a function v : F {0} Z such that:

Chapter 5. Number Theory. 5.1 Base b representations

Elementary Algebra Chinese Remainder Theorem Euclidean Algorithm

32 Divisibility Theory in Integral Domains

Definitions. Notations. Injective, Surjective and Bijective. Divides. Cartesian Product. Relations. Equivalence Relations

Notes on Systems of Linear Congruences

WORKSHEET ON NUMBERS, MATH 215 FALL. We start our study of numbers with the integers: N = {1, 2, 3,...}

Know the Well-ordering principle: Any set of positive integers which has at least one element contains a smallest element.

SOLUTIONS Math 345 Homework 6 10/11/2017. Exercise 23. (a) Solve the following congruences: (i) x (mod 12) Answer. We have

Lecture Notes Math 371: Algebra (Fall 2006) by Nathanael Leedom Ackerman

Homework #2 solutions Due: June 15, 2012

D-MATH Algebra I HS18 Prof. Rahul Pandharipande. Solution 1. Arithmetic, Zorn s Lemma.

12x + 18y = 50. 2x + v = 12. (x, v) = (6 + k, 2k), k Z.

Factoring Algorithms Pollard s p 1 Method. This method discovers a prime factor p of an integer n whenever p 1 has only small prime factors.

MATH 433 Applied Algebra Lecture 4: Modular arithmetic (continued). Linear congruences.

0 Sets and Induction. Sets

SOLUTIONS TO PROBLEM SET 1. Section = 2 3, 1. n n + 1. k(k + 1) k=1 k(k + 1) + 1 (n + 1)(n + 2) n + 2,

1. multiplication is commutative and associative;

Proof 1: Using only ch. 6 results. Since gcd(a, b) = 1, we have

FACTORING IN QUADRATIC FIELDS. 1. Introduction

ARITHMETIC PROGRESSIONS OF SQUARES, CUBES AND n-th POWERS

MATH 215 Final. M4. For all a, b in Z, a b = b a.

MATH 2200 Final Review

ALGEBRA HANDOUT 2.3: FACTORIZATION IN INTEGRAL DOMAINS. In this handout we wish to describe some aspects of the theory of factorization.

Ju-Si Lee 1. INTRODUCTION

Algebraic Number Theory

The Impossibility of Certain Types of Carmichael Numbers

Prime Numbers and Irrational Numbers

Selected Math 553 Homework Solutions

Mathematics 220 Homework 4 - Solutions. Solution: We must prove the two statements: (1) if A = B, then A B = A B, and (2) if A B = A B, then A = B.

Math 547, Exam 2 Information.

Example: This theorem is the easiest way to test an ideal (or an element) is prime. Z[x] (x)

2 Arithmetic. 2.1 Greatest common divisors. This chapter is about properties of the integers Z = {..., 2, 1, 0, 1, 2,...}.

Honors Algebra 4, MATH 371 Winter 2010 Assignment 3 Due Friday, February 5 at 08:35

Homework 6 Solution. Math 113 Summer 2016.

Course 2316 Sample Paper 1

Senior Math Circles Cryptography and Number Theory Week 2

Just like the ring of Gaussian integers, the ring of Eisenstein integers is a Unique Factorization Domain.

Definition For a set F, a polynomial over F with variable x is of the form

Math 547, Exam 1 Information.

MATH 145 Algebra, Solutions to Assignment 4

Number Theory. Final Exam from Spring Solutions

EXAMPLES OF MORDELL S EQUATION

Proposition The gaussian numbers form a field. The gaussian integers form a commutative ring.

Solutions for Homework Assignment 2

CS 5319 Advanced Discrete Structure. Lecture 9: Introduction to Number Theory II

. In particular if a b then N(

Solving Diophantine Equations With Unique Factorization

Solutions to Practice Final

Homework 7 solutions M328K by Mark Lindberg/Marie-Amelie Lawn

Lecture Notes. Advanced Discrete Structures COT S

Chapter 3 Basic Number Theory

Definition 6.1 (p.277) A positive integer n is prime when n > 1 and the only positive divisors are 1 and n. Alternatively

Congruence of Integers

LECTURE NOTES IN CRYPTOGRAPHY

Diophantine triples in a Lucas-Lehmer sequence

MATH 4400 SOLUTIONS TO SOME EXERCISES. 1. Chapter 1

Number Theory Proof Portfolio

LEHMER S TOTIENT PROBLEM AND CARMICHAEL NUMBERS IN A PID

U + V = (U V ) (V U), UV = U V.

Ch 4.2 Divisibility Properties

For your quiz in recitation this week, refer to these exercise generators:

Number Theory and Group Theoryfor Public-Key Cryptography

#G03 INTEGERS 10 (2010), MIN, A COMBINATORIAL GAME HAVING A CONNECTION WITH PRIME NUMBERS

EUCLID S ALGORITHM AND THE FUNDAMENTAL THEOREM OF ARITHMETIC after N. Vasiliev and V. Gutenmacher (Kvant, 1972)

Summary: Divisibility and Factorization

Gaussian integers. 1 = a 2 + b 2 = c 2 + d 2.

Wilson s Theorem and Fermat s Little Theorem

8 Primes and Modular Arithmetic

Greatest Common Divisor MATH Greatest Common Divisor. Benjamin V.C. Collins, James A. Swenson MATH 2730

Transcription:

FERMAT S LAST THEOREM FOR n = 3, NOTES FOR MATH 40520 SAM EVENS In these notes, we prove Fermat s Last Theorem for n = 3. 1 Recall that Z[ω] = {a+bω : a, b Z} has a Euclidean algorithm and is norm integral. in the sense of the notes on subrings. In particular, the following are true: Remark 1.1. (i) If π is a prime of Z[ω], and z, w Z[ω], and π z w in Z[ω], then π z or π w in Z[ω] (this is Proposition 2.15(i) from subrings notes for Z[i], and the same proof works for Z[ω]). (ii) If z Z[ω], then N(z) = 1 if and only if z is a unit of Z[ω] (see Lemma 1.8 of the notes on subrings) (iii) Let z = a + bω Z[ω] {0}. Then N(z) = a 2 ab + b 2 Z >0, and if N(z) is a prime in Z, then z is a prime in Z[ω]. (iv) λ = 1 ω is a prime in Z[ω]. Indeed, by (iii) above, N(λ) = 3, so λ is prime in Z[ω]. (v) Let z, w Z[ω]. Then z 3 w 3 = (z w) (z ωw) (z ω 2 w). Indeed, by explicit computation (z w) (z ωw) (z ω 2 w) = z 3 (1 + ω + ω 2 )z 2 w + (1 + ω + ω 2 )z w 2 w 3, since 1 + ω + ω 2 = 0. (vi) Let π be a prime of Z[ω]. Since Z[ω] is a unique factorization domain, then for any nonzero z Z[ω], we can write z = π e b for some b Z[ω] such that π does not divide b. Then we set ord π (z) = e, and it is routine to check that π z if and only if ord π (z) > 0. Further, if z, w Z[ω], then ord π (z w) = ord π (z) + ord π (w). (vii) In the language of (vi) above, let ord π (z) = e and let ord π (w) = f. Suppose e f, and let g be the minimum of e and f. Then ord π (z) = e. Indeed, suppose that g = e < f. Then z = π e a and w = π f b where π divides neither a nor b. Then z + w = π e a + π f b = π e (a + π f e b), and f e > 0. Note that π does not divide a + π f e b since if it did, it would divide (a + π f e b) π f e b = a, which is not the case. Hence, ord π (z + w) = e. A similar argument works if f < e. 1

2 SAM EVENS Remark 1.2. (i) If z, w Z[ω] are not both zero, then gcd(z, w) = d Z[ω] means that d z and d w, and N(d) N(e) for all e Z[ω] such that e z and e w. Similarly, if a, b, c Z[ω] are not all zero, then gcd(a, b, c) = d Z[ω] means that d a, d b, and d c, and N(d) is maximal among elements of Z[ω] dividing a, b and c. (ii) Suppose z, w Z[ω] are not both zero, and consider the ideal (z, w) = {az + bw : a, b Z[ω]}. Then Problem 4 of Homework 3 asserts that (z, w) = (d) = {d η : η Z[ω]}. It is then easy to show that d = gcd(z, w), in the same manner as this is proved for Z[i] in Proposition 2.11 of the notes on subrings. In particular, if e Z[ω] and e z and e w, then e d. Indeed, since (z, w) = (d), there are a, b Z[ω] such that d = az + bw, so since e z and e w, then e az + bw = d by Lemma 1.6(iii) from the notes on subrings. (iii) Let d = gcd(a, b, c). Then gcd( a d, b d, c d ) = 1, and the only common divisors of a d, b d, c d are units. Indeed, let e divide a d in Z[ω]. Then a = w e d for some w Z[ω], and e d a. Similarly, e d divides b and c in Z[ω], so since d = gcd(a, b, c), then N(e d) N(d). But N(e d) = N(e)N(d) N(d) since N(e) 1, so it follows that N(e d) = N(d), and N(e) = 1. Thus, e is a unit. Remark 1.3. Let u be a unit of Z[ω], and let x, y, z Z[ω] with x 3 + y 3 = uz 3. Then if a prime π of Z[ω] divides any two of x, y, z, then π divides all three of x, y, z. Indeed, suppose π divides x and y. Then π divides x 3 + y 3, so π divides uz 3. Since u is a unit, π does not divide u, so π divides z 3 by Remark 1.1 (i), and thus π divides z using the same Remark. The other cases are similar. Remark 1.4. Let z Z[ω] and u be a unit in Z[ω]. Suppose uz 3 = a b c with a, b, c Z[ω], and gcd(a, b) = gcd(b, c) = gcd(a, c) = π, where π is a prime of Z[ω]. Let ord π (z) = e, and suppose ord π (b) = ord π (c) = 1. Then there are units u a, u b, u c of Z[ω] and α, β, γ Z[ω] with π dividing none of α, β, γ and gcd(α, β) = 1, gcd(α, γ) = 1, and gcd(β, γ) = 1 so that a = u a α 3 π 3e 2, b = u b β 3 π, c = u c γ 3 π. To see this, let z = w π e with π w. Then u z 3 = u w 3 π 3e, and if π w 3, then π w by property (i) from Remark 1.1. Thus, π w 3, so ord π (z 3 ) = 3e. Since z 3 = a b c, we see that ord π (z 3 ) = ord π (a b c) = ord π (a) + ord π (b) + ord π (c), using the last equality of Remark 1.1 (vi). Since ord π (b) = ord π (c) = 1, we see that ord π (a) = 3e 2. Thus, by definition of ord π, we can write a = α a π 3e 2, b = β b π, c = γ c π, where π divides none of α a, β b, or γ c. Let q be a prime factor of a in Z[ω] and suppose q π. Then by Remark 1.1 (i), q α a. If q β b, then q a and q b. Hence, by Remark 1.2 (ii), it follows that q gcd(a, b) = π, which contradicts our assumption. Thus, q β b. Similarly, q γ c. Since q a, then q a b c = u z 3, so q z 3, and q z, again by Remark 1.1 (i). Let e q = ord q (z). Then ord q (u z 3 ) = 3e q, so ord q (a b c) = 3e q is

FERMAT S LAST THEOREM FOR n = 3, NOTES FOR MATH 40520 3 a multiple of 3. Since q does not divide b or c, we see that ord q (b) = ord q (c) = 0, and hence ord q (a) = 3e q. Thus, every prime factor appearing in a besides π must occur with exponent a multiple of 3, and it follows that α a = u a α 3 for a unit u a, where α is a product of prime factors of a besides π. Hence, a = u a α 3 π 3e 2. Similar arguments show that b = u b β 3 π, and c = u c γ 3 π, where β is a product of a prime factors of b besides π, and γ is a product of prime factors of c besides π. Lemma 1.5. Let z Z[ω]. Then z is congruent to exactly one of 1, 0, and 1 mod λ. Proof. Let z = a+bω. Then since 1 ω 0 (mod λ), a+bω a+bω+b (1 ω) a+b (mod λ). Since 3 = N(λ), then λ 3, so 3 0 (mod λ). We write a + b = 3q + r for q, r Z with 0 r < 3. Then z a + b a + b 3q r (mod λ), since 3 0 (mod λ). Thus, z is congruent to 0, 1 or 2 mod λ. If z 2 (mod λ), then z 2 3 1 (mod λ). It follows that z is equivalent to at least one from 0, 1 and 1 mod λ. On the other hand, ±1 0 (mod λ) implies that λ ±1, and this is impossible since λ is not a unit. If 1 1 (mod λ), then λ 2, so N(λ) N(2) = 4, so 3 4 in Z, and this is not the case. It follows that 1, 0, 1 are distinct elements mod λ. Lemma 1.6. (see proof of Lemma 1 in 17.8) (i) If z 1 (mod λ), then z 3 1 (mod λ 4 ). (ii) If z 1 (mod λ), then z 3 1 (mod λ 4 ). Proof. For (i), since z 1 (mod λ), then z 1 = t λ, with t Z[ω]. Thus, z 3 1 = (z 1) (z ω) (z ω 2 ) by part (v) of Remark 1.1. Thus, z 3 1 = t λ (1+λt ω) (1+λt ω 2 ). But (1 + λt ω) = (1 ω) + λt = λ + λt = λ (1 + t), and Hence, (1 + λt ω 2 ) = ((1 ω 2 ) + λt) = ((1 ω)(1 + ω) + λt) = λ (1 + ω + t). z 3 1 = t λ λ (1 + t) λ (1 + t + ω) = λ 3 t (1 + t) (1 + t + ω). By Lemma 1.5, either t 0 or 1 or 1 mod λ. If t 0 (mod λ), then t = λ w for some w Z[ω], so z 3 1 = λ 4 w (1 + t) (1 + t + ω), and thus, z 3 1 (mod λ 4 ). If t 1 (mod λ), then t + 1 = w λ for some w Z[ω], so z 3 1 = λ 4 t w (1 + t + ω), and z 3 1 (mod λ 4 ). The other possibility is that t 1 (mod λ), so t = 1 + w λ for some w Z[ω]. But then 1+t+ω = 1+1+w λ+ω = 3 (1 ω)+wλ = (1 ω 2 ) λ λ+wλ = λ ((1 ω 2 ) 1+w), where we used 3 = N(λ) = (1 ω 2 ) λ. It follows that z 3 1 = λ 4 t (1 + t) (w ω 2 ), and hence, z 3 1 (mod λ 4 ). Thus, in any of the three possible cases for t (mod λ), we see that z 3 1 (mod λ 4 ), and this proves part (i). For part (ii), if z 1 (mod λ),

4 SAM EVENS then z 1 (mod λ), so by part (i) of the Lemma, ( z) 3 1 (mod λ 4 ), so z 3 1 (mod λ 4 ), and thus, z 3 1 (mod λ 4 ). Lemma 1.7. Let u be a unit of Z[ω]. (i) 2 u (mod λ 4 ). (ii) If ɛ + u 0 (mod λ 2 ), where ɛ = ±1, then u = ɛ. (iii) If ɛ = ±1, and ɛ u (mod λ 3 ), then u = ɛ. Proof. For case (i), then 2 u (mod λ 4 ), then λ 4 (2 u), and thus, N(λ 4 ) N(2 u) in Z. The possibilities are u = 1, 1, ω, ω, ω 2, ω 2, since these are the units of Z[ω]. Thus, 2 u is one of 1, 3, 2 ω, 2 + ω, 2 + (1 + ω), and 2 (1 + ω), where we have used ω 2 = 1 ω. From the formula N(a + bω) = a 2 ab + b 2 in Remark 1.1 (iii), we see that N(2 u) is one of 1, 9, 7, 3, 7, and 3. Since N(λ 4 ) = N(λ) 4 = 3 4 = 81, we see that λ 4 2 u in all these cases. This proves (i). Assertions (ii) and (iii) follow in the same way. The following proposition is called the easy case of Fermat s last theorem for n = 3. Proposition 1.8. If x, y, z Z[ω] are nonzero and λ divides none of x, y and z, then x 3 + y 3 is not equal to uz 3. Proof. We argue by contradiction. Suppose x 3 + y 3 = uz 3. Since λ divides none of x, y and z, we conclude that x ±1, y ±1, and z ±1 modulo λ, by using Lemma 1.5. Thus, by Lemma 1.6, x 3 ±1 (mod λ 4 ) and similarly y 3 ±1 (mod λ 4 ) and z 3 ±1 (mod λ 4 ). Since x 3 + y 3 uz 3 (mod λ 4 ), we see that ±1 + ±1 ±u (mod λ 4 ). But ±1 + ±1 = ±2 or 0, so either ±2 ±u (mod λ 4 ) or 0 ±u (mod λ 4 ). Thus, either 2 ±u (mod λ 4 ) or 0 ±u (mod λ 4 ). But 0 ±u (mod λ 4 ) implies that λ 4 u, and this is impossible because λ 4 is not a unit. If 2 ±u (mod λ 4 ), then since ±u is a unit, we see that 2 v (mod λ 4 ) for some unit v of Z[ω]. But this contradicts Lemma 1.7, and it follows that x 3 + y 3 = uz 3 is impossible in Z[ω]. Lemma 1.9. Let u be a unit of Z[ω], and suppose x, y, z Z[ω] with x 3 + y 3 = uz 3. Suppose that λ x and λ y, and λ z. Then λ 2 z. Proof. Reducing mod λ, we obtain x 3 + y 3 uz 3 (mod λ 4 ). Since λ x, then by Lemma 1.5, x ±1 (mod λ), so by Lemma 1.6, x 3 ±1 (mod λ 4 ). Similarly, y 3 ±1 (mod λ 4 ). It follows that ±1+±1 uz 3 (mod λ 4 ). Note that ±1+±1 is either 2, 0, or 2. If it is ±2, we obtain ±2 uz 3 (mod λ 4 ), so (±2 uz 3 ) = t λ 4 for some t Z[ω]. Since λ divides z, λ divides uz 3, and it follows that λ divides ±2, so 3 = N(λ) divides 4 = N(±2), and this is false. We conclude that 0 uz 3 (mod λ 4 ), so that uz 3 = t λ 4 for some t Z[ω]. Let ord λ (z) = e, so that z = λ e a for some a Z[ω] with λ a. Thus, u a 3 λ 3e = t λ 4. Since u is a unit and λ a, we see that ord λ (u a 3 λ 3e ) = 3e.

FERMAT S LAST THEOREM FOR n = 3, NOTES FOR MATH 40520 5 On the other hand, ord λ (t λ 4 ) = ord λ (t) + 4 4, so that 3e 4, and e 4 3. Since e Z, we see e 2, and thus λ 2 z. Lemma 1.10. Let u be a unit of Z[ω], and let x, y, z Z[ω] with x 3 + y 3 = uz 3, λ x, λ y, and λ 2 z, and gcd(x, y) = 1. Then there is u 1 a unit of Z[ω], and x 1, y 1, z 1 Z[ω] with λ x 1, λ y 1, and ord λ (z 1 ) = ord λ (z) 1 so that Proof. By Remark 1.1 (v), we can factor x 3 1 + y 3 1 = u 1 z 3 1. u z 3 = x 3 + y 3 = (x + y) (x + ωy) (x + ω 2 y). (1.11) Since ord λ (z) = e 2, we see that ord λ (u z 3 ) = 3e 6. By Equation (1.11), we see that 3e = ord λ (x + y) + ord λ (x + ωy) + ord λ (x + ω 2 y) 6. Hence, one of ord λ (x + y), ord λ (x + ωy), and ord λ (x + ω 2 y) is greater than or equal to 2. Suppose ord λ (x + ωy) 2. Then we can let v = ωy, so y = ω 1 v = ω 2 v, and thus the above factors are x + ω 2 v, x + v, and x + ωv, and ord λ (x + v) 2. Since v 3 = y 3, we get a version of Equation 1.11 with v in place of y and ord λ (x + v) 2. We can then rename v as y, so that we get ord λ (x+y) 2. Similarly, if ord λ (x+ω 2 y) 2, we could rename variables to obtain ord λ (x + y) 2, so we may assume ord λ (x + y) 2. Consider ord λ (x + ωy) = ord λ ((x + y) (1 ω)y) = ord λ ((x + y) λ y). Note that ord λ (y) = 0 since λ y, so ord λ ( λ y) = ord λ (λ) = 1 < ord λ (x + y). Hence, by Remark 1.1 (vii), we see that ord λ (x + ωy) = 1. Similarly, ord λ (x + ω 2 y) = 1. Let π be a prime of Z[ω] so that π λ. Then π does not divide both x + y and x + ωy. If it did, then π would divide (x + y) (x + ωy) = λ y, so that π divides y by Remark 1.1 (i). Thus, π also divides x = x + y y, and this contradicts the assumption that gcd(x, y) = 1. Similarly, we can show that π cannot divide both x + y and x + ω 2 y, and π cannot divide both x + ωy and x + ω 2 y. It now follows by Property (ii) of Remark 1.4 that: x + y = u 1 α 3 λ t, t = 3 ord λ (z) 2, λ α, (1.12) x + ωy = u 2 β 3 λ, λ β, (1.13) x + ω 2 y = u 3 γ 3 λ, λ γ, (1.14) with u 1, u 2, u 3 units of Z[ω], and gcd(α, β) = 1, gcd(β, γ) = 1, and gcd(α, γ) = 1. Multiplying Equation (1.13) by ω gives ωx + ω 2 y = v 2 β 3 λ, (1.15) where v 2 = ω u 2 is a unit. Multiplying Equation (1.14) by ω 2 gives ω 2 x + ωy = v 3 γ 3 λ, (1.16) where v 3 = ω 2 u 3 is a unit. Now adding together equations (1.12), (1.15), (1.16) gives (x + y) + (ωx + ω 2 y) + (ω 2 x + ωy) = u 1 α 3 λ t + v 2 β 3 λ + v 3 γ 3 λ. (1.17)

6 SAM EVENS Separating x and y terms and using 1 + ω + ω 2 = 0, we obtain 0 = u 1 α 3 λ t + v 2 β 3 λ + v 3 γ 3 λ. (1.18) We divide through by λ, and note that t 1 = 3 (ord λ (z) 1) to obtain 0 = u 1 α 3 λ 3 (ord λ(z) 1) + v 2 β 3 + v 3 γ 3. (1.19) We set z 1 = α λ ord λ(z) 1, let x 1 = β, and let y 1 = γ, and obtain and after dividing through by v 2, we obtain v 2 x 3 1 + v 3 y 3 1 = u 1 z 3 1, (1.20) x 3 1 + w 1 y 3 1 = w 2 z 3 1, (1.21) with w 1 = v 3 v 2 and w 2 = u 1 v 2 units of Z[ω]. Since x 1 = β and y 1 = γ, then λ divides neither x 1 nor y 1. Thus, by Lemma 1.5, we see that x 1 ɛ 1 (mod λ), and x 2 ɛ 2 (mod λ 2 ), where ɛ 1, ɛ 2 are ±1. Note that λ z 1 since ord λ (z 1 ) = ord λ (z) 1 2 1, so λ 3 z1 3. Thus, z3 1 0 (mod λ2 ). Hence, by reducing mod λ 2, we see that ɛ 1 + w 1 ɛ 2 0 (mod λ 2 ). (1.22) We now let ɛ 1 = ɛ and w 1 ɛ 2 = u in Lemma 1.7, and conclude that w 1 ɛ 2 = ɛ 1, so w 1 = ɛ 1 ɛ2 = ɛ 3 with ɛ 3 = ±1. If w 1 = 1, we leave Equation 1.21 as it is, and if w 1 = 1, we change y 1 to y 1. In either case, letting w 2 = u, we obtain This proves the assertion. x 3 1 + y 3 1 = uz 3 1. (1.23) Theorem 1.24. Let u Z[ω] be a unit. Then there do not exist nonzero x, y, z Z[ω] such that x 3 + y 3 = uz 3. Proof. Let S := {(x, y, z) Z[ω] {0} : u Z[ω], x 3 + y 3 = uz 3 }. We want to show S =. By Proposition 1.8, if (x, y, z) S, then λ divides at least one of x, y, z. Thus, to show S is empty, it suffices to show T = {(x, y, z) S : λ xyz} is empty. If T is not empty, we may choose (x, y, z) T with the maximum of ord λ (x), ord λ (y), ord λ (z) less than or equal to the maximum of ord λ (x ), ord λ (y ), ord λ (z ) for all (x, y, z ) in T. If λ divides two of x, y, z then λ divides gcd(x, y, z) by Remark 1.3. Then by Remark 1.2 (iii), ( x λ, y λ, z λ ) S. By Proposition 1.8, λ divides at least one of x λ, y λ, and z λ, and hence ( x λ, y λ, z λ ) T But for any w Z[ω], if λ w, then ord λ ( w λ ) = ord λ(w) 1, so that the maximum of ord λ ( x λ ), ord λ( y λ ), ord λ( z λ )) is one less than the maximum of ord λ (x), ord λ (y), ord λ (z), which contradicts the choice of (x, y, z). Hence, there exists (x, y, z) T with the property that λ divides exactly one of (x, y, z).

Let FERMAT S LAST THEOREM FOR n = 3, NOTES FOR MATH 40520 7 T 1 = {(x, y, z) T : λ x, λ y, λ z}, T 2 = {(x, y, z) T : λ x, λ y, λ z}, T 3 = {(x, y, z) T : λ x, λ y, λ z}, The final sentence of the last paragraph implies that if T is non-empty, then either T 1, T 2, or T 3 is nonempty. We next show T 3 is empty, and later use this to conclude that T 1 and T 2 is empty. If T 3 is nonempty, there exists (x, y, z) T 3 with ord λ (z) ord λ (z ) for all (x, y, z ) T 3. Let d = gcd(x, y, z), and let a = x d, b = y d, and c = z d. By Remark 1.2 (iii), (a, b, c) S. Since a x and λ x, it follows that λ a. Similarly, λ b. If λ c, we would contradict Proposition 1.8, so we conclude that λ c. Since gcd(a, b, c) = 1, it follows that gcd(a, b) = 1 by Remark 1.3. Thus, we conclude that (a, b, c) T 3, and hence, ord λ (z) ord λ (c) by the choice of (x, y, z). But z = d c, so that ord λ (z) = ord λ (d) + ord λ (c), and we conclude that ord λ (z) ord λ (c). Hence, there exists (a, b, c) T 3 with ord λ (c) minimal, and gcd(a, b) = 1. By Lemma 1.9, ord λ (c) 2. By Lemma 1.10, there is (a 1, b 1, c 1 ) T 3 with ord λ (c 1 ) = ord λ (c) 1, which contradicts the choice of (a, b, c) T 3. Hence, T 3 is empty. We now show that T 1 and T 2 are empty. Indeed, if (x, y, z) T 1, then since λ x, we know x 3 0 (mod λ 3 ). Since (x, y, z) T 1, λ y and λ z. Hence by Lemma 1.5, y ±1 (mod λ) and z ±1 (mod λ). Thus, the identity x 3 + y 3 uz 3 (mod λ 3 ) implies ɛ 1 u ɛ 2 (mod λ 3 ), where ɛ 1, ɛ 2 are in {1, 1}. We conclude, that ɛ u (mod λ 3 ) for ɛ = ±1. Hence, by Lemma 1.7 (iii), we see that u = ɛ. If u = 1, then we obtain x 3 + y 3 = z 3, so z 3 + ( y) 3 = x 3, and hence (z, y, x) T 3, which is empty. It follows that (x, y, z) / T 1, and hence T 1 is empty. If u = 1, then ( z, y, x) T 3, so similarly we see that T 1 is empty. Finally, if (x, y, z) T 2, then (y, x, z) T 1, which we have just seen is empty. Hence, T 2 is empty. Thus, T 1, T 2, and T 3 are empty, so it follows that S is empty. Department of Mathematics, University of Notre Dame, Notre Dame, IN 46556 E-mail address: sevens@nd.edu